Chapter 2.3 Nation-Building And Social
Integration Theory
�
{A}3.1 Nation-building{/A}
�
The term �nation-building� came into vogue among
historically oriented political scientists in the 1950s and 1960s. Its main
proponents included such leaders of the American academic community as Karl
Deutsch, Charles Tilly, and Reinhard Bendix. Nation-building theory was primarily used to describe the processes of national
integration and consolidation that ledleading up to the
establishment of the modern nation-state--as distinct from various form of
traditional states, such as feudal and dynastic states, church states, empires,
etc. �Nation-building� is an architectural metaphor which, strictly
speaking, implies the
existence of consciously acting agents such as architects, engineers,
carpenters, and the like. However, as used by political scientists, the term coversdescribed not only
conscious strategies initiated by state leaders but also unplanned
societal change.[1] In the apt phrase of �yvind �sterud, to political science the concept of
�nation-building� became for political �science in a sense became what
�industrialization� was to social economy: an indispensable tool
for detecting, describing
and analyzingthe detection, description and analysis of
the macrohistorical and sociological dynamics that have producedproducing the
modern state.[2]
�
The traditional,
pre-modern state was
made up of isolated communities with parochial cultures at the
�bottom� of society and a distant, and aloof, state structure at
�the top,� that was largely content with
collecting taxes and keeping order. Through nation-building these two spheres
were brought into more intimate contact with each other. The mMembers of the local
communities were drawn upwards into the larger society through education and
political participation. The state authorities, in turn,on the other hand,
expanded their demands on, and obligations towards,
the members of society by offering a wide array of services and integrative
social networks. The subjects of the monarch
were gradually and imperceptibly turned into citizens of the nation-state. Substate cultures and loyalties either
vanished or lost their political importance, being superseded by
loyalties toward the larger entity, the state.
�
In Stein
Rokkan�s model saw, nation-building was seen as
consisting of four analytically distinct aspects.[3] �In Western Europe these aspects had
usually followed each other in more or less the same order. Thus, they could be
regarded not only as aspects but also as phases
of nation-building.
�
The first phase
resulted in economic and cultural unification at elite level. The second phase
brought ever larger sectors of the masses into the system through conscription
into the army, enrollment into compulsory schools, etc. The
burgeoning mass media created channels for direct contact between the central
elites and periphery populations and generated widespread feelings of identity with the
political system at large.
�
In the third phase, the subject masses were
brought into active participation in the workings of the territorial political
system. Finally, in the last stage the administrative apparatus of the state
expanded. Public welfare Sservices of public
welfare were established and nation-wide policies for the
equalization of economic conditions were designed.
�
In the oldest
nation-states of Europe, along the Atlantic rim, the earliest stage of these
processes commenced in the Middle Aages and lasted until the French
Revolution. While it iswas
impossible to pin-point exactly when the entire nation-building process was
completed, it certainly went
onlasted
for several centuries. In the ideal variant, each consecutive phase set in only
afteras
the previous one had run its course. This ensuredsecured the lowest
possible level of social upheavals and disruptions, Rokkan believed.
�
***
�
In the mid-1970s,The discussions on nation-building took a new turn. in the mid-1970s.
In a seminal article pointedly titledcalled
�Nation-building or Nnation-destroying?�
Walker Connor launched a blistering attack on the school of thought associated
with Karl Deutsch and his students.[4] Connor noted that
the nation-building
literature was preoccupied with social cleavages of various kinds--between
burghers and peasants, nobles and commoners, elites and masses--but virtually or
totally ignored ethnic diversity. This Connorhe regarded as an inexcusable
sin of omission, since, according
to hisin Connor's computation, only 9
percent of the states of the world could be regarded as ethnically homogeneous.
�
Since
�nation-building� in the Deutschian tradition meant assimilation into
the larger society and the eradication of ethnic peculiarities, Connor
believed that in world history it had produced more nation-destroying than nation-building. However, the
efficiency of active engineering
in nation-building engineering, he heldbelieved, had
generally been greatly exaggerated. Very often it was counterproductive, regularly producing. It regularly
produced a backlash of ethnic revivalism. Complete
assimilation of ethnic minorities had largely failed all over the world, even
in thate
alleged stronghold of consummated nation-building, Western Europe,
Connor maintained.
�
Another reason
behind the fundamental flaws of nation-building theory Connor found in the
terminological confusion caused by the diverse usages of the word
�nation.� As heHe
pointed out, that
this term sometimes is used with reference to cultural groups and peoples, while at other times it
describes political entities (states), cf. expressions such as �United
Nations� and �international politics.� Even more
misleading, he felt, was the tendency to use the term �nation� to
describe the total population of a particular state without regard for its
ethnic composition.
�
While reserving
the term �nation� for ethnic groups only, Connor discarded all objective cultural markers as valid identity demarcations
for these units. Neither common language, common religion, nor any other shared
cultural reservoir within a group qualified as a genuine sign of nationhood.
Any such attempt to objectivize the nation was to mistake the cultural
manifestations of a nation for its essence. The true nature of the ethnos
was in all and every case the sense of common ancestry shared by its members,
Connor asserted. The nation is the ultimate extended family. To be sure,
hardly ever could a common origin of the members of the nation be proven. In
fact, very often it can be established that a nation stems from diverse
ethnic sources. The belief in athe common genetic origin can
therefore usually be shown to be pure myth. Nonetheless, adherence to this myth
has remained a sine
qua non for every nation, Connor maintained.[5]
�
Later
theoreticians developed Connor�s understanding in two different
directions. The �modernists�--such as Benedict Anderson, Tom Nairn, Ernest Gellner
and, Eric HobsbawmHobsbawn--, etcstrongly underlined the myth
aspect of the nation. In a celebrated book-title, Benedict Anderson coined the
expression �imagined communities� to describe modern nations. The
nation is a product of imagination in the sense that the members of the
community do not know each other personally and can only imagine themselves to
be in communion with each other. However, Anderson distanced himself from
Gellner and HobsbawmHobsbawn
who took the �imagination� metaphor one step further, interpreting and
interpreted it in the direction of �invention� and
�fabrication.� The nation should not be defined as �false
consciousness� Anderson insisted. Such Ddefinitions like that would imply that
there are such things as �true communities� which can be juxtaposed
to �artificial� nations. �In fact, all communities larger
than primordial villages of face-to-face contact (and perhaps even these)
are imagined'.�[6]
�
At the same time,
Anthony Smith, Rasma Karklins. and others developed Connor�s
themes further in another direction, stressing strongly emphasizing the ethnic aspect of the
nation. While agreeing with the modernists that �nations� as we
know them are recent phenomena, Smith insisted that they have a long
prehistory, evolving out of ethnic cores. Of the conglomerate of ethnic groups
existing in earlier ages, some developed into would-be nations aspiring for
nationhood and a state of their own, with a few eventually acquiring it. Why do The successes of some
groups succeed while others
fail? Often thisand the failures of others must often be
explained as a result of historical contingencies, a confluence of
felicitous circumstances,--but it may also be due to the but also of
active efforts of determined nationalists, the nation-builders.[7]
�
Smith and his
disciples retained but re-employed
the term �nation-building� introduced by the earlier, modernist
school of thought. In accordance with their �neo-primordialist�
understanding of all modern nations as products of age-old ethnic building
material they heavilystrongly
underlined the cultural, symbolic, (ethnic) and myth-making aspects of the nation-building:.
�
{EXT}Even for the most recently created states, ethnic homogeneity and cultural unity are paramount considerations. Even where their societies are genuinely �plural� and there is an ideological commitment to pluralism and cultural toleration, the elites of the new states find themselves compelled, by their own ideals and the logic of the ethnic situation, to forge new myths and symbols of their emergent nations and a new �political culture� of anti-colonialism and the post-colonial (African or Asian) state.[8] {/EXT)
�
�
{A}3.2 Social integration{/A}
�
.In the liberal tradition of the 19th century we may identify two somewhat divergent
views on national integration. may be
identified. OneA
dominant line of thought regarded the cultural and linguistic dissolution of
the minorities into �high cultures� as not only historically inevitable
but also as indisputably beneficial to the minorities themselves. This process
was often labeled �assimilation,� �acculturation� or
�amalgamation� rather than �integration,� but no clear
distinctions were made among these concepts. It goes without saying that an
individual fully assimilated into the national culture also would be
successfully integrated into the larger society.
�
A classic expression of the assimilationist view may be found in John Stuart Mill�s Considerations on Representative Government:
�
{EXT)Experience proves that it is possible for one nationality to merge and be absorbed in another: and when it was originally an inferior and more backward portion of the human race the absorption is greatly to its advantage. Nobody can suppose that it is not more beneficial to a Breton, or a Basque of French Navarre, to be brought into the current of the ideas and feelings of a highly civilized and cultivated people--to be a member of the French nationality, admitted on equal terms to all the privileges of French citizenship, sharing the advantages of French protection, and the dignity of French power--than to sulk on his own rocks...[9]{/EXT}
�
A somewhat different
view was taken by Lord Acton. He was more inclined to see cultural diversity as a blessing for
the members of society and a safeguard against tyranny: �The presence of
different nations under the same sovereignty� . . .� provides
against the servility which flourishes under the shadow of a single authority,
by balancing interests, multiplying associations, and giving the subject
the restraint and support of a combined opinion.�[10] Not unity and uniformity, but diversity and harmony ought to reign in society, Acton
maintained. However, by no means did he regard all cultures as equal or equally
worthy of preservation. On the contrary, one of the main reasons why people
from different cultures ought to be included in the same state was that �inferior
races� could therebyin that way
could be raised,
by learning from intellectually superior nationalities:.
�
{EXT}Exhausted and decaying nations are revived by the contact of a younger vitality. Nations in which the elements of organization and the capacity for government have been lost� . . .� are restored and educated anew under the discipline of a stronger and less corrupted race.[11] {/EXT}
�
In fact, Acton was
prepared to use such phrases as �the cauldron of the State� in
which a �fusion� takes place throughby which the vigor,
the knowledge, and the capacity of one portion of mankind may be communicated
to another. Thus, his arguments for a multicultural state are leading
us towards a surprising result: under the tutelage of a superior nationality, members of the less advanced cultures in the
state will shed many of their distinctive traits and learn true civilization.
Exactly how much will remain of their peculiar identities (to use a modern
word which Acton does not employ), remains unclear,[12] but his vision of social integration was not as far removed from
John Stuart Mill�s as many observers have been led to believe.
�
Most of what was
written on nation-building and integration in the 1960s and 1970s stood in the
combined tradition of Mill and Acton. To Karl Deutsch and his disciples,
nation-building and national integration were, so to speak, but two sides of the same
coin, indeed, simply two ways of describing the same process. A major object of
nation-building was to wield the disparate population elements
into a congruent whole, by forging new loyalties and identities at the national
(= state) level at the expense of localism and particularistic identification.
Deutsch specified four stages by which he expected this process to take place:. Open or latent
resistance to political amalgamation into a common national state; minimal
integration to the point of passive compliance with the orders of such an amalgamated
government; deeper political integration to the point of active support for
such a common state but with continuing ethnic or cultural group cohesion and
diversity, and finally, the coincidence of political amalgamation and
integration with the assimilation of all groups to a common language and
culture.[13]
�
The modernists saw successful assimilation as a prerequisite for upward social mobilization for members of minority cultures. Only those individuals who mastered the language and the cultural code of the dominant group could aspire for achievement. In most of his writings Deutsch also saw the creation of the homogeneous society, with equal opportunities for all groups, as fully attainable.[14]
�
Walker Connor took issue with the assimilation theory of the modernizationists on two accounts. He did not believe that the eradication of cultural differences in society was necessarily a good thing.[15] Also, he questioned the one-to-one relationship between modernization and cultural homogenization.
�
{EXT}The continuous spread of modern communication and transportation facilities, as well as statewide social institutions such as public school systems, can have a great influence upon programs of assimilation. But can the nature of that influence be predicted? It is a truism that centralized communications and increased contacts help to dissolve regional cultural distinctions within a state such as the United States. Yet, if one is dealing not with minor variations of the same culture, but with two distinct and self-differentiating cultures, are not increased contacts between the two apt to increase antagonism?[16] {/EXT}
�
In later articles
Connor dropped the question mark and more and more fiercely insisted that this
was indeed the case. Advances in communication and transportation tend to
increase the
cultural awareness amongof the minorities
by making their members more conscious of the distinctions that set their own community
apart from other groups. The individual comes to identify more and more ever-more closely
identifies
with his own in-group, contrasting and contrasts
himself to the immediate surroundings.[17]
�
This view was accepted and even somewhat sharpened by Arend Lijphart, another pioneer of the new trend in integration theory. Lijphart distinguished between essentially homogeneous societies, where increased contacts are likely to lead to an increase in mutual understanding and further homogenization, on the one hand, and �plural societies,� where close contacts are likely to produce strain and hostility, on the other. In societies of the latter type, segregation among the dominant cultural groups would be preferable to integration, he maintained. �Clear boundaries between the segments of a plural society have the advantage of limiting mutual contacts and consequently of limiting the chances of ever-present potential antagonisms to erupt into actual hostility.�[18]
�
The writings of
Lijphart and Connor, as expressed by Anthony Birch, produced �a minor
revolution� in thinking about the processes of national integration,. as Anthony Birch put it.[19] It would certainly be wrong to see this as a switch from the
assimilationist vision of Mill to the more pluralist vision of Acton:, their
�revolution� was far more radical than that. Whereas Acton remained
a firmstrong
believer in the blessings of cross-cultural intercourse, and for that very reason
extolled the multinational state as an unqualified good, Connor and especially
Lijphart on the contrary not only accepted but relished the abundance of plural
states. They were skepticalskeptical not only toof the possibility
but indeed also toof
the desirability of assimilation.
�
On the issue of
assimilation, Ernest Gellner took a stance in- between
the two positions sketched above. Himself a Central European thoroughly
integrated into British academeia, he shared the conviction of the
early liberals and modernizationists that full assimilation of cultural
minorities was highly desirable, but he was somewhat more pessimistic about its
feasibility. Gellner identified what he called �entropy
resistance� as a major obstacle to successful assimilation, and, by the
same token, to the social mobilization of minorities. By �entropy�
Gellner meant the inherent tendency of modern industrial society to erase social
and regional barriers, creating a homogeneous, equalized society. The
territorial and work units of industrial societies are basically ad hoc, he pointed out: �Membership is fluid, has a great turnover,
and does not generally engage or commit the loyalty and identity of members. In
brief, the old structures are dissipated and largely replaced by an internally
random and fluid totality, within which there is not much (certainly when
compared with the preceding agrarian society) by way of genuine substructures.�[20]
�
However, some
group attributes, Gellner maintained, have a marked tendency not to become, over time,
evenly dispersed throughout society over time. Very often these entropy- resistant, ineradicable
traits are of a physical/physiological nature, such as black skin (or, to stick
to Gellner�s more surrealistic variant: blue pigmentation). Whenever
a high number of persons with of blue (black) complexion are located near the
bottom of the social ladder, colorcolor may become an
easily detectable identity marker checking the upward social drift of all blue
people. A convenient tool for social stigmatization and oppression of the
have-nots has thus been
found.
�
So far, it would
seem that Gellner�s theory of entropy resistance would belong to the
research of racial discrimination rather than to the study of ethno-cultural
integration. However, Gellner goes on to claim that �some deeply
engrained religious�cultural habits possess a vigor and tenacity which
can virtually equal those which are rooted in our genetic constitution. �[A]n identification
with one of two rival local cultures [may be] so firm as to be comparable
to some physical characteristic.�[21] Thus, while Connor and those who agree with him see the impediments
to smooth cultural assimilation as stemming from the very logic of
modernization itself, Gellner located these hindrances in traits and
characteristics which
are,
usually, borne by only some
members in society. are bearers
of.
�
�
{A}3.3 IsThe applicability of
Nation-Building/Integration Theory Applicable To Non-Western Societies?{/A}
.
As pointed out, The
classical theory of nation-building was an endeavor to understand the evolution
of Western states. Inevitably, therefore, it reflected Western
realities. Nevertheless, its proponents maintained that the theory was
applicable also to the study of non-Western societies. This belief was based in
part on a linear perception of history which was not always made explicit: all
societies were, by
the inner logic of human development, bound to pass through the same stages. In
addition, most of the nation-building theorists
believed that Western society was really a better society to live in. If they were not compelled by
the forces of history to emulate the West, the leaders of non-Western states
ought to do so--for their own sake and the sake of their population.
�
In fact, contrast
with the outside world was from the very beginning part and parcel of the
endeavor. It was certainly not fortuitous that this theory developed in the
1960s. The increased interest in the genesis of states came as a response to
the flurry of new state-making in the wake of the decolonization
in Africa. Nation-building theorists wanted to underline that
�states� could mean very many different things in different settings,
and that one should
not too readily equate these new, hastily created political contraptions with
the sturdy, time-tested nation-states of old.[22] At the very most, these new members of the international community
should be viewed aswere
nation-states in the making only. A fair number of the contemporary
nation-building projects, it was assumed, would never succeed.[23] Such
unfortunatesThese states would either sink back
into non-existence,
or remain internationally recognized states but devoid of any national character.
�
Rokkan remarked that the one distinguishing factor that setting nation-building
in the new states off from the �old� processes was the time factor.
Developments which in Western Europe had lasted for centuries, now had to be telescoped
into decades. Under such circumstances the various phases could hardly be kept
apart, but would overlap or even run parallel. This, in his opinion, would
produce �fundamentally different conditions.� The risks of wrong
turns and discontinuities would multiply. Likewise,Also, the element
of conscious social engineering in the nation-building process would increase.
Nevertheless, Rokkan felt that the new states could learn from European
experiences,
�more from the smaller countries than from the large, more from the
multiculturally consociational polities than from the homogeneous dynastic
states, more from the European latecomers than from the old established
nations.�[24]
�
The assumptions
which informed the nation-building debate in the post-colonial era of the 1960s
and 1970s have a bearing also upon the debate on nation-building in the
post-Communist world of the 1990s. Once againAgain, we see that the
state authorities and scholars in today�sthe newly independent countries employing the categories and
terminology of Western political science to describe--and prescribe--social
processes in their own countries, while their Western colleagues hastenurry to remind them
that similarities in terminology easily may obscure significant differences in
substance.
�
�
{A}3.4 Nations and Nation-Building in
Eastern Europe{/A}
�
As pointed out in chapter 1, the key term �nation� may
have two very different meanings:, as a community of a state and as a
community of culture, � in short, the
civic nation vs. the ethnic nation. In the former case, the nation will be
coterminous with the population of a (nation)-state;, in the latter case, it may be both
larger and smaller than the population in the state in which it resides.
�
In Eastern Europe--east of the
Elbe--the ethnic understanding of the nation has deep roots, whereas while
the civic concept has tended
to havetraditionally had very few
adherents.[25] There are probably two important, interrelated reasons for
this. First, in the West the bourgeoisie was the main motor behind the
civic nation-state and civic national consciousness, while in Eastern Europe
the national bourgeoisie has traditionally been conspicuously absent.[26] Trade and commerce were regarded as not very prestigious
occupations, and
often relegatedleft
to outsiders. As a result, the thin stratum of bourgeoisie that could be
found,
was very often of foreign stock--diaspora groups of Jews, Armenians,
Germans and Greeks. Such groups were frequently vilified as un-national leeches
on the national body.
�
In addition, the
imperial, dynastic state held itsthe ground much longer in Eastern
Europe than along the Atlantic rim. Both the Habsburg and the Romanov empires collapsed only as a result of the cataclysm that was World War I. cataclysm. The
appellation and identity of these two states were in principle unrelated to the
nations which werewas politically
dominant, the Germans and the Russians. Both states represented cultural and
ethnic patchworks �,
in the Habsburg domains, the
Germans made up less than 25 percent of the total population in the 19th
century.[27] In the Russian census of 1897 146 nationalities were listed;, the largest of
them, the Russians, constitutedmade up
only 45 percent.[28] In the Habsburg as well as the Romanov empires, local privileges
and customary laws held sway in many regions to the
very end.
�
The cultural and
territorial heterogeneity of the East European empires was not a result of
their size only. It also reflected the fact that their rulers were far less
energetic and systematic nation-builders than were their Western
counterparts.[29] As long as internal peace was retained and taxes paid, they werewere basically relatively
uninterested in the inner life of the various linguistic and religious groups
of the state. Left to their own devices, these communities could over time develop
strong national identities based on their cultural particularities. As long as
the state was imperial,
the nation could remained
cultural and non-state.
�
In Russia, the
ethnic understanding of the nation was reinforced rather than weakened after
the Bolshevik take-over.[30] As early as in 1903, Lenin�s party declared the right of all
nations to self-determination, �nations� here being unequivocally
identified with the (major) ethnic groups of the empire. However, as soon ast the cCommunist power had been
consolidated, the promised right to secede from the state becamewas so heavily
circumscribed as to be
renderedcome totally unattainable. Instead,
national homelands in the form of Union republics and autonomous republics were
instituted as a kind of substitute nation-states. These territorial units were
given the name and, up to a point, the cultural imprint of the dominant ethnic
group, the so-called �titular nations.�
�
In tThe 1920s and early 1930s saw, a vigorous policy
of promoting (often this meant: creating) new elites among these groups was pursued.[31] This is Uusually referred to as the
policy of korenizatsiya or �nativization,,� but one leading Western expert on Soviet
nationality policies prefers to call it the Soviet policy of
�nation-building.�[32]
�
In most respects,
the USSR was a strictly unitary state in which the powers of the center were
formidable. ThroughoutDuring
most of Soviet history,
the federal element in the state structure was largely dismissed as a mere
sham. However, in the finalduring the
last years of the Brezhnev period, the ethnically based federation became imbuedwas filled with a
certain degree of real content. Although this trend fell short of a complete
return to the korenizatsiya period, federalism did becoame an important
fact of Soviet life.[33]
�
The Union
republics of the Soviet Union were strange half-way houses between civic and
ethnic units. In the two-layer Union legislature they were represented in the
Chamber of Nationalities. The Deputies to this chamber were
chosen not among the titular nationalities only, but among all residents of the
republic. In some cases only a minority of the deputies from a certain autonomous
formation actually belonged
to the titular group. As far as these deputies had any political clout at all,
they were expected to represent the interests of the territorial unit, not
of the titular ethnic group.
�
To the other
chamber of the Supreme Soviet, the Chamber of the Union, the delegates were
chosen according to the territorial principle, and ethnicity played no role.
The real organs of power--the Politburo, the Secretariat of the Central Committee, the KGB and the Armed Forces--were also formally ethnically neutral, but in
reality ethnic Russians (and to some extent other East Slavs) were clearly
overrepresented.[34]
�
Thus, not only the Union republics, but also the very Union itself was a curious hybrid of an ethnic and a civic state: on the one hand, it was a multinational state based on a non-ethnic ideology (Soviet Marxism), on the other--an ethnic empire based on the power dominance of the largest nation, the Russians. This duality gave rise to a perennial debate on the nature of Soviet nationality policy--�internationalism or Russification?�[35]
�
Russian culture,
and especially the Russian language, certainly enjoyed a privileged position
and was forced on the non-Russians as well. Nonetheless, it should be borne in mind that the autonomous
formations did in fact give the various titular groups some special rights
within their respective territories. Indeed, whatever privileges and protection
the non-Russians enjoyed in the Soviet Union, (primarily in the
fields of culture, education and language policy), they enjoyed only within �their� republics. Members of the nationality living in other
parts of the Union had no special rights, even if they should happen to dwelllive in a compact
ethnic community. Such diaspora groups were more exposed to assimilation than
the core group. The important lesson which drawn from this arrangement by
the Soviet nationalities elites drew from this arrangement was that
protection of minority rights �necessarily� takes the form of territorial
arrangements. Non-territorial schemes of minority protection was something they had no
experience with. The Austro-Marxist�idea of cultural
(non-territorial) autonomy had been rejected by the future People�s
Commissar of Nationalities, Joseph Stalin, as early as in 1913, and remained a dead issue.was never since returned to.[36]
�
At the same time,
Soviet authorities did nothing to create ethnically pure Union republics
in the demographic sense. The many ethnic groups had for centuries been living heavilystrongly
intermingled with each other, and considerable inter-republican migration in the Soviet period
further complicated the ethnic map.[37] This is the dual legacy which the new states of Eurasia have to
come to grips with today aswhen they today they embark upon their
various nation-building projects: on the one hand, an exclusionary nation concept
which equates the nation with the ethnic group. On the other hand, a medley of
disparate ethnic groups
living on the territory of the state.
�
�
{A}3.5 The applicability of Is nation-building/integration
theory applicable to
post-Communist realities?{/A}
�
.ThroughoutAll over
the former Soviet Union the new leaders have proclaimed their states as
national states or �nation-states.� As Rogers Brubaker has suggested, that
they might perhaps more appropriately be called �nationalizing
states.� They are ethnically heterogeneous, �yet conceived as
nation-states, whose dominant elites promote (to varying degrees) the language,
culture, demographic position, economic flourishing, or political hegemony of
the nominally state-bearing nation.�[38]
�
The distinction
between nation-states and �nationalizing states� is analytically
useful, but is one of stages and degrees rather than of qualitative
differences. As Anthony Smith has argued, even the oldest nation-states in
Western Europe, such as France, seem to have evolved out of ethnic cores.[39] Also, Moreover, the forging of
a national identity is, in
a sense, is
a never-ending process:
thus,. In�
this sense all �nation-states� are also
�nationalizing states.� In Ernest Renan�s celebrated
expression, the nation is constituted and reconstituted in �a daily
referendum.�[40] Like a house which has to be kept up and repaired continuously once the construction period is
over,after the completion of the construction period,
nation-building in �nationalizing states� gradually shades into
what we might call �nation-maintenance.�
�
Even so, nation-building in newly independent states does not necessarily have to repeat the experiences of Western Europe or end up with the same architectural solutions. While there is hardly any question of whether the leaders of the post-Soviet states will pursue a policy of nation-building (they have repeatedly said that they will), we will need to find out what kind of nation-building this is supposed to be.
�
Rogers Brubaker has suggested a tripartite typology of alternative
nation-building models in the nationalizing states in the new Europe:.
1. The model of the civic state, the state of and for its citizens, irrespective of ethnicity.
2. The model of the bi- or multinational state, as the state of and for two or more ethnocultural core nations.
3. The hybrid model of minority rights in which the state is understood as a national, but not a nationalizing state. Members of minority groups are guaranteed not only equal rights as citizens and thus protected, in principle, against differentialist nationalizing practices but also certain specific minority rights, notably in the domain of language and education and are thus protected, in principle, against assimilationist nationalizing practices.[41]
�
In the civic state,
ethnicity and ethnic nationality haves no place, while in the bi- or
multinational state, they
haveit
has a major public significance. In the former case, the
constituent units of the polity are individuals, in the latter--ethnonational
groups. The third model draws
onborrows
elements from both. of them.
�
Another typology,
overlapping with Brubaker�s, has been suggested by Alexander Motyl.[42] Although hisMotyl's
typology is particularly geared
towards the Ukrainian situation, in particular, but in principle it is
applicable to all post-Soviet states. Motyl contrasts two types of ethnic
nation-building--exclusive and inclusive--with a political/territorial model
which, for all
practical purposes,
is identical with Brubaker�s civic model. The exclusive variant, which is
based on the linguistic, religious and cultural traditions of the titular nation
only, has relatively few adherents in the Former Soviet Union, Motyl notes with relief. Its disruptive potential may therefore easily be
exaggerated. The real temptation for contemporary post-Soviet
nation-builders, he believes, is the inclusive model. This model is not
necessarily inconsistent with a state-based national idea, but it nevertheless
views the ethnically defined titular nation as the cornerstone of state-buildingstatebuilding.
WhatInstead,
Motyl strongly advocates isrecommends
the political, non-ethnic model of nation-building.
�
Jack Snyder has remarked that civic nationalism normally appears in well-institutionalized democracies.[43] Ethnic nationalism, in contrast, appears in an institutional vacuum. Therefore, it predominates when institutions collapse, when existing institutions are not fulfilling peoples basic needs, and when satisfactory alternative structures are not readily available. This, Snyder believes, is the main reason why ethnic nationalism has been so prominent after the collapse of the Soviet state.
�
Certainly, in the
new states of Eurasia strong, smoothly-functioningwell-working state
organs are a scarce commodity. The establishment of such institutions will
inevitably be a protracted process. Nevertheless, they are slowly coming into
existence. According toFollowing
Snyder, then, one would think that the time factor should would work in
favorfavor
of civic nationalism. Gradually, the new state leaders will feel that they have
the necessary tools and the political security they need to implement a
color-blind and culturally neutral variety of nation-building. Brubaker,
however, disagrees. He recognizes that since the civic model has a certain
international legitimacy, civic principles have been incorporated into
some constitutional texts and are being evoked in some public declarations:.
�
{EXT}But these civic principles remain external. It is hard to imagine a civic understanding coming to prevail given the pervasively institutionalized understanding of nationality as fundamentally ethnocultural rather than political, as sharply distinct from citizenship, and as grounding claims to �ownership� of polities--(which, after all, were expressly constructed of and for their eponymous ethnocultural nations).[44] {/EXT}
�
It is not difficult to find evidence in support of Brubaker�s conclusion. What follows below is a random selection of quotations from post-Soviet academics.
�
In April 1994, a KazakhKazak law professor
tried to define the difference between �national� (natsional�nyy�) sovereignty and �popular� (narodnyy) sovereignty. He concluded that �in character� KazakhstanKazakstan
is a national state of the KazakhKazak
nation, but �in content� it is a democratic, law-governed state.
These two aspects, in his view, do not contradict each other.
�
{EXT}To my mind, a national state stems from the fulfillment of a
nation�s right to self-determination. In our case, this means the KazakhKazak nation, as
the indigenous nation which has an historical and unalienable right to fulfill
its right to self-determination on its own territory.[45] {/EXT}
�
The ethnic understanding of the nation is here unmistakable.
�
In 1997 a Latvian
professor of sociology reminded his readers that a national state is not the
same as a monoethnic state,--that, in fact, an absolute monoethnic society
does not exist anywhere. Therefore, he believed, also Latvia can become a
national state. �The idea of the national state is that it ensures the
security of the ethnic nation in the long run,� he concluded.[46]
�
The ethnocentrism
of the statements quoted above are
perhaps not representative of the whole spectrum of the nation-building debate
in their respective countries. On the other hand,However, it should be pointed
out that �this kind of
thinking may be found also among post-Soviet scholars who represent liberal
traditions clearly oriented toward the West and Western values. The prominent
Estonian scholar and former Estonian minister of nationalities, Klara Hallik, asks: �Is it possible to combine the idea of a nation
state with the integration of the non-citizens and democratic perspectives of the
state?�[47] Also Hallik�s question is based on an ethnic
understanding of �the nation.� She explicitly states that
�restored national statehood must guarantee the ethnic security of
the Estonian nation.� 'The �Estonian nation� is here, is equated with
the ethnic Estonians.
�
In her question
Hallik links the concept of the nation-state directly to the issue of
integration, as did also the pioneers of classical nation-building theory.
However, the way she poses theis
question would probably made little sense to them. The early nation-building
theorists, as we have seen, defined
nation-building as the inclusion of parochial, culturally anomalous groups
into the greater polity. Reinhard Bendix, for one, saw the extension of citizenship to members of
ever-larger groups as the very hallmark of successful nation-building.[48] Clearly, the key concepts of the debate have undergone significant
transmutations since they were first formulated. These transmutations we must
keep in mind when we next turn to today�s nation-building strategies in the former
Soviet republicsKazakstan.
[1] Carl J. Friedrich, �Nation-Building?,�� in Karl Deutsch and William Foltz, eds.,� Nationbuilding (New York: Atherton, 1963): 28; Charles Tilly, ed., The formation of national states in Europe (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1975).
[2] �yvind �sterud, Utviklingsteori og historisk endring (Oslo: Gyldendal, 1978): 117ff.
[3] Stein� Rokkan, �Dimensions of state formation and nationbuilding. A possible paradigm for reasearch on variations within Europe,�� in Tilly, The formation of national states: 570ff.
[4] Walker Connor, Ethnonationalism. The Quest for Understanding (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994): 22-66. First published in 1972.
[5] Ibid. First published in 1978.
[6] Benedict Anderson, Imagined Communities (London: Verso, 1994): 6.
[7] Anthony D. Smith, �Nationalism and the Historians,� in Anthony D. Smith, ed.,� Ethnicity and Nationalis (Leiden: E.J.Brill, 1992): 74.
[8] Anthony D. Smith, The Ethnic Origins of Nations (Oxford: Blackwell, 1986): 147.
[9] John Stuart Mill, On Liberty and Considerations on Representative Government (Oxford: Blackwell, 1946): 294-95.
[10]� John Emerich Edward Acton, Essays in the Liberal Interpretation of History (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,1967): 149. Originally published in 1862.
[11] Ibid.: 150.
[12] On the one hand, he saw the multinational character� of Austria as one of the assets of this state. In the Habsburg domains no single nation was so predominant as to be able to overcome and absorb the others. One the other hand, Acton accepted the idea that, in the course of time, �a State may produce a nationality.� Acton, Essays: 152 and 156.�
[13] Karl Deutsch, �Nation-building and national development: Some issues for political research,� in Deutsch and Foltz, Nationbuilding: 7�8.
[14] Connor pointed out that there was some vacillations and inner inconsistencies in Deutsch's writings on the subject. Connor, Ethnonationalism: 30-35. Deutsch's basic optimism was at times interrupted by fits of pessimism. The upbeat mood prevailed, however, and resonated in a number of scholarly works on ethnic integration in the 1970s.
[15] He described� it as �succumbing to foreign cultural inroads.� Connor, Ethnonationalism: 139.
[16] Ibid.: 21. Reprint from 1966.
[17] Ibid: 37 (Reprint from 1972); Ibid: 171 (Reprint from 1979).
[18] Arend Lijphart, Democracy in Plural Societies (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1977): 88.
[19] Anthony H. Birch, Nationalism and National� Integration (London: Unwin Hyman, 1989): 70.
[20] Ernest Gellner, Nations and Nationalism (Oxford: Blackwell, 1990): 63.
[21] Ibid.: 71.
[22] Friedrich, �Nation-Building?�: 32.
[23] Joseph R.� Strayer, �The Historical Experience of Nationbuilding in Europe,� in Deutsch and Foltz,� Nationbuilding: 25.
[24] Rokkan, �Dimensions�: 600.
[25] Hans Kohn, The Idea of Nationalism (New York: Macmillan, 1946); Andr� Liebich, �Nations, states, minorities: why is Eastern Europe different?,�� Dissent,� Summer 1995.
[26] Peter F.� Sugar and Ivo Lederer, eds., Nationalism in Eastern Europe (Seattle: University of Washington Press, 1994); Richard Pipes, Russia under the old Regime (Harmondworth: Penguin, 1979): 191�221.
[27] Raymond Pearson, National minorities in Eastern Europe (London: Macmillan, 1983).
[28] Theodor Shanin, Russia as a �developing society� �(London: Macmillan, 1985): 58.
[29] Andreas Kappeler, Russland als Vielv�lkerreich (Munich: Beck, 1993).
[30] Yuriy Slezkine, �The USSR as a Communal Apartment, or How a Socialist State Promoted Ethnic Particularism,�� Slavic Review 53, 2, 1994, pp. 414-452; Ronald Grigor Suny, The revenge of the past.� Nationalism, Revolution and the collapse of the Soviet Union (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1993).
[31] H�l�ne Carr�re d�Encausse, The Great Challenge. Nationalities and the Bolshevik State, 1917-1930� (London: Holmes and Meier, 1992).
[32] Gerhard Simon, Nationalism and Policy
Towards the Nationalities in the Soviet Union (Boulder, CO: Westview, 1991). By this term Simon was referring , on the one hand, referred
to the purposeful policy of the party and the state to consolidate or create
nations, on the other, to the internal processes of change that convert an
ethnic community into a nation.
[33] Gregory Gleason, Federalism and
Nationalism. The Struggle for Republican Rights in the USSR (Boulder CO: Westview, 1990); Viktor
Zaslavsky, ��The
Soviet Union,��
in Karen Barkey and Mark von Hagen. eds, After Empire. Multiethnic societies
and nation-building. The Soviet Union and the Russian, Ottoman, and Habsburg
Empires (Boulder CO: Westview
press, 1997).
[34] H�l�ne Carr�re d�Encausse, Decline of an Empire. The Soviet Socialist Republics in Revolt (New York: Newsweek, 1979).
[35] Bohdan Nahaylo and Victor Swoboda, Soviet Disunion. A History of Nationalities Problems in the USSR (London: Hamish Hamilton, 1990).
[36] I.V.� Stalin, �Marksizm i natsional�nyy vopros,� in Sochineniya (Moscow:� Ogiz, 1946): 320-332. Reprint from 1913.
[37] Robert A. Lewis, Richard H. Rowland, and Ralph Clem, Nationality and Population Change in Russia and the USSR (New York: Praeger, 1976); Mikk Titma and Nancy B. Tuma, Migration in the Former Soviet Union, (Cologne: Bundesinstituts f�r ostwissenschaftliche und internationale Studien, 1992).
[38] Rogers Brubaker, Nationalism Reframed. Nationhood and the national question in the New Europe (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996): 57.�
[39] Anthony D. Smith, The Ethnic Origins of Nations (Oxford: Blackwell, 1986).
[40] Ernest Renan, Qu�est-ce qu�une nation? et autres essais politiques (Paris: Presses Pocket, 1992). Originally published in 1882.
[41] Brubaker, Nationalism Reframed: 104-105.
[42] Alexander J. Motyl, Dilemmas of Independence. Ukraine After Totalitarianism (New York: Council of Foreign Relations Press, 1993): 80.
[43] Jack Snyder, �Nationalism and the Crisis of the Post-Soviet State,�� Survival 35, 1, 1993: 12.
[44] Brubaker, Nationalism Reframed: 104-105.
[45] S. Sabikenov, �Natsional�nyy i narodnyy suverenitet. V chem ikh razlichie?,�� Mysl� (Almaty) 4, 1994: 9.
[46] Elmars� Vebers, Latvijas Valsts un etniskas minoritates (Riga: Latvijas Zinatnu akademijas, 1997): 158.
[47] Klara Hallik, �On the International Context of the interethnic relations in Estonia,�� paper presented at the conference �Democracy and Ethnopolitics,�� Riga, March 9-11, 1994: 9�10.
[48] Reinhard Bendix, Nationbuilding and Citizenship (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1977).