,
================ ;:=======::======== .::=========-=--=--=--=--=--=--=
NATION FORMATION
Politics and Culture •
A Theory, Culture & Society series
Politics and Culture analyses the complex relatjonships between civil soci
ety, identities and contemporary states. Individual books will draw on the
major theoretical paradigms in politics, international relations, history and
philosophy within which citizenship, rights and social justice can be under
stood. The series will focus attention on the implications of globalization,
the information revolution and postmodernism for the study of politics and
society. It will relate these advanced theoretical issues to conventional
approaches to welfare, participation and democracy.
SERIES EDITOR: Bryan S. Turner, Deakin University
EDITORIAL BOARD
J.M. Barbalet, Australian National University
Mike Featherstone, University of Teesside
Stephen Kalberg, Boston University
Carole Pateman, University of California, Los Angeles
Also in this series
Welfare and Citizenship
Beyond the Crisis of the Welfare State?
Ian Culpitt
Citizenship and Social Theory
edited by Bryan S. Turner
Citizenship and Social Rights
The Interdependence of Self and Society
Fred Twine
The Condition of Citizenship
edited by Bart von Steenbergen
NATION FORMATION
Towards a Theory of Abstract Community
Paul James
SAGE Publications
London • Thousand Oaks • New Delhi
Q Paul Jame, 1996
Fu-st published 1996
All rights re,cl'\ed No part of this publication ma) be
reproduced. stored in a retrieval system. transmitted or utilized
m an) form or b)' any means, electronic. mechanical,
photocopying, recording or otherwise. without permission m
wntmg from lhe Publishers.
SAGE Publications Ltd
6 Bonhill Street
London EC2A 4PU
SAGE Publications Inc
2455 Teller Road
Thousand Oaks, California 91320
SAGE Publications India Pvt Ltd
32, M-Block Market
Greater Kailash - I
New Delhi 110 048
British Library Cataloguing in Publication data
A catalogue record for this book is
available from the British Library
ISBN 0 7619 5072 9
ISBN 0 7619 5073 7 (pbk)
Library of Congress catalog card number 96---068420
Typeset by M Rules
Printed m Great Britain at the University Press, Cambridge
For comrades and friends associated with Arena,
particularly for Gerry and Geoff
Contents
Acknowledgements IX
Introduction XI
PART ONE: OLD AND NEW LINES OF UNDERSTANDING
The Nation as an Abstract Community
The 'Imagined Community' as an Abstract Community
Some Definitions: From Natio to Nation
2 National Formation in Theory 18
Integrative Levels
Integrative Levels as Levels of Abstraction
The Materiality of Abstraction
The Abstraction of Intellectual Practice
PART TWO: CLASSICAL THEORY
3 Marx and Engels: 'Seeing through the Veil'? 47
A Poverty of Theory?
Marx and Engels in the Age of Nationalism
All that is Solid Melts into Air
Continuity, Unity and the Abstract Avant-Garde
4 Durkheim and Weber: The Antinomies of Abstract Nationalism 83
The Imperative of National Integration
Different Approaches, Convergent Appreciations
Where Does the 'Nation' Reside in Durkheim's and Weber's
Theories of Social Forms?
Social Form in the 'Age of Subjectivist Culture'
PART THREE: CONTEMPORARY THEORY
5 Nation Formation and the Janus Faces of History:
A Critique of Marxism 103
New Nationalisms and the New Left
Tom Nairn: A Partial Break with Orthodoxy
The Original Formation of Nationality and Nation
From the Historic Nation to Nationalism as Culturally Invented?
VIII
Past and Present
An Interlude on Nairn's Concrete-Abstract Distinction
6 Nation Formation and the 'Rise of the Cultural':
A Critique of Liberal Sociology 123
Out of the Traditions of Weber and Durkheim
Ernest Gellner: A Partial Break with Orthodoxy
From 'Savage' to 'Cultivated' Cultures?
Structure, Culture and the New Subjectivity
Gesellschaft as Mass Society and Culturally Bounded
A Homogeni:::ed Cultural Space?
Uneven Development and the Cultural Boundary
The Rise of the Cultural?
7 Nation Formation and the Instituting State:
A Critique of Structuration 151
Giddens' Theory of Nation-State Formation
Europe as the Source and Origin?
Means of Violence and Mode of Production
The Material Abstraction of Social Relations
ff the Nation-State is a Management Structure, W hat is
the Nation?
Nationalism as Political Ideology and Personal Psychology
Subject and Object, Person and Society
Continuity-in-Discontinuity
8 Themes for .a Theory of the Nation 179
The Subject of Nationalism and the Object of Enquiry
Nation Formation as both Primordial and Modern?
Intellectual Practice and the Abstraction of Community
A Political Coda
Appendix 198
Bibliography 201
Index 225
Acknowledgements
The approach of Na/ion Formalion is profoundly influenced by the theoreti
cal arguments of Geoff Sharp. It is difficult to convey this debt through
academic conventions such as footnoting for it derives from over a decade of
ongoing discussion. On the national question more specifically I need to
mention the influence of Benedict Anderson's slim but important volume,
Imagined Communilies. It remains the most insightful book written in the
area. I have learned much about conceptual method and issues of historical
transformation in working my way through the writings of Karl Marx,
Anthony Giddens, Ernest Gellner and Tom Nairn, as well as Max Weber and
Emile Durkheim. At the same time, my ideas were formulated in the context
of a long-time association with a group of people perhaps best known
through reference to the Melbourne-based journal Arena, people for whom
practical and engaged politics is as important to their lives as intellectual
enquiry.
Given the scope of this study I have been extraordinarily fortunate to have
been criticized and helped by many people with specialized knowledges rang
ing across a diversity of areas. There are numerous people whom I need to
thank. They include those with whom I have discussed back and forth across
the national question; friends and colleagues who have read the manuscript in
whole or part and commented upon various drafts; people who have made
critical suggestions about the direction of its central themes; as well as those
who have contributed to its research and production. In particular I would
like to thank Steve Alomes, Ben Anderson, Tony Ayers, Verity Burgmann,
Peter Cotton, Phillip Darby, Gloria Davies, Lindsay Fitzclarence, Anthony
Giddens, Gerry Gill, John Hinkson, Rod Home, Kim Humphery, Rita
Hutchison, Graeme James, Jean James, Henry Krips, Bruno Letour, Vicki
Lukins, Stuart Macintyre, Jim MacLaughlin, Julie McLeod, Marion Merkel,
Michael Muetzelfeldt, Eleni Naoumidis, Ephraim Nimni, Alison
Ravenscroft, Edna Ravenscroft, Harry Redner, Alan Roberts, Gary Shapcott,
Geoff Sharp, Charles Tilly, Stephanie Trigg, Bryan Turner, Helen Watson,
Doug White and others.
I need to thank the editors of various journals for their support in criticiz
ing and publishing research in progress and earlier versions of sections of this
book: Arena, Philosophy of the Social Sciences, Canadian Re1·iell' of Sil/dies in
Nationalism, Arena Journal and the Melbourne Journal of Polilics. I want
also to thank colleagues and students, past and present. in the Politics
Department at Monash University, in particular Freya Carkcek. Hugh Erny,
X Nation Formation
Michael Janover, Peter Lawler (now at Manchester), Andrew Linklater (now
at Keele), Darren Lynch, Paul Muldoon, Harry Redner and Chris Ziguras. At
Sage Publications. Robert Rojek has been the most efficient and enthusiastic
editor one might hope to have. He was a pleasure to work with, as was
Pascale Carrington. the book's p!'oduction editor.
Amongst all these critics, there are five persons that have to be singled out
for special appreciation and thanks. Geoff Sharp was extraordinarily gener
ous with his time, offering support, responding at length to draft chapters,
and opening up lines of approach which fungamentally shaped my thinking;
Rita Hutchison worked painstakingly through successive drafts never demur
ring at yet another set of changes to read; Ben Anderson commented
extensively on an early manuscript of Nation Formation making numerous
helpful suggestions; discussions with Gerry Gill served to crystallize some
intuitions on method and theory; and Alison Ravenscroft helped me in
numerous ways with her careful reading and insightful comments.
Introduction
In the late twentieth century, nationality is lived as a series ofremarkable con
tradictions. We are living through a time when the nation-state continues to
be one ofthe central constituents ofinternational relations, yet its slow death
is constantly proclaimed. The call ofnationalism resounds stronger than ever
as people grapple with social change and the fragmentation ofsocial identity.
It is a time when the processes of globalism have brought to bear new
emphases on the local, a time when the fragility of identity has highlighted
our relationship to place and people. Certainly there are cosmopolites who
regard themselves as floating free ofnational attachments, but for most ofus
the nation-state continues to frame our lives. And it does so at different and
contradictory levels.
The nation is at once assumed to be a rich and inalienable relationship of
specifiable compatriots; at the same time it connects anonymous strangers
most of whom will probably never even pass each other in the street. It is lived
as a 'concrete' relationship which each individual takes to his or her grave, and
yet it is abstracted across time and space in ways that leave us culturally obliv
ious to the particular deaths of any other than those persons who are our
immediate associates or who in some way have publicly walked the national
stage. National community is subjectively experienced as a 'primordial' rela
tion which, except for a few late arrivals who have to be naturalized, is said to
be traceable deep into the past as a complex though specific genealogy. Yet the
bounding ofsuch ties by the nation-state is objectively quite modern: most of
us in the contemporary nation-state must now self-consciously rediscover our
own personal genealogies - our roots back into the dead generations.
Such contradictions, themselves historically specific, form the background
to my attempt to characterize the nation as a changing but distinctive kind of
abstract community. 1 Since this entails something of a new departure, or at
I. The argument draws heavily upon a perspective developed by Geoff Sharp and others called,
for want of a less elaborate name, the 'constitutive abstraction argument'. Specific concepts writ
ten within this approach are footnoted where appropriate. The argument has been developing in
the pages of the journal Arena. Its fullest early expression can be found in Geoff Sharp,
'Constitutive A bstraction and Social Practice', 1985. See also, for example, Gerry Gill. 'Post
Structuralism as Ideology', 1984; John Hinkson, 'Postmodern Economy: Value, Self-Formation
and Intellcctual Practice', 1993; and Geoff Sharp, 'Extended Forms of the Social', 1993. The jour
nal began in 1963 as a forum for the Australian Left. In 1993 two new publications emerged out
of the old: Arena Maga=ine and Arena Journal, the latter being an international journal of social
theory and ethically concerned discussion of contemporary social practice. Both publications are
produced colJectively as part of a broader co-operative project of research and cultural politics.
While the project is still developing, it is in a very real sense emerging as a school of social enquiry.
XII Nation Formation
least a new emphasis in method, the book begins by outlining a theoretical
approach for describing the changing dominant social forms of the national
community. It argues that the commonly acknowledged failure of commen
tators to theorize the nation adequately is partly due to an inattention to the
complications ensuing from the neeessarily abstracting nature of theorizing as
an intellectual technique. More broadly, it is due to an inattention to the
implications of contradictions arising out of the wider, material abstractions
of social relations. How can the nation be experienced as a concrete, gut-felt
relation to common souls and a shared landsc;_ape, and nevertheless be based
upon abstract connections to largely unknown strangers and unvisited places?
As part of the 'nation of strangers' we live its connectedness much more
through the abstracting mediations of mass communications and the com
modity market than we do at the level of the face-to-face, but we continue to
use the metaphors of the face-to-face to explain its cultural power.
If the central argument holds that it is important to consider the contra
dictory intersection of more abstract with more concrete forms of association
in grounding the emergence of the nation, then its corollary is that in either
failing to recognize this process or treating abstraction as only relevant to the
realm of ideas, social theorists have substantially limited the depth of their
theorizing. In other words, Nation Formation is an exploratory examination
of the socially grounding (ontological) conditions which make the changing
forms of national association possible. Since the concept of ontology is liable
to misinterpretation it is worth defining even before the argument begins to be
elaborated. The concept is used in the sense of the modes of
being-in-the-world. the forms of culturally grounded conditions; historically
constituted in the structures (recurrent practices) of human inter-relations.
Thus the concept ·does not fall back upon a sense of the 'human essence'
except in so far as the changing nature of being human is always taken to be
historically constituted. The concept is not confined to the sphere of selfhood
except insofar as the self is always defined in interrelation with the 'other'.
The book asks why is it that this area of examination, the ontology of
national formation, has been a relatively untheorized shadow-area, traversed
in the main either by idealists who imbue it with the force of a primordial
essence or by historians who seem resigned to documenting its outer reaches.
Although the book discusses what are argued to be necessary grounding con
ditions and contextualizes these in history, it makes no sustained attempt to
answer such questions as why the nation came into existence, or what are the
sufficient conditions for such a development. Its aim is to explore in theory
and practice what Slavoj Zizek calls 'the ambiguous and contradictory nature'
of the nation:
On the one hand, 'nation' of course designates modern community delivered of the
traditional 'organic' ties, a community in which the pre-modern links tying down
the individual to a particular estate. family, religious group, and so on, are broken -
the traditional corporate community is replaced by the modern nation-state whose
constituents are 'citizens': people as abstract individuals, not as members of par
ticular estates, and so forth. On the other hand, 'nation' can never be reduced to a
Introduction XIII
network of purely symbolic ties: there is always a kind of 'surplus of the Real' that
sticks to it - to define itself, 'national identity' must appeal to the contingent
materiality of the 'common roots', of 'blood and soil', and so on. In short, 'nation'
designates at one and the same time the instance by means of reference to which tra
ditional 'organic' links are dissolved and the 'remainder of the pre-modern in
modernity': the form 'organic inveteracy' acquires within the modern, post-tradi
tional universe; the form organic substance acquires within the universe of the
substancelcss Cartesian subjectivity. The crucial point is again to conceive both
aspects in their interconnection: it is precisely the new 'suture' effected by the
Nation which renders possible the 'de-suturing', the disengagement from tradi
tional organic ties. 'Nation' is a pre-modern leftover which functions as an inner
condition of modernity itself, as an inherent impetus of its progress. 2
The most illuminating contributions to the national question are those
which have attempted to develop a social-theoretical framework sensitive to
historical research, philosophies of ideas and political interpretations, those
which show an active awareness of the relevance of work done in a breadth of
disciplines, from literary studies to anthropology and from linguistics to polit
ical geography. Along with Benedict Anderson's work which has this quality,
we must include the diverse contributions of Ernest Gellner and Anthony
Smith, Tom Nairn and Anthony Giddens. These, in turn, stand upon the
shoulders of traditions which go back to the classical social theorists: Emile
Durkheim, Max Weber and Karl Marx. Hence the book is structured around
an examination of 'stages' of theorizing of the nation. It is critical of all these
writers, though acutely aware that the critique itself is made possible only by
building upon and reworking the insights they opened to consideration. The
discussion tries to make sense of the strengths and limitations of the theorists
in terms of their own grounding assumptions, the historical period in which
they are writing, and the form of the nation which they face in that period. In
other words, it takes a social-theoretical approach to the history of method:
it is not intended to be a comprehensive survey of theory or history.
The book's structure is very simple. The first two chapters summarize my
methodological and definitional assumptions, attempting to evoke what is
meant by the notion of the abstract community. Following this introduction,
Part Two examines the classical theorists: Chapter 3 looks at Marx, the nine
teenth-century theorist who spent the most time on the national question;
Chapter 4 discusses the writings of Durkheim and Weber. By situating these
writers in historical context it attempts a reconnaissance of the question,
'why, in the period of the late-nineteenth, early twentieth centuries, when
national formation was assuming an ontological predominance, were theo
retical responses to this consolidation so limited?'
In the second main section, Part Three, some contemporary theories of the
nation are critically assessed. Taking Tom Nairn (Chapter 5), Ernest Gcllner
(Chapter 6) and Anthony Giddens (Chapter 7) as key, representative figures
within variant debates and traditions, it asks to what extent have these recent
writers moved to strengthen and deepen our understanding of the national
2. Slavoj Zizek, For They Know Not What They Do. 1991. p. 20.
xiv Nact'ot/ Formation
formation. The structure of this section mirrors that of Part Two, beginning
with the contribution of a prominent marxist and going on to discuss the
work of a well-known writer coming out of the Weberian-Durkheimian tra
dition. It is suggested that while each of these theorists makes an important
contribution, each is fundamentaCTy limited by his largely one-dimensional
theory of social formations. This leads on to the chapter on Anthony
Giddens, a theorist who has attempted to synthesize both of these traditions
into a coherent alternative. However, it is argued that ultimately a similar
problem of developing theory on 'one plane' is-also found in Giddens' work. 3
As with Part Two on the classical theorists, Part Three considers some of the
historically conditioned assumptions which give rise to and frame contem
porary approaches to the national question. In contrast to the early chapters,
the stronger concern here is to assess the detail and structure of their theories,
to evaluate how comprehensive they are, how internally coherent, and how
they stand up against the wealth of material elucidated by recent empirical
and social research.
Throughout the book, the discussion attempts to draw out the implications
of the continuing theoretical weaknesses in our general understanding of the
nation, but rather than just being a general exposition of theory, this is
located first in extensive reference to salient historical periods through which
national formations emerged and changed; and secondly in discussion of
particular theories. In discussing historical change, Nation Formation con
centrates upon the structural subjectivities which ground national formation:
three categories of human existence and social relations -the body, space and
time -provide focusing sub-themes. They were chosen because of their obvi
ous bearing upon the national question . The body relates to the nationalist
emphasis upon organic metaphors such as the 'blood of the people'; space is
relevant to the emphasis on territoriality; and time is important to the cul
tural themes of historicity, tradition and primordial roots.
History is not treated as a continuous, evolving narrative. Nor is it possible
to confine the study, as in the conventional sense, to a neat, specifiable
time-frame, nor to a particular country or region. That would be to assume
the logic of an assumption that is being questioned, namely, the ideology
that particular nation-states have internally coherent histories able to be
traced on a single-level time-line, and that they are the culmination of pro
gressive development with an essentially continuous form of social relations.
Neither, as will soon become apparent, do I uncritically accept the revision
ist (often postmodernist) claims that there are no such things as social
boundaries, social systems (closed or open); no totalities and therefore no
'sub-systems', 'dimensions' or 'levels' of such a society. In the same vein, I
reject the bald version of the revisionist assertion that the nation is a recently
contrived, cultural invention.
A continuing concern of the book is to place theory in history. All the
3. The concept of theory on 'one plane' cannot be more than hinted at here but it is crucial to
later discussion. For a detailed definition see Sharp, 'Constitutive Abstraction', 1985.
Introduction xv
while, my overriding interest is to work through the possibilities of the argu
ment that the nation is a particular kind of abstract community, to probe its
relevance for a theory of national formations and national subjectivities, and
indirectly, implicitly, to canvass its implications for rethinking directions in
political practice. The nation and nation-state have become extraordinarily
important in framing the practices and subjectivities of contemporary social
life from the individual's sense of identity to the 'collective' activity of fight
ing wars. At the same time, the increasing permeability of nation-state
boundaries to waves of culture, capital and emigrants has provided the con
text for contradictory responses: on the one hand, new and more febrile
nationalisms such as in Bougainville and Bosnia, Russia and Rwanda; and on
the other hand, denials of the continuing significance of the national frame as
the nation itself comes to be reconstituted by the structures of postmodern
capitalism and the processes of globalization. As the national form undergoes
new changes it becomes all the more pressing that we critically examine old
and new lines of understanding.
PART ONE: OLD AND NEW LINES
OF UNDERSTANDING
1
The Nation as an Abstract Community
[The nation] is imagined as a community, because, regardless of the actual
inequality and exploitation that may prevail in each, the nation is always
conceived as a deep, horizontal comradeship. Ultimately it is this frater
nity that makes it possible, over the past two centuries, for so many
millions of people, not so much to kill, as willingly to die for such limited
imaginings.
These deaths bring us abruptly face to face with the central problem
posed by nationalism: what makes the shrunken imaginings of recent
history (scarcely more than two centuries) generate such colossal sacri
fices? I believe that the beginnings of an answer lie in the cultural roots of
nationalism.
Benedict Anderson, Imagined Communities, 1991
Understanding the nation-state has gained a renewed urgency as across the
world we watch grotesque and continuing wars, bloody conflicts fought either
in the name of national independence or of national integrity. Everywhere the
call of the nation continues to be invoked: in the old Yugoslavia with the hor
rors of ethnic cleansing; in post-communist Russia as Yeltsin's oppressive
stance on national integrity creates new counter-nationalisms across the
Caucasus; in Rwanda as an ethnic civil war creates the conditions for the
largest scale refugee movement in human history; and in Indonesia as mili
tary-cultural solutions are sought to the 'problems' of East Timor and lrian
Jaya. Enough has been written about the immediacy of the national conflict
to suggest however that it is sometimes important to step back from the fray
and to reflect comparatively, historically and theoretically. Despite all the
work we have done the nation remains 'the one most untheorized concept of
the modern world'. 1
This first chapter begins to establish the ground-work for making sense of
the argument that the nation is a particular kind of abstract community.
I. Partha Chatterjee, The Nation and its Fragments, 1993, p. xi.
2 Nari�,� Formarion
abstract 111 the dominant level of its integration, in the mode of its subjectiv
ities as well as in the symbolic representation of that relationship. It is an
abstract community but one which always, subjectively and ideologically,
reaches back to more concrete ways of living and representation. This makes
it the best and worst kind of human associations, beset by contradictions,
ope1� to self-conscious cultural management, yet embedded deeply within
our taken-for-granted histories. In working its way through this argument the
book tends to accent questions relating to the nation as a material form of
social relation. However, given the usual phitosophical and commonsense
meaning of abstraction as a process pertaining only to ideas, it is easier to
begin with a comparison which puts its emphasis on modes of representation.
This opening is no more than an overture. Instead of referring to one of the
many issues of the day - the hoisting of the tri-colour Russian flag over the
blackened and bombed-out city of Grozny, or the flying of the swastika in
street marches through Berlin - we begin with a different flag and with some
representations of identity which are often discussed in the literature and
somewhat less contested in practice.
It is fairly uncontroversial to suggest that French citizens have a more
abstract relation to each other as represented through the industrially manu
factured piece of calico they call the tricolore than the Aranda tribe of central
Australia have embodied in the particular animal or plant of their totemic
identity. 2 However, the basis for any proposed qualitative difference between
these two modes of representation cannot adequately be located in the ma
terial character of the objects themselves, piece of cloth or natural totem.
Neither can it be assumed that intensity of identification is necessarily rele
vant to such a comparison. Reverence for the tricolore or, to take an example
from a different national setting, the Warsaw cenotaph fragment, is undoubt
edly intense. The Warsaw stone was once part of the Polish Tomb of the
Unknown Warrior, almost totally destroyed by a Nazi bomb attack during
World War II, and now is concreted into the facing of the foundation of
Victory Square. Notwithstanding this rich overlay of reference, a condensa
tion of meaning which redoubled over the course of recent history and
intensified its subjective hold, the fragment signifies a more abstract (though
not necessarily more complex) relation to others as strangers-yet-compatriots
than the skull of a dead reiative holds for a Trobriand Islander.
2. Reading through The Elemenrary Forms of Religious Life, (1912) 1976, pp. 219-239, exam
ples can be found where Durkheim treats the totem and the flag as homologous signs standing
in for a social reality - 'the totem', he says, 'is the flag of the clan' (p. 220). However, given the
overall thrust of his theory of social forms he would have to agree that there is something differ
ent about them. I will argue that there are substantial differences between the social forms which
give meaning to such 'signs', but approaches which posit ideal-type distinctions such as that
between the 'traditional' and the 'modern' give us very limited insight into these differences.
Equally, positing a theory of forms does not entail homogenizing all the different ways of living
that are possible within the broad, common structures and ontologies of such forms. For exam
ple, that the Pintupi people put a greater emphasis upon identity as bound up in the 'concrete'
place to which they 'belong' than they do upon identity as bound in living totems, confirms
rather than qualifies the present thesis (Fred Myers, Pinlupi Country. Pi111upi Self, 1986).
The Nation as an Abstract Community 3
The source of the difference is fundamentally to be found in the social
relational setting. A tribal, reciprocal-exchange society provides a qualitative
contrast with a Western nation-state: the problem is to find a way of describ
ing the difference without implying a dichotomous Great Divide. The
cenotaph is set in a focal urban location, existing as a symbolic evocation of
long-since-forgotten compatriots who died in the course of Polish history. It
is thus symbolically stretched across extended reaches of time and space.
Whereas the deceased Trobriander's skull is, over a ritually significant num
ber of years, passed from hand to hand, known person to known person,
before being given over to his or her matrilineal relatives to take to a final
place of rest. This is to say that the skull is set within a more concrete relation
and the cenotaph a more abstract relation. However, rather than to set up a
dichotomy between the concrete and the abstract, it is to begin an argument
about different dominant, materially constituted levels of abstraction.
Perhaps the key point which brings home the more abstract quality of the
cenotaph is that by definition a cenotaph is always empty of human remains.
Its dominant meaning signifies the death of no one in particular. This would
not be possible in a tribal burial site. Like the national flag, the cenotaph is
constructed (often self-consciously) as signifying the abstract representatives
of the national community - national heroes in general rather than known
persons. The suggestion that the cenotaph is an abstract sign does not infer
that its meaning is merely an arbitrary or culturally empty construction. Nor
does it suggest that its abstraction denies the possibility of particularized
connections. A cenotaph is a place invested with a specific and macabre rich
ness, a place of national remembrance for a history of generations, who, as
the forward projection of linear time would have it, 'shall not have died in
vain'. Placed here are the generations 'who shall not grow old' . Thus a super
ordinate sense of place overlays, connects, and abstracts from particular
deaths; but it does so without precluding the possibility that an individual
mourner will give the empty tomb particular, direct, and more concrete sig
nificance. In other words, in attempting to understand the cenotaph we are
faced with an overlaying of levels of abstraction.
With this overlay of levels, such apparently direct symbols as the skull are
complicated. It is indicative that I can call it a symbol. By contrast, it can
never be an empty symbol for the traditional Trobriander. It first of all sig
nifies a particular relation and at its most abstract remains an embodied
symbol. In contemporary, Westernized society the skull continues to be a
highly condensed symbol of death: witness the mass-media depictions of the
fields of nationalist-inspired killing in Pol Pot's Kampuchea. Recently the
cover of Time magazine used a dirt-encrusted skull to illustrate the words:
'Unburied Sins: From Cambodia to Rwanda, the world struggles to avenge
the victims of atrocity and genocide'. 3 However, what are we to make of the
fact that the skull was reduced to a macabre illustration without reference
3. Time, 22 May 1995.
4 Nation Formation
point.4 The photo credit simply read: 'Photograph by Scott Peterson -
Gamma Liaison'. It seems that it is now more important to acknowledge the
photographer's corporate agency than to locate the place or even country in
which the person died. In the same vein, what are we to make of the laughter
that often ensues when contemporary Western theatre-goers first hear Hamlet
bitterly say: 'Alas, poor Yorick! - I knew him . . .'? (Hamlet, [c.1602] V.i) For
the contemporary sensibility, the attenuation of association from decaying
skull back to particular human being is in most circumstances incongruously
distant. This is not to presume that the mocfern person cannot make such a
connection, but it is to say that the connection is not brought to the fore by
our assumed habitus. The mixed humour and pathos in Fazil Iskander's poem
'Memory of a School Lesson' depends upon us knowing that the language of
the sacred is no longer sacrosanct:
Prince Svyatoslav drinks from a skull.
And, of course, in this he is at fault,
For the skull is a sacred vessel,
Which, luckily, is not drunk frorn. 5
Different forms ofrepresentation are integral with different forms of asso
ciation, and the history of these forms of human association can similarly be
theorized as a complex overlaying of levels of abstraction. The roots of the
modern nation, while being overlaid by more abstract levels of integration,
are continuous with 'prior' dominant forms of social integration. They range
from kinship ties predominant in reciprocal-exchange societies to institu
tionally mediated extensions of social connection, such as carried by the
monarchical state and the Church. Continuation ofthe forms which structure
more concretely cnnstituted societies (as well as the continuation of aspects of
their content) is not precluded by the setting which conditions the rise of the
national formation. 6 However, as is exemplified by comparing different 'ways
of seeing' burial sites and human skulls, more embodied forms of integration
tend either to be reframed in terms of the new dominant level, such as has
happened to monarchy, or marginalized in pockets of'backwoods arcadia' as
happened to many peasant groupings.7 An example of the reconstitutive
process is the way the language ofkinship and blood-ties, abstracted to name
the relation to 'Our Father who art in heaven' (Matthew, 6: 9), was later used
4. See Philippe Aries, The Hour of Our Death, 1981, pp. 328-332, on the early modern roots
of the rendering of the skull as 'abstract symbol'.
5. In Daniel Weissbort, ed., Post-War Russian Poetry, 1974.
6. Gerd Baumann's work on the Miri (National Integration and local Integrity, 1987) shows
how it is possible for tribal face-to-face communities to find ways of 'local redintegration' (his
term for a particular kind of re-integration) despite the penetration of the nation-state. For
some quite different examples see Jonathon Wylie, 'The Sense of Time, the Social Construction
of Reality, and the Foundations of Nationhood in Dominica and the Faroe Islands', 1982.
7. Eugen Weber's research (Peasants into Frenchmen, 1976) attests that under the overbracing
level in dominance that makes possible the national community, 'unclaimed' enclaves can exist
long after national boundaries are secured. People could, in particular until the late nineteenth
century, live for generations in the largely unreconstituted interstices of the emergent nation-state.
The Nation as an Abstract Community 5
to describe aspects of national solidarity: mother-tongue; patriot; fatherland;
in Japanese, family-state (kazoku kokka); or as the Italian term la madre
Patria would have it, the mother-Fatherland. All the while, however, kinship
is subordinated to, or at least overlaid by, the new forms of solidarity from
city-state and kingdom to nation. Etienne Balibar forcefully articulates the
difficulty of theorizing this when he says:
That is why the representation of nationalism as 'tribalism' - the sociologists' grand
alternative to representing it as a religion - is both mystificatory and revealing.
Mystificatory because it imagines nationalism as a regression to archaic forms of
community which are in reality incompatible with the nation-state (this can be
seen from the incompleteness of the formation of a nation whenever powerful lin
eal or tribal solidarities still exist). But it is also revealing of the substitution of one
imaginary of kinship for another, a substitution which the nation effects and which
underpins the transformation of the family itself. 8
In short, I want to argue that modern national association only becomes pos
sible within a social formation constituted in the dominance of a level of
integration (described in the next chapter as disembodied integration). This
involves an abstraction from people's more particularistic relations with others.
There is a long way to go to even establish the terms of this argument. But
having fired off a single flare, it is advisable to begin its elaboration from a less
direct point of entry. By the end of the next chapter it is intended that we will
arrive back at a clearer and more useful restatement of the opening assertion.
The 'imagined community' as an abstract community
The argument that the nation is an abstract community has considerable
descriptive resonance with Benedict Anderson's representation of the nation
as an imagined, political community - 'imagined as both inherently limited
and sovereign':
It is imagined [we might translate imagining as one among the many possible
processes of abstraction] because the members of even the smallest nation will
never know most of their fellow-members, meet them, or even hear them, yet in the
minds of each lives the image of their communion.9
While the argument that the nation is a particular kind of abstract commu
nity does not draw directly on Benedict Anderson's theoretical
underpinnings - in part because his theory and methodology are left
implicit - there is nevertheless much to be learnt from Anderson's historical
insights. His is a powerful and elegantly presented treatise. In summary, he
argues that the transition from religious communities and dynastic realms to
the new, imagined national communities entailed a fundamental (ontological)
change in the mode of apprehending and being in the world. It was made pos
sible by a 'half-fortuitous. but explosive interaction between a system of
8. Etienne Balibar and Immanuel Wallerstein, Race, Nation, Class, 1991, p. 102.
9. Anderson, Imagined Communities, 1991, p. 6 (cf. fn. 9 on the same page). Insertions into
quotations which are bound by square brackets are my additions to the original text.
6 Na1i9n Formation
production and productive relations (capitalism), a technology of communi
cations (print), and the fatality of human linguistic diversity'. 10 The core
insight that I want to draw upon is that for the nation to become a predomi
nant organizational and cultural form there had to occur changes in the
framing categories and practices of being.
Anderson uses the example of time. The medieval sacred community was
bound as a simultaneity-along-time. This connection was not lived as if it
were the reflexive result of human practice, but as a manifestation of some
thing else, something which has always been, something universal and
omnitemporal - God in 'Messianic time'. Past, present and future were held
together by the omnitemporal Reality of the Word. Even genealogies were
ultimately connected by the sacred as much as by blood. By contrast, the idea
of the nation posits a community of strangers moving simultaneously through
'homogenous, empty time', time which is measured by the calendar, 'empty'
time which people fill with their own history. The connection between past,
present and future can be provided by something as apparently banal as the
date which heads a newspaper.
Imagined Communities is developed with exciting perspicacity. However, by
so prominently centring the concept of imagination as the organizing princi
ple, Anderson limits the reach of his argument. This is not just a quibble over
word choice. The concept is both too central and not sufficiently developed.
The solution does not necessarily lie in elaborating this highly evocative term.
Anderson acknowledges that 'all communities larger than primordial vil
lages of face-to-face contact (and perhaps even these) are imagined'. In the
same way, I have already noted that both tribal and national communities are,
at different dominant levels, constituted abstractly. Anderson follows this up
by saying, quite r·ightly, that forms of communities can be distinguished by
the style of their imagining. Javanese villagers, he says, 'have always known
that they are connected to people they have never seen, but these ties were
once imagined particularistically - as indefinitely stretchable nets of kinship
and clientship'. 11 It is an important distinction to make, but it leaves the ful
crum of his analysis, the concept of imagination, doing almost no theoretical
work. The notion of particularity here marks the line of differentiation, but as
we have already seen in comparing a Trobriand burial and a Polish cenotaph,
such a conception very quickly becomes complicated. Something like a
metaphor of constitutive levels is, I will argue, helpful for teasing this out.
The subsidiary point is that even if imagination is conceived of as lived and
materially framed (Anderson analyses ways of thinking, not just the content
of ideas), the concept overly emphasizes the world as being made up of sys
tems of signification. Writers such as Cornelius Castoriadis and Claude
Lefort have already entered into the labyrinthine pursuit of a theory of the
social imaginary. However, an excursion into the category of the imaginary
I 0. Ibid., pp. 42-43. The body of Anderson's analysis focuses on the latter two dimensions of
the 'interaction'.
11. Ibid., p. 6.
The Nation as an Abstract Community 7
suggests that this is not particularly helpful in extending our understanding of
the imagined community substantially beyond what Anderson has already
achieved. Castoriadis writes: 'The imaginary of which I am speaking is not an
image of It is the unceasing and essentially undetermined (social-historical
and psychical) creation of figures/forms/images, on the basis of which alone
there can ever be a question of "something". What we call "reality" and
"rationality" are its works.' His entire book is consequently spent opening up
a space in materialist social theory for this category 'that constitutes history
as such', that, for example, allows 'us' to name ourselves as a particular asso
ciation.12 This present book, by contrast, is more concerned with the
conditions which frame different ontologies. It takes it as given that persons
can act creatively and imaginatively, but is concerned to emphasize the con
stitution of different forms of social practice. It thus rejects the notion that the
imaginary is undetermined.
By beginning from the concept of the imagined, Anderson inadvertently
makes the way of thinking, or the form of consciousness, primary in defining
the national formation. 13 His concept (as opposed to his analysis) of imagi
nation puts misleading emphasis on the mode of subjectivity. One of the
basic challenges still confronting theories of the nation is to bring together the
subjective with the objective, that is, to synthesize an understanding of
national consciousness, nationality and nationalism as entailing certain forms
of subjectivity, with an approach to the nation, the nation-state, and the
nationalist movement as objective forms of social relations. Nation Formation
attempts to build upon Benedict Anderson's historical insights by developing
an approach which cuts across familiar conceptions of the relation between
social conditions and social consciousness.
Any criticism of Imagined Communities is heavily qualified. It is not being
suggested that Anderson's theory is idealist. 14 His theory cannot be consid
ered to fall within the standard expression of the idealist/materialist
dichotomy still assumed by writers as sophisticated as Liah Greenfeld and
Michael Mann. 15 The substance of Imagined Communities brilliantly c!evelops
12. The concept is worked through in Castoriadis' The Imaginary Institution of Society. 1987
(quotes are from pp. 3, 161, 148) and is discussed by John Thompson ('Ideology and the Social
Imaginary'. I 982).
13. lt can quickly be acknowledged that the concept of"abstraction' has a similar problem m
commonsense language of being confined to the realm of ideas, but as I will discuss at various
points throughout, this usage can be dislodged. Marx's work on the commodity and labour
abstractions (see for example, Capital, vol. I, (I867) 1977, part I, ch. I) shows how abstraction
occurs in the practice of exchange relations. See also Sharp, "Constitutive Abstraction·, 1985:
Alfred Sohn-Rethel, /11tellectua/ and Manual wbour, 1978; and Jose Maria Ripalda, The Di1·ided
Nation, 1977. See also for example 1he section entitled 'The material abstraction of social rela
tions' in Chapter 7 below.
14. Cf. Jim Maclaughlin, 'Renections on Nations as "Imagined Communities'", 1988, and
Balibar and Wallerstein. Race, l\'ation, Class, 1991, p. 106 fn. 11.
15. When, for example, Liah Greenfeld attempts to "allow for the causal primacy of ideas.
without denying it to structures' (Nationalism, I9<J2, p. 21) she is still working within an old-st)le
dichotomous divide. Michael Mann's division of the bases of social power into four substantive
8 Narto11 Formation
the historically grounded position that the national formation can only be
theorized 'by aligning it not with self-consciously held political ideologies, but
with the large cultural systems that preceded it, out of which - as well as
against which - it came into being', 16 However, the centrality of the concept
imagined works against the theory being grounded in this way. W hen
Anderson comes to explain the spread of the national formation as being pos
sible because of its 'modular', capable-of-being-transplanted quality, we are
back to an emphasis on ideas, even though much of the substance of his
analysis implies the relationship between the-content of ideas, the form of
subjectivity and the changing social relations. In the language of the present
text, ideologies such as nationalism are, through their abstract form, available
to be elaborated beyond their original formative context. However (and this
is a fundamental qualification consistent with a reworked theory of historical
materialism), such ideologies can only take root in the consciousness and
practice of individuals or people(s), whose relationships to each other are
already in the process of being reconstituted at a more abstract level. If the
vanguard nationalists of Latin America were 'marginalized vernacular-based
coalitions of the educated' it was, as Anderson himself says, not just because
self-interest, or practical exigency, or even an understanding of
Enlightenment ideas moved them. 17 It was that the mode of their activities, as
for example state functionaries or provincial printers and publishers, was
part of the re-forming of their own subjectivities and of the larger social rela
tions. This helps to make sense of the issue that although the concepts
associated with nations and nationalism were European in derivation, nation
alism as a political movement was already taking hold in the New World well
before the peuple of the oft-proclaimed 'first nation-state' took to the streets
of Paris to stonn the Bastille (the symbolic beginning of the French
Revolution in 1789).
The idea of nationalism never in itself moved anyone. This is to say that
ideas only take hold in a constitutive medium in which they have meaning, not
that ideas cannot be profoundly influential. In the words of Miroslav Hroch:
The diffusion of national ideas could only occur in specific social settings. Nation
building was never a mere project of ambitious or narcissistic intellectuals ...
Intellectuals can invent national communities only if certain objective preconditions
for the formation of a nation already exist.18
In order to proceed to a clarification of the argument that the nation is an
abstract community, its central concepts still need to be laid out and defined,
as, first of all, does the concept of 'nation' and its cognates.
sources - ideological, economic, military and political - still carries the notion that because these
are analytically distinguishable categories they sit behind social life offering four 'distinct poten
tially powerful organizational means to humans pursuing their goals' (The Sources of Social
Power, vol. 2, 1993, p. 10). Ideas (ideologies) become things to take off the shelf, sometimes to
good effect, sometimes not.
16. Anderson, Imagined Communities, 1991, p. 12.
17. Ibid., ch. 4.
18. Hroch, 'From National Movement to Fully Formed Nation', 1993, p. 4.
The Nation as an Abstract Community 9
Some definitions: from natio to nation
Thus far, I have tried to use the term 'nation', and the cluster of associated
concepts - nation-state, national community, national consciousness, nation
ality and nationalism - with some care about their differentiation. However,
they are vague, elusive and historically changing concepts. We should be
aware of this and its implications for social theory, seeking workable clarity
rather than striving for an uncompromisingly precise lexicon.
Johan Huizinga suggests that the Latin terms patria and natio (plural,
nationes) should be taken as a way into this area for it was in Latin writings
that these concepts were formed. 19 It raises the interesting point that Latin,
the language of the cleric and intellectual (the truth language, in Benedict
Anderson's phrase, of European religion and scholarship) should be the
medium of conceptualizing what was to become the means of its own under
mining. This occurred particularly through the assertion in Latin of the
richness and relativity of the vernacular languages, and hence the marginal
izing of the old truth language. A related point, a continuing theme of this
book, is that it is intellectuals who, by virtue of the way their work lifts them
into an abstract relation to locale and time, become a central 'grouping'
relevant to the rise of the national formation. 20 It is important to note even at
this early stage that it was not just intellectuals and intellectual groupings who
were abstracted in relation to locale and time. The merchant, trader of com
modities and money-changer were all drawn into a wider ambit than the
local and the face-to-face. Their relation to customers and competitors
quickly lost the particularity of association concomitant with gift exchange
and even feudal bartering. A further, very interesting example is the case of
the professional soldier. The division of soldiers fighting for the same sover
eign into separate nationes parallels the case of university scholars. The
distinctiveness of the intellectuals derives from the way in which their work is
carried beyond them, not only by the abstraction of language but also on the
wings of abstract media such as writing - scripted, printed and most recently
digitalized. We will return to this theme towards the end of this chapter and
throughout the discussion, but for the moment there is only the need to intro
duce it empirically and in relation to the problems of definition.
19. Johan Huizinga, Mm and Ideas, 1959, p. 105.
20. As a working definition Ihe term 'intellectual' will be used to refer to those persons who
work critically with ideas, extending or assessing the given frame of knowledge. It includes those
persons who work in both the scientific and humanistic branches of the intelleclual culture. While
all intellecrnals are intellectually trained, whether 'self-laugh!' through the abstract medium of
olhers' writings or tutored in an instilutional selling, !hey are a distinct grouping from the
broader category of the 'intellectually trained' (a term taken from GeotTSharp and Doug While,
'Features of the Intellectually Trained', 1968). The !alter term, somewhat akin to Alvin
Gouldner's use of the term 'technical inlelligentsia', refers lo !hose intelleclual (as opposed lo
manual) workers who in Lewis Coser's Weberian phrase live otT rather than for ideas. See GeotT
Sharp, 'In1ellec1uals in Transilion', 1983; Ron Eyerman, Lennart G. Svensson and Thomas
Sederqvisl, eds, lnrellecruals. Universiries and r/re Srare in Wesrern Modern Socieri<•s, 1987: Alvin
f
Gouldner, The Furure of lnrellecruals and rhe Ris,• o rh,• New Class, 1979.
10 Nation
' Formation
It is indicative that the term natio was used in the Middle Ages particularly
(though not at all exclusively) to distinguish communities of foreigners at
the newly formed universities, in refectories of the great monasteries, and at
the reform councils of the Church. 21 The self was here defined through iden
tifying 'the other', and the modi! of identification was explicitly lifted into
abstracted modality: persons were identified as being part of an aggregate
which overlaid the older sense of identity conferred by kinship and place. This
new need for self-definition was invoked in communities which were both cos
mopolitan and face-to-face; communities which came into constant contact
with others. Identification occurred through various means of categorical
distinction including place of birth and way of speaking, but these distinc
tions took on a new generality. This helps to explain the paradox that it was
in settings where the working language was Latin, and where their pretensions
were universalistic, that scholars and clerics almost immediately turned back
to more particularistic distinctions, and separated into nationes. Around
1220, half a century after the establishing of the University of Paris, four divi
sions were declared between its scholars: F rance, indicating the native
speakers of the Romance languages; Picardie, referring to the peoples of the
Low Countries; Normandie, being those scholars from north-eastern Europe;
and Germanie, including people whom we now unself-consciously call
German and English. At the University of Bologna there were said to be
thirty-five nationes. They gradually combined into two aggregates,
Citramontanes and Ultramontanes (those from the near- and other-side-of
the-mountain). At Oxford, factions were so intense, with several fatal riots
arising out of conflicting observances of the festivals of patron saints, that in
1320 the University officially recognized the existence of two nationes: it was
decreed that the three guardians of the Rothbury Chest should always include
a Northerner and a Southerner. In 1334 the riots, 'dangers, perils, deaths,
murders, mayhems and robberies' led the northern masters to secede and set
up an alternative university at Stamford. 22
These few examples should suffice to illustrate some of the various appli
cations and stretchings of the term natio, the intersections with religious,
regional and language communities, the intensity with which people held to
such nationes - even at this early stage people were killed in the name of
these allegiances. It should also serve to illustrate the distinctiveness of the
term from the post-eighteenth-century usage of the words 'nation' and
'nation-state'. The Latin concept of natio had a shifting meaning, designating
various associations of people:
21. See amongst others Guido Zernatto, 'Nation: The History of a Word', 1944.
22. G.G. Coulton, 'Nationalism in the Middle Ages', 1935; Elie Kedourie, Nationalism, (1960)
1993, pp. 13-14; John Lawson and Harold Silver, A Social History of Education in England, 1973,
chs 2-3; Hans Kohn, The Idea of Nationalism, 1944, pp. 107-109; Emile Durkheim, The
Evolution of Educational Thought, (1904-5) 1977, pp. 97ff.; Max Weber, in From Max Weber
(essays from 1904 to 1920), 1968, p. 179; Philip Caraman, University of the Nations, 1981. The
quote comes from J.I. Catto, ed., The History of the University of Oxford, vol. I, 1984, p. 186. See
also pp. 64-67, 187, 396--399.
The Nation as an Abstract Community II
Closely linked with natus [birth] and natura [inborn characteristics], it vaguely indi
cated a larger context than gens or populus, but without there being any fixed
distinction between the three terms. The Vulgate [that is, the authorized Latin ver
sion of the biblical scriptures prepared mainly by Jerome near the end of thefourth
century) used genres, populus, nationes interchangeably for the nations [sic) of the
Old Testament, and that biblical usage determined the significance of natio for the
time being. It indicated a fairly indefinite interrelationship of tribe, tongue and
region, sometimes in a restricted sense, sometimes in a broader one. [In the Middle
Ages, the) Burgundians, the Bretons, the Bavarians, and the Swabians were called
nations, but so were the French, the English, and the Germans. Unlike patria, natio
did not have an administrative significance, and initially not a political one either.
But little by little the various relationships of dependence and community obtain
ing exerted an influence on the restriction and delimitation of the concept natio. 23
If Frederick Hertz and Bernard Guenee24 are right, we can be a little more
precise than the above passage from Huizinga suggests. Natio, which had a
similar root to 'native', was used before the Middle Ages for 'uncivilized'
peoples: nationes ferae (Sallust), natio servituti nata (Cicero), innumerabiles et
ferocissimae nationes (Hieronymus). Hence in the Vulgate, natio is used to
refer to the Gentiles, while the chosen people is the populus. However, natio
came later to refer to all aggregations, or classings, of people with a common
'ethnic' background, 25 including, as we have seen, those most prestigious and
'civilized' of associations, university corporations.
It is a strange twist; the common thread seems to have been that the term
marked an association between persons who found it important to distinguish
themselves from others, but for whom the distinguishing marks of old were
insufficient or no longer available in the same way. After the Middle Ages,
natio was initially used in Germany and France to designate the ruling classes,
in opposition to the Volk or peuple. Up until this period, the words communis
patria or regna, the latter primarily meaning 'kingdom' but used more broadly
as in civitates et regna, were the most commonly used means of denoting the
highest earthly association of allegiance. As will be discussed in the next chap
ter it was also during the post-medieval period that the concept of status (root
of the word 'state') changed from being embodied in the person of the prince
towards being the abstracted administrative apparatus of the body politic.
The concept of 'nation' took on a more abstract meaning and clearer
political ascriptions from the sixteenth century. 26 The use of the word to
mean the 'whole people of a country' was in evidence from the early seven
teenth century, though, as Raymond Williams suggests, 'realm', 'kingdom'
and 'country' continued to be more common until the late eighteenth
century. The English term 'nationalism' (similarly written in French as
23. Huizinga, Men and Ideas, 1959, pp. 106-107.
24. Frederick Hertz, Na1ionali1y in Hislory ond Polilics, 1944, pp. 5-7. Bernard Guenee.
Sia/es and Rulers in La/er Medieval Europe, 1988, Introduction, ch. 3, and Appendix.
25. 'Ethnicity' is placed in inverted commas here because as a twentieth-century term it is
anachronistic in this context. Ethnicity, I argue, involves an abstraction from the reciprocal ties
of kinship.
26. Philip White, 'What is a Nationality?', 1985.
12 Nation Formation
11ativnalis111e) is even more recent. Rarely found even in the early nineteenth
century, it referred to the doctrine that certain nations had been chosen by
God.27 The conjoining of 'nation' with 'state' - the latter term itself only
becoming common in the eighteenth century28 - seems, as does the use of the
term 'nationalism', to have been generalized as late as the mid-nineteenth
century.
It was during this period that the cluster of terms associated with the
notion of 'kingdom' were substantially supplanted by ·nation' and its cog
nates, referring to an overarching, continuous and abstract community of
loyalty. Running on into the nineteenth century, the concept of the 'nation'
continued to carry contradictory levels of meaning. It was at once an embod
ied community based upon ties of genealogy (that is, the racial, linguistic
nation) and a disembodied aggregation of 'free individuals' connected by a
culturally willed closing of territorial boundaries (the nation, in Renan's
words, formed by daily plebiscite). 29 This tension was for example evidenced
in a late nineteenth-century commentary on how Adam Smith used the term
'national': 'Edwin Cannan [writing in 1894] thought Adam Smith's "nation"
consisted only of the collection of individuals living on the territory of a state
and considered whether the fact that in a hundred years' time all these
people would be dead, made it impossible to speak of the "nation" as a
continuously existing entity.' 30 In the early twentieth century the force of
such philosophical conundrums seemed to be comfortably submerged by
employing a common caveat about how complex the term is: 'it defies easy
definition' , as they said. And apart from the hesitations of a few recalcitrants
it entered common-sense parlance with little debate. One writer remarks
that in 1918 with Wilson's Fourteen Points the quality of being a nation-state
was formal)y maae the basic criterion of state legitimacy and of inter
national relations. 31
At the very least, the historical shifts confront us with extensive problems
of establishing definitions. Anthony Giddens, a relatively careful glossarist,
defines the nation as a 'collectivity existing within a clearly demarcated terri
tory, which is subject to a unitary [and uniform] administration, reflexively
monitored both by the internal state apparatus and those of other states'. 32
The definition is not without (fatal) drawbacks which I will discuss in Chapter
27. Raymond Williams. Keywords, 1976, pp. 178-179; Anthony Smith, Theories of
Nationalism, 1983, p. 167.
28. Kenneth Dyson, The State Tradition in Western Europe, 1980, ch. I.
29. According to Martin Thom ('Tribes within '-lations·, 1990, p. 23), an inspection of Renan's
earlier writings shows that he was less committed to the voluntarism than his famous lecture,
'What is a Nation?' would suggest.
30. Eric Hobsbawm. .\'ations and Nationalism since 1780, 1990, pp. 26--27.
31. Cornelia Navari, 'The Origins of the Nation-State', 1981, p. 14. While overall I agree
with the suggestion, a glance at the Fourteen Points speech shows that Wilson never uses the
word 'nation-state': 'nation' assumes a coverall meaning. Hence, League of Nations and United
:,.;ations.
32. Anthony Giddens, The Nation-State and Violence, 1985, p. 116.
The Naiion as an Abs1rac1 Communily 13
7, but it has distinct advantages over the common definitions of the nation as
a politically sovereign people or as willed association. It does not have to deal
with the issue as to whether a people can be said to be sovereign under an
authoritarian or totalitarian state-apparatus. It is a structural definition
rather than depending upon an assessment of the strength of national senti
ment. Importantly, the definition goes on to recognize that the nation(-state)
comes to be sustained only within a complex of other nation(-state)s. And,
pregnantly, this world system is said to be formed at a particular conjuncture
in 'world time'. 33
Moreover, the definition emphasizes the relatively uniform administration
of state sovereignty over a specific area with a boundary rather than a fron
tier. Given that even a relative or proclaimed uniformity was not possible
under even the most centralized, absolutist state system such as that of Louis
XIV (I 638-1715) or Frederick William I ( 1688-1740), it adds to a definitional
distinction between the nation-state system and absolutism. The absolutist
state, prevailing in Europe during the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries
(with concurrent structural parallels in Japan), was a late-feudal social for
mation where political power was increasingly bureaucratized and
depersonalized even as sovereignty was invested in a single ruler. In Europe,
it coincided with the entrenchment, particularly for the aristocratic classes, of
the abstract concept and practice of 'absolute' private property. 34
Absolutist power did not fade off at its edges as it tended to do towards the
frontiers of the feudal regimes or the earlier empires. However, it was not until
after the height of absolutism that negotiated, abstract lines on maps were
considered to precisely mark states' sovereign boundaries. Maps provide us
with an extraordinary example of the process of abstraction of place. As
Giddens records, the first boundary drawn as a line of mutually agreed
demarcation between states occurred in the 1718 Flanders Treaty. 35 We should
keep in mind that along with many conventional geographers Giddens tends
to underestimate the concern for precise delimitation of boundaries which
existed prior to the nation-state. Nevertheless, his general distinction between
frontier and border is useful. John Armstrong gives an example from the
fourteenth century of a seventy-eight kilometre straight-line boundary cutting
through frozen lakes and open terrain, 36 but this nevertheless would seem to
be a case of a precise frontier rather than a boundary demarcation in the
sense Giddens uses. By way of definition, a frontier is a particular kind of
boundary which marks the end of territory before it transforms or shades off
into open space. It is unusual for frontiers to be precise lines of delimitation;
33. The concept of 'world time', taken from Wolfram Eberhard, suggests that superficially
similar processes may be quite differently constituted depending upon the period of world history
in which they are set. See Eberhard, Conquerors and Rulers, 1965, pp. 131T, and Anthony Giddens.
Poll'er. Property and State, 1981, pp. 167 168.
34. See Gianfranco Poggi, The De1•elop1111·111 of the Modem State, 1978. ch. 4; and Perr)
Anderson, Lineages of the Ahso/11tist Stat,·, 1974.
35. Giddens, Nation-S//lte and Vioh•nce, 1985. p. 90.
36. Natio11S he/ore Natio11ali.,111, 1982, p. 27.
14 Nation Formation
'
however, long before the development of states there were other kinds of
boundaries which were culturally maintained as delimiting social life and
social movement. (It is tempting here to extend the discussion into an elabo
ration on how absolutism and boundary demarcation were transformed in the
abstraction of the state, making f>ossible the modern conjunction of state
and nation. But it is better left until further down the track.)
Unfortunately, however, for all its strengths Anthony Giddens' definition
conflates nation and nation-state.37 It brackets off the complicating actuality
of early modem 'nations'. This can be partly.handled by distinguishing the
existence of 'nations before nation-states' by the use of the original Latin des
ignations natio, nationes, as intimated earlier - still, there is a further issue.
Giddens' suggestion that a nation 'only exists when a state has a unified
administrative reach over territory over which its sovereignty is claimed' ,38 is
narrowing and exclusive. In one sense it is useful and will be retained as a par
tial definition of the modern nation-state (albeit with the qualification that in
theory more than one nation can reside in the territory of an established
nation-state). However, the suggestion is too narrowing in that it implies
reducing the nation-state and the nation to one form of social practice - the
institutional - and to one level of social integration, a level which shall be
called 'the agency-extended'. 39
The language of 'levels of integration' used here will carry much more weight
later in the discussion, but for current purposes it is sufficient to illustrate the
nature of Giddens' delimitation with a few examples. For Giddens,
non-state-bounded 'national' associations are merely adherents to the ideology
of nationalism, not nations. But definitional neatness has its costs. Do territo
rially associated 'collectivities' magically become nations when a unified state
asserts claims of unified sovereignty? Alternatively, to the extent that a collec
tivity is a lived abstract community, formed beyond the level of the face-to-face,
is it not too restrictive to exclude all non-state-bound collectivities from the
appellation of 'nation'? What are we to make of the following examples?
Diaspora nations - that is, self-proclaimed but scattered nations, or
trans-state networks like the Jews prior to, and even after, the formation
of the State of Israel.40
Irredentist nations - where the nation is said to extend beyond the
boundaries of the existing state, such as in the case of the Somali where
at least a third of their population lives in neighbouring Ethiopia,
Kenya and Djibouti.41
37. On the other hand, Giddens is heedful to distinguish between nation-state and national
ism. At one point, for example, he says 'the advent of the nation-state stimulates divergent and
oppositional nationalisms' (Nation-State and Violence, 1985, p. 220).
38 Ibid., p. 119.
39. For an expansion of this criticism of Giddens see below, Chapter 7. The concept of 'the
agency-extended' is defined in Chapter 2.
40. Gabriel Sheffer, ed., Modern Diasporas in International Politics, 1986.
41. I.M. Lewis, ed., Nationalism and Self-Determination in the Horn of Africa, 1983.
The Nation as an Abstract Community 15
Sub-state nations - again self-proclaimed 'nations', including the
Quebecois and the Cree in Canada, the Tamils in Sri Lanka, the
Basques and Catalans in Spain and France, and the Irish, Scottish and
Welsh in Great Britain. 42
The fact that the examples above are ambiguous and that some may be
open to be challenged as examples of nations does not detract from my pur
pose of indicating the complexity of the question. Writers like Anthony
Smith, John Armstrong and Walker Connor4 3 have attempted to deal with
such issues by defining the nation as a self-differentiating or politically
self-conscious ethnic group. I would be happy enough to accept this nicely
unadorned rendering except for two main reservations. Firstly, these writers
allow, at least in their explicit pronouncements, the idealistic possibilities of
the definition to dominate its meaning. Connor goes furthest in this direction
when he says that the 'essence of the nation is a matter of attitude, the tangi
ble manifestations of cultural distinctiveness are significant only to the degree
that they contribute to the sense of uniqueness'. 44
The second main reservation is that defining the nation in terms of 'ethnic
ity' entails elaborating what is meant by this additional, similarly amorphous
and contradictorily abstract/concrete term. The three writers just mentioned
rightly want to reject the 'primordialist' assumption of a biological or histori
cally unchanging ethnicity, the projection of an essence which has an inherent
political destiny. On the other hand, they also want to qualify the quite sophis
ticated 'modernist' argument that, as Ernest Gellner puts it, 'Nationalism is not
the awakening of nations to self-consciousness: it invents nations where they do
not exist'.45 Benedict Anderson, whom we could also place in the modernist
camp, criticizes this comment ofGellner's for assimilating "'invention" to "fab
rication" and "falsity", rather than "imagining" and "creation'".46 There are
strong, historically based reasons for qualifying the point even further.
To this end, Smith introduces the French term ethnie, meaning ethnic com
munity existent prior to and during the present Age of Nations. For Smith,
ethnicity resides not in biology but in culturally transmitted, myth-symbol
complexes, particularly what is called - following Armstrong and d'Abadal i
de Vinyals47 - the mythomoteur. These are the 'constitutive myths of the
42. For example, on Quebec see Larry Shouldice, ed., Contemporary Quebec Criticism, 1979;
Dominique Clift, Quebec Nationalism in Crisis, 1982, and Michael lgnatieff, Blood and
Belonging, 1994, ch. 4.
43. Anthony D. Smith, The Ethnic Re,•ival, 1981, and his The Ethnic Origins of Nations, 1986;
John Armstrong, Nations before Nationalism, 1982; and Walker Connor, Etl111onationalism, 1994.
44. Connor, ibid., p. 43. For a critique of this problem in Smith's The Ethnic Re,•fral, 1981, see
Jim MacLaughlin's strong but sometimes overstated article, 'Nationalism as an Autonomous
Social Force: A Critique', 1987.
45. Ernest Gellner, Thought and Change, 1964. p. 168. See also his Nations and Nationalism,
1983, p. 55 for a similar argument.
46. Anderson, Imagined Communities, 1991, p. 6.
47. Smith, Ethnic Origins, 1986, draws on Vinyals' article via Armstrong, Nations b,fore
Nationalism, 1982, p. 9.
16 Nt;tion Formation
ethnic polity', the myths of common descent. However, the continuing prob
lem of over-emphasizing ideas is still evident. Myths are elevated to both the
motor of early history and its 'cognitive maps', rather than examined in the
context of the forms of social relations which sustain and are in part repro
duced by such 'histories' of a shared ancestry. 48 There seems little point in
introducing the exotic term ethnie into the present study when 'ethnic com
munity' can be divested of its primordialist and overly biological emphases.
The word 'community' is too rich a concept to ignore. It has a wonderful
complexity which draws into intersection the cultural-ideological sanctifying
of more direct relations of mutuality with the historical revolt against the
bounding implications that such mutuality entails.49 The term 'abstract com
munity' is an intentional oxymoron, much like the concept 'a nation of
strangers' , which extends upon this contradictory history of the concept and
practice of 'community'. 'Ethnic community' is not immune from the same
tensions of meaning. It will be used, overlapping natio and nation, to distin
guish those associations lived in terms of the cultural predominance of
kinship relations and common genealogy. The form taken by ethnic commu
nities has of course changed over history despite the continuing emphasis on
'common genealogy'. The notion of 'ethnicity' is a very modern expression
which came to be asserted self-consciously at the very time that 'ethnically'
connected groupings were fragmented within overbracing nation-states. I
suspect that as we approach the year 2000 we will see a further lexical
experiential shift. Just as in some quarters 'ethnicity' replaced 'race' as the
ideologically sound signifer of blood ties, in the Age of Self-Definition the
word 'people' will be increasingly used as a catch-all nomenclature, safe to use
by liberals and racists alike. 50
Though the contemporary national community continues to 'live off' an
ongoing yet subordinate sense of blood ties, and though ethnic communities
often aspire to have their own state, the difference between the national and
ethnic community can nevertheless be defined without too much ambiguity:
a person can be institutionally naturalized as a national, whereas one still has
to be born into ethnicity. Even if it is already an abstract relation, ethnicity
continues to be lived as inscribed culturally in one's body, whereas national
ity is culturally contradictory, deeply embedded but more and more open to
48.It is indicative of this tendency (though not of Smith's entire approach) that he says;
'Form is akin to sry/e, in that, though the symbolic contents and meanings of communal cre
ations may change over time, their characteristic mode of expression remains more or less
constant. Of course, over very long time spans, even forms may change (like artistic styles ...)'
(emphasis added, Smith, Ethnic Origins, 1986, p. 14).The distinction between form and content
is vitally important, but to equate form with style is unnecessarily reductive. It gives only the
sense of form as manifest shape or manner; no sense of form as structured and constitutive.
49. See Williams, Keywords, 1976, pp. 65-66; Eugene Kamenka, ed., Community as a Social
Ideal, 1982; and Robert Nisbet, The Quest for Community, 1953. For a recent survey of the
revival of writings on community, see Elizabeth Frazer and Nicola Lacey, The Politics of
Community, 1993.
50. For example see Felipe Fernandez-Armesto, ed., The Peoples of Europe, 1994.
The Nation as an Abstract Community 17
choice. In practice this contradiction between choice and embeddedness is the
source of two opposing political possibilities.On the one hand, we see glim
merings of a reflexive sense of embedded identity and place, a critical politics
that works towards a renewed sense of community without its old closures
and ethnocentrisms.st On the other hand, news bulletins are replete with the
negative outcomes of a renewed identity politics:
If the nation's past, contained in an image of racial and cultural difference, is rele
gated outside its democratic, collective history, then the signifying sign of race and
its iterative, interruptive temporalities of archaism and discrimination inform the
very moment of the enunciation of the contemporaneity: time and time again, the
sign of the complex, unassimilable phenomena and paraphernalia of racial mark
ing emerges with its banal evil ...Time and time again, the nation's pedagogical
claim to a naturalistic beginning with the unchosen things of territory, gender, and
parentage - amor patriae - turns into those anxious, ferocious moments of
metonymic displacement that marks the fetishes of national discrimination and
minoritization ...52
As well as indicating definitional problems, the foregoing discussion of 'long
durational' shifts has served to highlight several important methodological
issues. It will now be useful to spell these out more directly. The following
chapter is designed to set up the minimal, broad requirements for sustaining
the proposition that the nation is a particular k_ind of abstract community.
51. This is my political position: the present text however is not the place to defend such ·crit
ical communitarianism' against orthodox internationalists and civic (postmodern) globalists at
one end of the spectrum and conservatives and New Right radicals at the other end "ho want to
protect against cultural 'loss' by instituting sets of neo-medieval barriers to social interchange.
See, for example, the debates in Michael Keith and Steve Pile. eds, Place and the Politics of
Identity, 1993.
52. Homi Bhabha, 'Anxious Nations, Nervous States·. 1994. p. 208.
2
National Formation in Theory
The momentous nature of the ruptures whi<;h characterize politics today
is reflected in the inadequacy of our familiar interpretative frameworks.
Disorientation, along with a sense of foreboding and even helplessness,
has become widespread. Not only does this affect the relatively familiar
political discourses of social democracy and socialism, it strikes too at the
core of the more basic frameworks of liberalism and marxism. The
grounding categories of these different versions of political economy are
opened out to questioning as change charts a course into unfamiliar ter
ritory.
John Hinkson, 'Postmodern Economy', 1993
When we consider the familiar ideological descriptions of the national
past - the invention of tradition, or the instrumentality of national nos
talgia - we realize that they do little justice to this discursive movement of
the nation's time and being caught in the act of turning-returning, to the
restless hesitation that articulates the contemporaneity of the past: part
disavowal, part elliptical idealization, part fetishism, part splitting, part
antagonism, part ambivalence.
Homi Bhabha, 'Anxious Nations, Nervous States', 1994
Any discussion of the national question faces the dilemma that the contem
porary forms of the nation and nation-state are both objectively modern, and
yet at the same time they are rooted in long-run, cultural forms of associa
tion. Because a long history of controversy is evoked by even putting the
issue in this way let me hastily make some qualifications. It does not
entail accepting the nationalist claim for the deep antiquity and continuity
through-history of their own particular nation. It does not necessarily mean
assuming that national festivals or symbols recuperated from the past are
anything other than recuperations. Nor does recognition of the dilemma
involve accepting the primordialist assumption prominent in mainstream
theory until the 1960s, that is, that those long-run forms lay essentially
unchanged beneath the surface flux of history. But it does suggest the neces
sity of allowing for the theoretical space in which, firstly, an explanation of
the relationship between the modernity but deeply embedded nature of the
national formation might at least be attempted; in which, secondly, the evi
dence concerning pre-modern nationes can be incorporated; and thirdly that
allows us to understand the continuation even within some contemporary
postmodern settings of both modern nationalist ideologies and primordial
ist assumptions as carrying commonsensical force. At the very least, by
National Formation in Theory 19
developing a theory of changing social forms it is intended that we might cut
through the debate between the modernists, the primordialists and the peren
nialists, the latter arguing that, given the need to belong, nations are a
perennial feature of post-tribal history. 1
The dilemma that national formation is both historically deeply embedded
and yet distinctively modern is related to an issue of historical methodology,
called here the dialectic of continuity-in-discontinuity. This issue, frequently
raised during the following discussion, refers to the way in which history -
continuous, apparently evolving human history - can be theorized as a dis
continuity of forms of social formation. A number of definitions are crucial
to this point.
The term 'form' (or 'social form') is used very broadly. 'Form' describes
more than the manifest shape or manner: it designates the way in which
social relations are structured. It is a synchronic term which refers both to
modes of practice and to kinds of society (where even during the heyday of
the modern nation-state, 'society' could not necessarily be equated with
nation-state boundaries). The concept of 'social formation' is used more
diachronically to describe a society uniquely constituted at a particular his
torical conjuncture. As a way into understanding particular social formations
the present approach works across a number of different levels of analysis,
each more abstract than the last . These levels of theoretical abstraction are:
1 Empirical generalization
2 Analysis of modes of practice
3 Analysis of modes of integration
4 Categorical analysis2
1 Empirical generalization The first level is self-explanatory - any worth
while theory constantly engages in empirical generalization, drawing
first-order conclusions about the recurrence and patterning of social prac
tices, drawing out general descriptions from the details of history and place.
I. For an elaboration of these terms see Anthony D. Smith, The Ethnic Origins of Notions,
1986, pp. 7-13. The assumptions of these approaches are lo be avoided. Equally, I do not want
to be subsumed within the categories 'Traditionalist-Culturalist', 'Modernist' or 'Post-mod
ernist' as set up by Jonathan Friedman in 'Culture, Identity, and World Process', 1989. A helpful
treatment of some of these issues can be found in John Hutchinson, Modern Na1ionalisms, 1994.
2. See Appendix I. Also Geoff Sharp, 'Constitutive Abstraction and Social Practice', 1985.
The proposition that theories are couched at various levels of 1heoretica/ abstraction will be
important to the later discussion of the relation between levels of constitutil'e abstraction and the
history of approaches to theorizing the national question, but it is too distracting to consider
developing it in the body of the text at this stage. Though I disagree with the evolutionist direc
tion in which Jurgen Habermas takes the integrationist way of conceiving of society, the problems
with the 'mode of production' approach do, as he says, lead one to look 'in the direction of even
stronger generalization, namely, the search for highly abstract principles of social organization'
(see Jurgen Habermas, Communicalion and 1/,e E>·olution of Socie1y, 1979. p. 153). Anthony
Giddens hints at a comparable methodological distinction to the one suggested here when he
asks, 'what levels of abstraction can be distinguished in studying the structural properties of
social systems?' (see Anthony Giddens, The Cons1i1ution of Socie1y, 1984, p. 181, also pp.
180-193 passim).
20 Na,ion Formation
The damning charge that a theory is empiricist is brought to bear only when
it works exclusively at this level, when it argues that the gathering of social
facts is a value-free process, or when it treats empirical generalization as the
most sound analytic way of knowing.
2 Analysis of modes of practice At a second level of theoretical abstrac
tion, the method draws upon a modified version of the neo-marxist reading
of social formations. Rather than assuming the primacy of the mode of pro
duction (as in orthodox marxism), social formations are understood to be
constituted (historically overdetermined) by a complex of modes ofpractice -
modes of production, exchange, organization, communication and enquiry.
These patterns of practice are enacted within and across variously extended
social boundaries. Even when used in this way the concept of 'social forma
tion' is not limited to a society of a particular size. For example, when
specified, a social formation can be coextensive with a world system. This is
not to imply, as some world systems theorists tend to, that such a system can
be equated with a particular mode of exchange (in this case capitalist
exchange relations), nor that the loosely articulated trade transversals of the
sixteenth century made up such an integrated network as to warrant being
called a 'world system'. Along these lines, the concept of 'mode of produc
tion', always treated as an overlay of various modes of production, continues
to be basic to understanding any social formation, but it is not afforded for
mal determinant predominance in the first, last or in-between instance. 3 In
order to understand, for example, the transition from industrial capitalism to
information capitalism as the dominant formation of practice we have to
study each of the changing modes of practice and their uneven intersections.
The phrase 'forms of social formation' used earlier thus partly refers back
to the proposition that particular societies at particular historical conjunc
tures can be compared with regard to their dominant and subordinate forms
of production, exchange, organization, communication and enquiry.
3 Analysis of modes of integration At this level the approach examines
the intersecting practices of integration and differentiation, expressed here
as ranging from face-to-face integration to disembodied integration where
technologies and techniques of extension such as digitalized communica
tions and mass media broadcasting come to mediate and abstract from
relations of embodied 'presence'. How is this level more abstract than analy
sis of modes of practice? By comparison with concepts such as 'production'
3. Cf. Louis Althusser, 'Contradiction and Overdetermination' in For Marx, (1965) 1979; and
Nicos Poulantzas, Political Power and Social Classes, (1968) 1973, passim. Raymond Williams,
'Base and Superstructure in Marxist Cultural Theory' and 'Means of Communications as Means
of Production' in Problems in Materialism and Culture, 1980, provides a nice critique of such
approaches. Marx's emphasis on the abstract category of 'mode of production' was part of what
made classical historical materialism a kind of 'form analysis' . Introducing the notion of 'modes
of social integration' into the present work is not to take away from the insights of a 'mode of pro
duction' analysis. Neither is it intended to imply the acceptance of the usually conservative
implications of integration theory with its usage of 'the cultural' as a relatively untheorized con
sensual, static or essential category. It is to propose a more abstract form ofform analysis.
National Formation in Theory 21
and 'communication' which are recognized by people as things they do, the
concept of 'integration' is more removed. It too is analytically derived from
a matrix of lived social relations, but people do not self-consciously effect
integrative processes, that is, not until recently with the increasingly abstract
reflexivity about the means of social regulation and cultural management.
Even Machiavelli was not concerned about integrating 'the people'. This
immediately takes us into the issue of relationship between social theorizing
and social practice, the 'double hermeneutic' of theory as practice.
4 Categorical analysis This level of analysis directly explores the onto
logical categories that people leave in the realm of the commonsensical, the
unquestioned foundation of a social formation - categories of social being
such as time and space, identity and the body. These categories have been
lifted into theoretical vogue surprisingly recently.4 This is the realm that post
structuralists and cultural materialists have made their own, the former
sometimes forgetting that analysis at that level, if not tied back into more
concrete political-ethical considerations, is in danger of abstracted irrele
vance, utopianism without a subject, or empty spiritualism.
At this level, generalizations can be made about the dominant categorical
frame(s) of a social formation or its fields of practice and discourse. In fact it
is only at this level that it is possible to generalize beyond categories of being
and to talk about ontological formations, societies formed in the uneven
dominance of, for example, tribalism, traditionalism, modernism, or post
modernism.
The remaining pages of this chapter are used to develop these last two lev
els of analysis and to distinguish analytically different forms of human
association and subjectivity, in particular, different forms of national associ
ation. 5 Emphasis is placed upon these means of theoretical understanding
only because they are the least familiar.
Integrative levels
The argument - that a form of social formation such as the nation-state is
constituted in the changing intersection-in-dominance of levels of abstrac
tion - can be approached through a fairly straightforward and schematic
point of entry. It will entail radically departing from the more usual marx
ist designations of levels as comprising the economic base upon which are
built other structural levels, namely, the political-legal and the ideological
cultural. And it will have almost nothing in common with the structural-
4. For example, on time see Norbert Elias, Time: An Essar. 1992; Christopher Gosden, Social
Being and Time, 1994; Amo Borst, The Ordering of Time, 1993.
5. This is not on the surface a particularly novel suggestion. Peter Berger, for example, dis
tinguishes 'three types of patriotism': direct communal; extended face-to-face; and abstract
patriotism (see Facing up to Modernity, 1979, ch. 10). The basis of his approach is, however, quite
different from that proposed here.
22 Na1ion Formation
functionalist designation of the cultural, social and personality systems as
relatively autonomous levels of social action. 6
Levels of integration, understood as modes of structured practices of asso
ciation (and differentiation) between people, can be expressed in various
ways. Here they will be delineatee in terms of the modes of embodiment pur
suant to each level. As mentioned earlier, three categories of human
ontology - the body, space and time - provide sub-themes to carry the dis
cussion back and forth between an abstract schema of social forms and
examining lived social formations. This tex_t is thus intended as a dialogue
between history and theory, a relation which as Femand Braudel has put it is
too often conducted as 'a dialogue of the deaf ' . 7 I do not mean to privilege
the body, time and space, but they are certainly central to the national ques
tion. Regis Debray, for example, says that the assignation of origins in time
and the delimitation of space are the 'founding gesture[s] of any society'. 8 The
task in which Debray fails is to posit ontological levels without essentializing
the primary ('primordial') level and its grounding categories. Conversely, the
task in which the critics of such primordialism fail is to ground the national
ist ideologies of blood (body), tradition (time) and soil (space) in long-run
historical practices and forms.
The method of 'form analysis' is a heuristic way of engaging with a histor
ical issue which contemporary social theory continues to find mockingly
elusive. By eschewing a classical schema of ideal types it is hoped to avoid the
tendency of such approaches to drown living detail in dead stereotype
(Clifford Geertz's phrase). However, it still entails a continual stepping back
from the rich detail of history, and at times it requires apparently arcane
abstract excursions into issues of method.
Three level� of integration are analytically distinguished, each of which is
abstract in relation to 'prior' levels. It should be stressed, firstly, that no social
formation is constituted at one level of integration. Given the proposition that
all societies are formed in the uneven intersection of various overlaying levels
of integration, levels enacted across various reaches of time and space, the
argument is not open to the criticism that any approach which refers to what
Michael Mann calls 'levels of social formation' presupposes a view of society
as a single unitary whole, geometrically layered across the same overall space. 9
Secondly, it should be recognized that by putting the weight of emphasis on
levels of integration the present text is only taking a couple of steps into a
fuller theory of constitutive levels. For example, a fuller theory would have to
examine the modes of differentiation associated with different forms of inte
gration. Moreover, it would have to examine in much more detail the
relationship between modes of integration and modes of practice. Thirdly, it
should be said that I have chosen to distinguish three levels only for reasons
6. The metaphor of levels occurs constantly through Talcott Parsons, The Social System,
1951.
7. Cited in Peter Burke, Sociology and History, 1980, p. 14.
8. 'Marxism and the National Question', 1977, p. 27.
9. Cf. Michael Mann, The Sources of Social Power, vol. I, 1986, ch. I.
National Formation in Theory 23
of illustrating the methodology. To have distinguished two levels might have
given the misleading impression of the acceptance of a dichotomous view of
history, commonly expressed as the distinction between the traditional and
the modem.To have chosen to distinguish four, or some greater number of
levels, would have been more unwieldy. For present purposes then the three
levels are:
• the face-to-face
• the agency-extended
• the disembodied
Face-to-face integration
Through human history the face is the most condensed metaphor we have for
conveying the meanings of social relations. Pierre Bourdieu records that 'just
as the Kabyles condense their whole system of values into the word qabel, to
face, to face the east, the future, so the older peasants in Bearm would say
capbat (literally, head down) to mean not only "down, below" but also
"northwards", ...and that words like capbacha, "to bow the forehead", or
capbach were associated with the idea of shame, humiliation, dishonour or
affront'. 10 The apparently simple phrase 'face to face' has in this way a
remarkably complex cultural-historical depth. When Elizabeth Barrett
Browning (1806-61) writes 'Face to face, silent, drawing nigh and nigher'
(from 'Sonnets from the Portuguese', 1850) it carries a substantial cultural
baggage. Other bodily metaphors of interaction abound: 'They shall see eye
to eye' (Isaiah, 52:8); 'The silver link, the silken tie/ Which heart to heart and
mind to mind/ in body and in soul can bind' (Sir Walter Scott, 1771-1832,
from 'The Lay of the Last Minstrel', 1805). Together with newer colloqui
alisms like 'eyeball to eyeball', they are commonly used in the present even for
interactions beyond embodied contact, but none of them has assumed the
generality of meaning that 'face to face' has engendered.
The concept of 'face-to-face integration' draws upon this complexity to
refer to the level of integration at which the modalities of co-presence, the
modalities of being in the presence of the other, are central and predominant
in maintaining a continuing association of persons even in their physical
absence from one another. Understanding the face-to-face as a level of inte
gration entails putting emphasis upon the importance of the modalities of
co-presence rather than the fact of co-presence, the acts of interaction. This
is crucial to the present argument.It is not wrong to say that face-to-face inte
gration is substantiated in the immediacy of any instance of face-to-face
interaction, that is, even in co-presence 'fading away across time and space' in
the sense used by Anthony Giddens and Irving Goffman.11 However, such a
IO. Pierre Bourdieu, The logic of Practice, 1990, p. 19; see also Terry Landau, About Faces,
1989.
11. Giddens, The Constitution ofSociety, 1984, p. 36.
24 Na1ion Formation
statement puts a too heavy emphasis on the particularities of interaction and
downplays the social relational setting. Here we can make an analytic dis
tinction between interaction and integration. The distinction allows for the
recognition that interaction is never simply present to itself: it always occurs
in the context of structured integrative relations. 12
In a setting marked by the dominance of face-to-face integration, such as
a tribal or peasant society, the limitations and possibilities of fully embodied
interaction constitute the boundaries of social existence and thus of social
subjectivity. It conditions the way in which people live such apparently pre
given but already abstracted 'natural' categories as the body, space and time.
It binds the abstracting practices of myth-telling, long-distance gift exchange
and even cross-tribal partnership with unseen others, within the modalities of
co-presence. It binds them within the modalities of reciprocity, continuity
and concrete otherness. What is being described here then is an ontological
framing, not just circles and lines of spatial extension. In this context, inte
gration does not depend upon individuals constantly standing toe-to-toe,
nor after a particular interaction does it, in the modern sense, fade away. In
this sense the modalities of co-presence bind absence. For example, kinship
based on the existential significance of being born of a particular body into
lines of extended blood-relation is a key social form of face-to-face integra
tion. In social formations where kinship is fundamental to social integration,
a person is always bound by blood or affinity even after the dramatic sepa
ration brought by death.
It is only at the point at which a particular grounding practice can no longer
be taken for granted that we meet the recurring paradox that its centrality and
continuing importance is formally announced: the proverb 'blood is thicker
than water' cau only be traced back as far as the early seventeenth century. 13
Similarly, any theory of national association confronts the problem that the
common nationalistic catchcry, 'for blood and soil', only arises long after the
ontological setting of being bound by kinship and locale has been qualitatively
reconstituted. This issue leads into a further step in the present argument.
Instances of face-to-face interaction are constitutively different when set in the
context of different integrative levels. Neither the act of being in the presence
of others, nor the continuation of ties of blood, nor attachment to a particu
lar locale, necessarily suggest a setting in which the face-to-face is the
12. Despite some similarities this is not to say that I fully concur with the way in which
Jiirgen Habermas distinguishes between system integration and social integration (i.e. experien
tial integration in the lifeworld). See his Legitimation Crisis, 1976, ch. I. Anthony Giddens also
distinguishes social integration ('systemness in circumstances of co-presence') from societal or
system integration ('reciprocity between actors of collectives across extended time-space, outside
conditions of co-presence'). See, for example, Giddens, Constitution of Society, 1984, pp. 28,
64-73, 139-144, 282, 376-377. I will argue later (in Chapter 6) that its strengths can be incorpo
rated into a levels argument without taking on accompanying problems and limitations. See also
David Lockwood, 'Social Integration and System Integration', 1964; and Ian Craib, Modern
Social Theory, 1984, pp. 53fT. and 212fT.
13. See also below Chapter 7 on the first appearance of permanent family names.
National Formation in Theory 25
dominant integrative level. For example, the description that peak-hour sub
way commuters are squashed cheek by jowl into the Tokyo express by
professional passenger loaders says nothing about the relevant structure of
relations which holds together these strangers-cum-national compatriots.
Agency-extended integration
With agency-extended integration, social integration is abstracted beyond
being based predominantly on the directly embodied and/or particularized
mutuality of persons in social contact. At this level, institutions (agencies)
such as the church or state, guild or corporation, and structuring practices of
extension such as commodity exchange through merchants, traders, pedlars
and the like (agents and mediators), come to bind people across larger
expanses of space than is possible under face-to-face integration. More
importantly, as the processes of agency extension consolidate and overlay
ongoing relations of the face-to-face, different ontological formations become
possible. Nineteenth-century and early twentieth-century social theorists such
as Emile Durkheim, Ferdinand Tonnies, Henry Maine, Fustel de Coulanges
and C.H. Cooley, would seem to be drawing parallel lines of distinctions
when they divide societies constituted predominantly in the face-to-face from
those they respectively refer to as characterized by organic solidarity. the
affirmations of Gesellschaft, or the bonds of contractual or secular society. A
recent theorist like Anton Zijderveld in his description of the Abstract Society
would also seem to be making parallel suggestions about changing societal
forms. However, the levels argument, a form analysis rather than a specifica
tion of ideal types, will more obviously part company with such typologies as
this discussion proceeds.
The concept of 'agency', despite its breadth of allusion - as an instrumen
tality or institution, as the office of an agent, or as a state of exerting power
or being in action on behalf of another - needs to be conjoined with the con
cept of'mediation' to give a fuller sense of this level of integration. A further
analytic distinction could be made between agency-extended integration and
what might be called'object-mediated integration', drawing particular atten
tion to the forms of mediation reproduced in the practice of commodity
exchange. For reasons of methodological simplicity, early capitalist market
exchange will be subsumed within the schema of levels of integration as
already delineated. While pedlars, for example, do not usually act as agents in
the institutionalized sense used above, they do mediate relations of produc
tion in the breakdown of subsistence and feudal agriculture, and as Fernand
Braudel documents, they were most often the agents intermediating between
the stores of wholesale merchandisers (or even not-so-important shopkeep
ers) and the widening classes of consumers. 14
In a social formation where agency extension is in predominance as it
began to be in a quasi-regulated way in the polities of feudal Europe or late-
14. The Wheels of Commerce, 1985, pp. 75-80.
26 Nution Formation
imperial China, representatives or agents of the central institutions including
clerics, soldiers and tax collectors came to minister to geographically sepa
rated groups of people who, at the level of the face-to-face, continued to have
few points of connection with other groups. Networks of agency-extension
overlapped and were often in "tompetition. As part of this process, an
abstracted political concept of space was created. It was a concept of space
with antecedents in the Roman Empire and developed from the early Middle
Ages in Western Europe, a concept 'capable of distinguishing space [territory]
from the people who lived in it, people who, hitherto, had charged it with a
purely social identity'.15 The effects of the process varied across social settings.
In Europe and across the Byzantine Christian realm it overlay rather than
completely re-formed the more parochial sense of place, 16 while in the Middle
East, quasi-territorial, ethnic-genealogical identity continued to be derived
from the mythologies and practices of nomadism.
Going back further, the diverse formations we collate under the heading
'traditional empires', from the Assyrian to the Carolingian empires, from the
Han to the Mogul empires, all depended upon administrative and military
representation for the continuing domination of their extensions of terri
tory.17 Up until the Middle Ages the prince was most often there in person on
the battlefield or in the counting house; however, this does not mean that
face-to-face ties predominated in that setting. As in the example of feudal
Europe, the relationships of the princes and their agents were formed in the
uneasy intersection of relations of the face-to-face and of agency-extension.
The nature of this intersection shifted over time and from locale to locale. The
Roman military tradition, for example, emphasized the 'personal' relation
between the army and the ruler - ritual oath-taking sanctioned loyalty to the
emperor as a 'fellow-soldier' (commilito). However, it is obvious, firstly from
the importance placed on emoluments and regular wages and secondly from
15. Robert A. Dodgshon, The European Past, 1987, p. 139. lt should be qualified somewhat:
Dodgshon's phrase, 'a purely social identity', gives a sense of the changed meaning of space only
by virtue of the context in which the phrase is placed. The new meaning of space is equally
'social', but takes a different form. See also Robert Sack, Conceptions of Space in Social Thought,
1980, ch. 7; and Armstrong, Nations before Nationalism, 1982, ch. 2.
16. It is important to my argument to distinguish the concepts of 'space' and 'place'. Whereas
the concept of 'space' is open and empty - 'space' is derived from the Latin spatium, from spa
tiari, meaning 'to wander' - the concept of 'place' is more particular, more concrete in its
reference. The concepts overlap, but certainly from the nineteenth century they have tended to be
used quite differently. In Abraham Lincoln's Gettysburg Address (1863) the term 'place' is not
interchangeable: 'We have come to dedicate a portion of that field [of civil war], as a final rest
ing place for those who here gave their lives that the nation might live.'
17. Marxist theorists need to take seriously Michael Mann's argument that it was neither class
structure nor mode of production that made this territorial extension possible: 'I am not argu
ing that classes did not exist or that one cannot describe Roman or Chinese modes of production:
rather that such concepts cannot be used to give an explanation of why these societies were so
large in extent and had states of a particular "Imperial" form.' See his States, War and
Capitalism, 1988, p. 57. Even if Mann is right that the military structure had crucial repercussions
for the forces and relations of production, this is not to say that the relevance of the mode of pro
duction as making possible the exacting of surplus resources is to be down-played.
National Formation in Theory 27
the lack of evidence of a flow-on of loyalty to the res publica (the republic
itself), that this was an uneasy relation, now strong, now weak. 18
The power of the early empires over their dominions was effected by mili
tary coercion, and though it was often religiously sanctioned it was dependent
on the beginnings of an agency-regulated exaction of surplus production from
subservient, often ethnically differentiated, populations. (As will be discussed
in the next section it was also increasingly dependent upon the development of
disembodied administrative mechanisms such as basic systems of writing and
accounting, record keeping and organization of agency networks.) At the
same time, relations between the ruling factions still were based commonly
upon face-to-face modalities such as extended-kinship or reciprocal loyalties.
In other words, ruling power was still substantially founded upon patrimonial
or traditional authority as opposed to the more abstract, bureaucratic and rel
atively impersonal power of legal authority. 19 However, this too was changing.
Patrimony was itself part of the reconstitution of face-to-face relations across
all classes. With patrimony, reciprocity became a skewed and hierarchical rela
tionship of fragile, constantly negotiated alliances. In other words, the mode of
organization was being recast at a more abstract level of integration.
Concomitantly, through the Middle Ages in Europe and elsewhere, the recip
rocal ties carried by the subsistence-based barter economy and by vestiges of
gift exchange (Mauss) were gradually being subsumed under the over-bracing
reaches of trade and more abstract market exchange: that is, the mode of
exchange was being recast. As Norbert Elias suggests, the transformation
from a barter economy to a money economy connects with a multitude of
other processes in conditioning the form of integration. 20
The development of an intersection between face-to-face and agency
extended relations should not be seen as part of an uncontradictory, con
sensual, unidirectional or continuous evolutionary pathway. At the height of
the Carolingian Empire, Charlemagne (-814) 21 ruled through the appoint
ments of comites (locally based agents) and missi dominici (circulating agents)
and through reliance on bishoprics and abbeys. But as Gianfranco Poggi
describes them, 22 such offices were qualified and complemented by under
standing derived from Gefolgschaft: highly personal, face-to-face bonds of
followership between a warrior chief and his retinue of near-peers. In a twist
of influences, Gefolgschaft became institutionalized in the later feudal system
of rule (late eighth to early fourteenth centuries), in turn being qualified by
legal principles revived from an earlier polity, the Roman empire.
18. J.B. Campbell, The Emperor and the Roman Army, 1984.
19. For definitions of 'traditional' and 'legal authority' see Max Weber, The Theory of Social
and Economic Organization, (1910-20) 1945, pp. 329-336, 341-346.
20. Norbert Elias, State Formation and Cfrili:ation, ( 1939) 1982, ch. I.
21. Bernard Guenee, States and Rulers in Later Medieml Europe. 1988, pp. 61 ff. discusses the
competing claims of Capetian and Valois France and, later, of Habsburg Germany to
Charlemagne as 'national' precursor and legitimator of monarchical legitimacy. The history of
legitimation by ascension of blood-lines is certainly a discontinuous story.
22. Gianfranco Poggi, The De1·elopment of the Modern State, 1978, p. 20 and pp. 19-25.
28 Nation Formmion
As well as the problem of discontinuity in history, the issue of emergent
contradiction in historical practices is brought to the fore by the metaphor of
levels. (The term 'cultural contradiction' 23 or what I prefer to call 'ontologi
cal contradiction' will be used here to designate contradictions arising out of
the intersection of constitutive levels.) For example, contradictions between
the respective modalities characteristic of face-to-face and agency-extended
relations are shown up in the subjective identity of medieval office-bearers.
Considerable cultural confusion, generating philosophical and legal debate,
had to be resolved in trying to understand the-double ontology of the person
as-'office bearer' . Their identity was founded on the one hand upon the
limitations and possibilities of being embodied and private, and yet on the
other hand on being the bearer of a 'higher' identity through embodying an
official or sacred agency with transcendent meaning, abstract in relation to
the particularities of its incumbent. Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679) is one
example among many writers who found it necessary to distinguish between
the 'Natural! Person' and the 'Feigned or Artificial! person'. 24 Perhaps the
most graphic illustration, relevant to the sub-theme of modes of embodi
ment, is the feudal conception of the king's body.25
Kingship first evolved not as the individual exertion of power but as the
expressed authority of a kinship grouping within an extended face-to-face set
ting: 'king' and 'kindred' have the same etymology. 26 However, while, as we
have just discussed, genealogy and other face-to-face ties such as Gefolgschaft
remained important to the identity of the sovereign through the period of
Charlemagne, this came to be overlaid by a more abstract level of identity
conferral. The body of the monarch, singular, came to be seen as also the
embodiment of an ongoing administrative structure, as the incarnation of a
relation between the City of Man and the City of God, and, most pertinently
for the present discussion, it became the corpus repraesentatum of the rela
tively new territorial concept of the patria (the fatherland). The levels of
integration were, in effect, set against each other.
In the sixteenth century and after - but with a wealth of antecedents
including the corpus Christi conception of the early Church councils and the
entombing practices of ancient Egypt27 - the contradiction between the per
son and the office of the sovereign was resolved by convolutedly projecting a
23. Sharp, 'Constitutive Abstraction' , 1985, pp. 72ff.
24. Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, (1651) 1976, pp. I, 83-86. For a more general discussion of
the transformations of 'role' and 'character', and the distinguishing of 'the skin from the shirt'
(Pierre Charron's phrase), see Agnes Heller, Renaissance Man, 1967.
25. Ernst Kantorowicz, The King's Two Bodies, 1957; also Andrew Vincent, Theories of the
State, 1987, ch. 2; and Otto von Gierke, Political Theories of the Middle Ages, 1900.
26. Writers who argue this proposition include: Reinhard Bendix, Kings or People, 1978, ch.
2, particularly p. 25; and Friedrich Engels, The Origin of the Family, Private Property and the
State, (1884) 1985, p. 140 and chs iv-viii, passim.
27. Kantorowicz, King's Two Bodies, 1957, notes the occasionally observed Egyptian custom
'of entombing two statues of a dead officer: one, attired with a wig and loincloth, in his capac
ity of a royal officer; and the other one, bald and in a long garment, as the "man" that the dead
was' (pp. 497-98, also ch. 9).
National Formation in Theory 29
unity-in-the-distinction between the natural body and the body politic. 28 The
latter body was believed to be of a higher though now increasingly secularized
realm. Thus for legal purposes the abstract king, Henry VIII, was still alive,
though Henry Tudor was long dead. Jurists of the Tudor period in England,
simultaneously talking in the medium of the face-to-face and the agency
extended, expressed this unity/distinction as the doctrine of the King's Two
Bodies: 'His Body natural (ifit can be considered in itself) is a Body mortal ...
But his Body politic is a Body that cannot be seen or handled, consisting of
Policy and Government, and constituted for the Direction of the People' 29
(emphasis added).
The theme of monarchy will surface time and again. However, before
leaving this particular illustration I would like to reformulate earlier charac
terizations of natio and patria in terms of the levels argument. During the late
feudal period, patria, the root of the later term 'patriotism', referred at one
level to a person's birthplace or homeland. It paralleled the French pays or
German heirnat. But this meaning was held in place by a new, superordinate
form of association, the kingdom as comrnunis patria, overarchingly held
together through relations of agency-extension. Allegiance was owed to the
abstract person who embodied this territorially expressed extension of space,
not to the person conceived through the modalities of the face-to-face.Hence
the confused concept of the King's Two Bodies. Centuries later we still find
strong expressions of personally held authority - such as the everywhere
quoted statement apocryphally attributed to Louis XIV (1638-1715), 'L'Etat
c'est moi'. However, the abstraction of sovereignty, and the transition from a
bureaucracy of monarchical servants to servants of the state, 30 marked the
beginning of the end of patrimonially exercised power:
Power ceases to be conceived as a collection of discrete rights and prerogatives, as
it had been under the Stiindestaat, and becomes instead more unitary and abstract,
more potential, as it were. As such, it begins to detach itself conceptually from the
physical person of the ruler; we might put it another way and say that it subsumes
the ruler within itself. 31
The more abstract meaning of the patria was associated with an ethic
which exemplified the reconstitution of the ontological significance of the
face-to-face: pro patria rnori, or death for the glory of the fatherland. 32
Jurists drew on antecedents in Roman law to assert that a person acting in
the name of the patria could legitimately kill his (or her) pater. Some
28. Through this distinction the gender of the monarch could be overlooked. Although, in
France, the Leges lmperii contained the Salic Law forbidding female succession to the throne.
29. Kantorowicz, King's Two Bodies, 1957, p. 7.
30. These phrases allude to G.E. Aylmer's thesis of a transition from The Kin!('s Sm·ants: The
Civil Service of Charles I, 1625-1642, 1961 to The State's Serrants: The Civ,/ Sen·ice nf the
English Republic. 1649-1660, 1973.
31. Poggi, Modern State, l 978, p. 74. For a discussion of the political metaphors drawn upon
during the period of Louis XlV's reign see George Armstrong Kelly, 'Mortal Man. Immortal
Society?', 1986.
32. Ernst Kantorowicz, • Pro Patria Mori in Medieval Thought', 1951.
30 Natio11 Formation
Humanist intellectuals got carried away and took the ethic to grotesque
extremes:
Thou knowest not how sweet is the amor patriae: if such would be expedient for the
fatherland's protection or enlargem&nt, it would seem neither burdensome and dif
ficult nor a crime to thrust the axe into one's father's head, to crush one's brothers,
to deliver from the womb of one's wife the premature child with the sword. 33
If feudal patriotism drew upon and yet changed the meaning of the
face-to-face, the same could be said of allegi_ance to the natio. These alle
giances were formed in the context of face-to-face interaction, in such places
as universities, monasteries and military barracks. But they were felt by
people who had been lifted out of many of the constraints of face-to-face inte
gration. These were people who had, at one level of their being, ascended into
the disembodied realm of the written Word,34 or at least who had in practice
been 'liberated' from the parochial boundaries of village and kinship-related
life. There is no evidence, until we come to a much later period, of the villager
experiencing sentiments of incipient nationalism. And by then, the relation
ship of the village to the outside world had fundamentally changed. By then,
the outside world had irrupted to haunt the most parochial hamlet, pene
trating at a level which, paradoxically, its inhabitants most often came to
actively embrace, even as in many cases they strove against its particular
manifestations to maintain the face-to-face boundaries of old. As Jim
MacLaughlin reminds us, national formation may have been constitutive but
it certainly was not consensual.35
The development of the institutional continuity of the body politic and the
patria beyond the limitations of directly embodied interactions depended
upon - among ruany other conditions - the possibility of storing and trans
mitting information across time and space in a way that stretched the
capacities of personal or word-of-mouth memory. The full significance of
writing as a disembodied medium of extension is in this respect profound.36
Writing, literacy and, later, print as means (this marxist term is used inten
tionally) of information organization, storage and communication, beginning
33. Coluccio Salutati, cited in Kantorowicz, King's Two Bodies, 1957, p. 245. See also pp.
232-272. Salutati (1331-1406) was a fourteenth-century Florentine 'civic humanist'.
34. M.T. Clanchy, From Memory to Written Record: England /066-1307, 1979.
35. On the importance of recognizing the uneven constitution of national identity across
class and from urban to rural settings see Jim Maclaughlin, 'The Political Geography of
"Nation-Building" and Nationalism in Social Sciences', I 986; as well as Maclaughlin,
'Reflections on Nations as "Imagined Communities"', I 988.
36. Geoff Sharp, 'A Revolutionary Culture', 1968. This insight is only just beginning to be
structurally incorporated into theoretical and historical studies. See Gerry Gill, PhD thesis,
forthcoming; Jack Goody, The Domestication of the Savage Mind, Cambridge, 1977; Elizabeth
Eisenstein, The Printing Remlution in Early Modern Europe, 1983; as well as Benedict Anderson,
Imagined Communities, 1991 and Anthony Giddens, The Narion-State and Violence, 1985.
Though Max Weber is sometimes credited with the full force of recognizing the significance of
writing, it is actually only given sparse or passing attention in his work. See for example Weber,
The Theory of Social and Economic Organi�ation, (1910-1920) 1945, p. 332.
National Formation in Theory 31
with the earliest lists of pictograms in Mesopotamia, became basic to the sta
bilization of the varied forms of centrally administered, agency extension.
Moreover, as Jack Goody and others have convincingly argued, the develop
ment of writing and the acquisition of literary skills, as well as affecting the
nature of political systems, contributed to transforming the nature of human
cognitive processes.
Until relatively recently, this medium, which at least within the practices of
intellectually related groupings carried the possibility of more abstract,
decontextualized and disembodied extensions of social interaction/integra
tion than are engendered by face-to-face or agency-extended communication,
was limited in its constitutive generality. It was bound by the means of pro
duction of written texts (the industrial printing press began operating in the
fifteenth century); by the hand-to-hand delivery of written communication
(the telegraph was a product of the nineteenth century); by the separation
between vernacular and administrative or written languages, persisting in'
some cases into the twentieth century; by low levels of literacy; and so on.As
a methodological aside it should be noted here how the analysis, working
across levels of theoretical abstraction, ties together (a) empirical generaliza
tions, (b) form analyses of modes of production and communication etc., and
(c) form analyses of particular levels of integration, to show how they qual
ify each other.
The example of writing37 and the fundamental break that occurred with
printing technologies has been admitted into the discussion here because it
provides a bridge into talking about the 'third' level of social integration, the
disembodied. It is also integral to the phenomenon of the newspaper, raised
here to introduce the process which, in Benedict Anderson's words, 'quietly
and continuously .. . [helps to create] that remarkable confidence of com
munity in anonymity which is the hallmark of modem nations'.38
Disembodied integration
The phrase 'disembodied integration' is used to refer to a level at which
people are part of a network of connections where the full modalities of
face-to-face interaction and the continuing practices of intermediating agency
are not the salient features of the social relation. At this level the social rela
tion transcends time and space quite apart from any personal intermediation.
It is an analytically distinguishable level at which the constraints on commu
nication, exchange, organization and production entailed in the deceptively
complex fact that human beings have bodies, are qualitatively attenuated. As
has already been stressed in relation to the intersection of the face-to-face and
agency-extended, this is not to say that in a particular social formation
37. 'A'hile I think Paul Hirst and Penny Woolley underplay the dramatic innovation of writ
ing, certainly I agree that print was in a much more generalized way ·the enabling condition of
an entirely different level of culture' (to use their words). See their Social Relations and Human
A flributes, I 982, p. 33.
38. Anderson, Imagined Communities, 1991, p. 36.
32 Natiqn Formation
marked by the emergent dominance of processes of disembodied integration
the more concrete levels dissolve. Rather, historical hindsight suggests that
they tend, unevenly and beset by contradiction, to be reconstituted in terms
of the dominance of the more abstract level. 39 For example, as Goody says:
The written word does not replace speech, any more than speech replaces gesture.
But it adds an important dimension to much social action.This is especially true of
the politico-legal domain, for the growth of bureaucracy clearly depends to a con
siderable degree upon the ability to control 'secondary group' relationships by
means of written communications ... The relation with both ruler and ruled
becomes more impersonal, involving greater appeal to abstract 'rules' listed in writ
ten code and leading to a clear-cut separation between official duties and personal
concerns. I do not wish to suggest that such a separation is totally absent from non
! iterate societies ... But it is clear that the adoption of written modes of
communication was intrinsic to the development of more wide-ranging, more
depersonalized and more abstract systems of government; at the same time, the shift
from oral intercourse meant assigning less importance to face-to-face situations.40
The present approach provides a way of lending some precision to the recent
emerging dominance and generalization of a new form in the late twentieth
century, one which has commonly been characterized by the appellation, 'the
information society' . 41 The approach is also intended to broaden Benedict
Anderson's focus on print culture with a much wider emphasis on the mani
fold of processes which contribute to the abstraction of social being.
The means of disembodied extension are multifarious. Examples taken
just from the sphere of communication (though they cannot be divorced from
their uses in exchange, production and organization) range from the illumi
nated manuscript to the daily newspaper, from the telegraph wire to the
national and international 'telecom' system, the satellite-connected televi
sion grid, and 1he network which bleeps the passage of capital across the
globe to on-line personal computers.42 None of these media rely upon either
their one-to-one communicants or the individuals who make up their mass
audiences having a prior face-to-face relationship with each other. Even the
newspaper which is distributed by agents - newsagents - does not in principle
depend upon the people it addresses being interconnected by ongoing net
works of agency-extension, although in practice they are thoroughly
so-connected.
39. Cf. the interesting but confused argument by Eric Leed, "'Voice" and "Print": Master
Symbols in the History of Communication', 1980. He concludes that the present revolution in
communications provides the possibility for consolidating an enriched version of the 'old', the
'traditional' ..
40. Goody, Savage Mind, 1977, pp. 15-16. See also Jack Goody, The Logic of Writing and the
Organization of Society, 1986; and his The Interface BellVeen the Written and the Oral, 1987.
41. See Hinkson, 'Postmodern Economy', 1993 and his 'Post Lyotard: A Critique of the
Information Society', 1987; Jean Chesneaux, 'Information Society as Civic Mutation', 1987; and
Mark Poster, Foucault, Marxism and History, 1984; and his The Mode of Information, 1990.
42. Technological apparatuses are the easiest way of exemplifying the changed level of inte
gration, but this should not be taken to mean that they in themselves usher in a new age. For a
critique of such reductionist determinism see Raymond Williams, Television: Technology and
Cultural Form, 1974, ch. I.
National Formation in Theory 33
At the same time it is important to note that even the electronic media
depend, both for the meaning of their content and for the depth of their con
stitutive hold, upon the assumption of an ontological continuity from the
embodied to the disembodied. Examples can be taken from across the twen
tieth century. One inter-war British writer proclaimed: 'There is a grumble
and a cause of complaining if the crofter of the North of Scotland or the agri
cultural labourer in the West of England has been unable to hear the King
[now effectively (dis)embodied by a further level] speak on some great
national occasion' 43 (emphasis added). The Scottish crofter is no different
from any of his or her compatriots in being able to conceive of the reconsti
tuted relationship to a national monarchy in face-to-face terms. The Queen
Mother can by this process be said to be the most loved person in Britain, as
if the technologically mediated relationship via the press and broadcasting
networks affords a personal relationship to her.44
A person's relationship to their unseen, unheard, 'massified' national fel
lows is similarly abstract, yet conducted as if it could be consummated
concretely.45 Raymond Williams gives the phenomenal meaning of the masses
as people we don't know yet. By contrast, Paul Virilio misses out on the con
tradictory nature of this when he says, 'The masses are not a population, a
society, but a multitude of passers-by.' 46 Similarly Zygmunt Bauman misrep
resents the dialectic between living in a nation and confronting strangers
when he says that 'strangerhood is the waste of nation-state building. They
are waste, as they defy classification and explode the tidiness of the grid.' 47
National community, despite being formed within the modern concern for
distinguishing and classifying compatriots and foreigners, is replete with
strangers. One of the tasks of the state becomes to administer the difference
between strangers for inclusion and strangers for exclusion. Each of the
media contributes in specifiable ways to this sense of concrete consummation,
to the sense that strange compatriots, people on the street, are not merely
passers-by. A newspaper is consumed by readers who may at one level pre
suppose an abstract community of readership, a common community
simultaneously moving through calendrical time. All the while, in observing
replicas of their own paper being read by their 'subway, barbershop, or resi
dential neighbours, [people are] continually reassured that the imagined world
is visibly rooted in everyday life' . 48
43. John Reith, Broadcast over Britain, cited in David Cardiff and Paddy Scannell,
'Broadcasting and National Unity', 1987, p. 157. They go on to talk of the explicit concern 'in
the earliest years of broadcasting, to employ radio to forge a link between the dispersed and dis
parate listeners and the symbolic heartland of national life'.
44. See Tom Nairn, The Enchanted Glass, 1988.
45. Although it should be obvious by now, it is worth emphasizing that 'concreteness' and
'abstraction' are treated as descriptive terms, not as dichotomous polarities.
46. Paul Virilio, Speed and Politics, 1986, p. 3.
47. Zygmunt Bauman, Modernity and Ambivalence, 1991, p. 15.
48. Anderson, Imagined Communities, 1991, pp. 35-36. See also Colin Mercer, 'Regular
Imaginings: The Newspaper and the Nation', 1992.
34 Nation Formation
The intersection of the emergent level of disembodied extension with 'prior'
levels ('prior' is used here to emphasize a formal and ontological ordering, as
distinct from a chronological sequence) brings new ontological contradic
tions. In relation to the natiof\jll question, the media of disembodied
extension radically lift the surveillance, monitoring, administrative and cul
tural management possibilities of the modern nation-state.49 Out of the same
structural processes, though in contradiction with the consolidation of the old
national form, the mass media facilitate the over-reaching of national bound
aries by meta-national capital, commodifies, and cultural values and
practices. In old Czechoslovakia, for example, the ultra-Stalinist daily of the
Austrian Communist Party, Volkstimme, was, until recently, readily bought by
Czechs and Slovaks for its listing of Austrian television programmes. Long
before the dismantling of the Berlin Wall these programmes crossed the
national/political divide. In Belgium, the state controls a national television
monopoly, except, that is, for the satellite border-hopping of more than a
dozen competing foreign channels. In Australia and New Zealand, the
high-profile, nationalistic governments of Hawke to Keating and Lange to
Bolger have been in the forefront of renovating their national economies to
deregulate the flow of international capital across their borders. In short, the
very processes of integration which further the bases for the integrity of the
national boundary and for the power of the state (an institution of agency
extension), also carry the possibilities for its 'dissolution' from without.
The older form of the nation-state, held together in the intersection of
reconstituted face-to-face relations and the still politically ascendant institu
tions of agency-extension, is with current developments simultaneously prone
to be hollowed out from within. 50 The emergent dominance and generaliza
tion of disembodied relations provides the conditions for the re-formation of
what (somewhat ironically) can be called the classical nation-state. 51
Anthony Smith expresses the experiential dimension of this when he says,
'We are probably never so aware of phenomena and objects as when we are
about to gain or lose them'. He continues: 'In the mid-twentieth century, what
ever our attitudes to nationalism, there was a very widespread assumption in
the public mind, echoed in much of the scholarly community, that the nation
was something as 'natural' as the family, speech or the human body itself.'52
49. This is what Anthony Giddens is referring to when he argues that 'electronic communi
cation for the first time in history separates "immediate" communication from presence, thereby
initiating developments in modern culture that ... are basic to the emergence and consolidation
of the nation-state' (Nation-State and Violence, 1985 p. 14). See also Habermas, 'Legitimation
Problems in the Modern State', in Communication, 1979, ch. 5; and Christopher Dandeker,
Surveillance. Power and Modernity, 1994.
50. This apt phrase is taken from GeofT Sharp, 'Hollowed Out from Within', 1983.
51. 'Classical' is used here ironically because, as discussed in Chapter 3, even in the nineteenth
century when commonsense and theoretical views were beginning to take the national and
nation-state formation relatively for granted, the nation-state had not consolidated and was
already beset by the processes of dissolution.
52. Smith, Ethnic Origins, 1986, p. 7. See as an example Esme Wingfield-Stratford, The
Foundations of British Patriotism, 1940.
National Formation in Theory 35
By the late twentieth century, particularly in the West, the given-ness of the
national form has become less secure, though, again, this is contradictory. In the
capitalist Westernized states (and for different but related reasons in the Third
World states) the assertions of national sentiment are becoming more pro
nounced than has been generally the case in the post-war period. In other
words, the national formation is being strengthened at one level, while the prior
levels which gave historical national forms their hold arc being gradually and
unevenly attenuated. The classical modem nation is being reconstituted and in
some settings is giving way to what we might call the postmodern nation.53
That is, postmodern subjectivities and practices are coming to overlay and
reframe the (continuing) condition of modernity. This needs some elaboration.
A number of grand (though always contested) narratives were relevant to the
modern nation-state: the notions of boundedness and sovereignty; assump
tions about the virtues of both high-cultural homogeneity and genealogical
integrity; and claims to the civilizing value of assimilating 'backward' ways of
life; and pretensions to the progressive necessity of comprehensively regulating
the civic culture and national economy. Described in categorical terms, the
modem nation was imagined as being bound within particular conceptions of
time, space and embodiment. What then characterizes the postmodern nation?
If the modern nation-state was experienced as both publicly and intimately
structuring one's lifeworld, then the postmodern nation (even when it is not
named as such) is increasingly experienced as an unstructured, and at times even
optional, background choice: for example the distinctions between race, eth
nicity and nationality have become even further stretched with nationality
becoming less and less inscribed in one's body. Simultaneously, under conditions
of postmodemity the stale is most often viewed either as a baleful institution to
be minimized and deregulated or as a necessary, if intrusive, organ of public
administration, a provider of last-resort services for the vulnerable.
At the heart of the postmodern nation is a fragile and contradictory imme
diacy. On the one hand, the media of disembodied extension link distant,
privatized (or even still-localized) strangers into an abstract national com
munity by paradoxically giving a new immediacy to national occasions and
events. When our sporting heroes cover the nation with reflected glory at the
Barcelona Olympics, or when our defence forces carry the flag into the Gulf
war, we can all 'be there' , on the wings of the television. Over the past few
decades this media of immediacy has underscored a new nationalism. 54 lt has
53. The term 'postmodern nation' is used with reference to the way Jean-Fran,ois Lyotard and
others talk of the postmodern condition as the replacement of the old grand narratives by flexible
networks of information. However, it should not be taken to imply a concurrence with either the
methodology or the politics of such writers. See Lyotard's The Postmodern Condition. 1984.
54. It seems to have caught social theorists unawares. It is only possible to find isolated chap
ters, journal articles and newspaper sketches of instances of the phenomenon. l'or a discussion
of the new nationalism in Australia see Stephen Alomes, A Notum at La.,t•, 1988; cf. Stephen
f
Castles et al., Mistaken Identity: Multiculturalism and the Demi.<,· o Na1io11ali.m1 in A11.11ro/ia,
1988; Tony Bennett et al., eds, Celehrating the Nation. 1992; and Wayne Hudson and David
Carter, eds, The Repuh/icanism Dehate, 1993.
36 Nation For111a1ion
been evident particularly in the late-capitalist countries, from the United
States to New Zealand, from Japan to France. Apparently archaic and resid
ual cultural practices (Raymond Williams' terms), including conducting
Royal Marriages, sailing Tall Ships, competing before the Gods of Olympus
and committing ritual hara-kiri, have been given a new level of meaning, thin
as it is. National symbols are drawn together as pastiche. Public actors, from
political leaders and television evangelists to transnational corporations, have
been advised on the basis of computer-analysed opinion polls that it is advan
tageous to speak in the name of the nation'. They speak in the name of the
content of prior levels - traditional values and modern nation-building prac
tices - while effectively acting to displace those levels.
The new nationalism is thus continuous with modern nationalism but con
ducted with a new reflexivity. In this way it is increasingly open to
self-conscious cultural management. On the other hand, the new nationalism
has a febrile fragility. Because our distance from the past (over time) and from
our compatriots (across space) is 'overcome' in the accentuation of a single
level of integration (the disembodied), the ontological depth of the contem
porary nation-state is 'thinned out'. In the abstraction of time, tradition
comes to be a largely self-consciously upheld and selected set of practices. But
the more fervent this becomes the more the once taken-for-granted authen
ticity of tradition is revealed as no longer inscribed in itself, 'no longer written
in the stars'. The more our sense of history is managed, 'invented', the more
our attention is drawn to the processes of cultural management. In the
abstraction of space a constant tension also exists. At least four incongruent
developments can be listed: firstly, a nation's territory is thoroughly homog
enized in terms .of its cultural significance; secondly, some places, such as
Uluru (Ayers Rock) in Australia or Mount Fuji in Japan, are conferred with
symbolic meaning over and above, although representative of, the whole; 55
thirdly, one's everyday locale is emptied of such meaning - at least in any
binding sense - as an increasingly socially mobile population searches for the
optimal location to put down roots. And fourthly, certain corporate and state
centres, such as stock exchanges and bureaucratic departments, became focal
points for global networks of information and capital exchange which both
centralize space and dissolve it into what Manuel Castells calls 'flows and
channels' or Fredric Jameson calls 'hyperspace'. Anthony Giddens describes
aspects of this process in a passage notable for its broad connections:
The dissolution of the foundation of society in relations of presence substantially
replaces the grounding of those primordial sentiments in tradition and kinship by
a more routinised, habitual round of 'everyday life'. This is one point of intersec
tion, I have argued, between notions of 'mass society' and the theory of the
commodification of time and space deriving from Marx. In the spheres of 'everyday
life' created by the expansion of capitalism the areas of 'meaningful' existence
retreat - to the intimacy of personal and sexual relations on one side - and to the
55. For a discussion of the fusion of nation and territory, the historicizing of natural sites and
the naturalizing of built objects, see Smith, Ethnic Origins, 1986, pp. 1831T.
National Formation in Theory 37
arenas of 'mass ritual' on the other (as in spectator sports and in political ceremo
nial). In such conditions of social life the ontological security of the individual in
day-to-day life is more fragile than in societies dominated by tradition and the
meshings of kinship across space and time.56
There is a further complication. The long-term, uneven thinning out of
day-to-day life has, in conjunction with other factors sharpened by the late
capitalist mode of production and exchange, such as regional economic
disparities and cultural divisions of labour, 57 contributed to a renewed empha
sis on ethnicity, local culture, regional difference and the existence of hitherto
politically 'unrealized nations' within the hinterlands of existing nation-states.
Along with examples earlier listed under the heading of sub-state nations,
others can be added: ethnic groups such as the Alsatians/Lotharingians,
Bretons and Corsicans in France, the Kurds in Turkey and the Frisians in the
Netherlands. This neo-nationalism 58 is then distinct from, in some ways oppo
sitional to, what I have been calling the new nationalism, though both are
heightened by the same process. Neo-nationalism is clothed in the garments
of the modern nationalist movements of the nineteenth century. Yet in exist
ing at a different point in world time, in being set in the context of a changed
intersection of integrative levels, neo-nationalism, like the new nationalism, is
part of and a response to a more general transformation of the older national
form. The nation-state will not wither away in the foreseeable future, but it
can certainly be described as having entered a new stage in the way it bears
upon human subjectivity and social relations.
Integrative levels as levels of abstraction
The previous section in setting up a three-level schema of forms of integration
drew upon the illustrative point of entry of modes of embodiment. It was sug
gested that at each successive (that is,formally successive) level of integration,
the limitations and possibilities of embodied co-presence were progressively
abstracted. In practice, integrative relations were not only extended across
time and space, but the categories of being-in-the-world, including time and
56. Anthony Giddens, Power. Properly and S101e, 1981, pp. 193-194.
57. See for example Michael Hechter, Internal Colonialism, 1975 (for a critique of Hechter's
assertion of the cen1rali1y of cultural divisions of labour see Phillip Rawkins, 'Nationalist
Movements within the Advanced Industrial State', 1983; and Colin Williams, 'Ethnic Resurgence
in the Periphery', 1979); and also, Etienne Balibar and Immanuel Wallerstein, Race, Nalion.
Class, 1991.
58. The term comes from Tom Nairn, The Break-up of Britain: Crisis and Neo-Nationalism,
198 I. See also Walker Connor, Ethnona1ionalism, 1994, and his 'The Politics of
Ethnonationalism', 1973; Joseph Rudolph, 'Ethnic Sub-States and the Emergent Politics of
Tri-Level Interaction in Western Europe', 1977; Anthony H. Birch, 'Minorit y Nationalist
Movements and Theories of Political Integration', 1978; Peter Gourevitch, 'The Re-emergence of
"Peripheral Nationalisms"', I 979; Franjo Tudjman, Nalionalism in Conlemporary Europe, I 98 I;
Anthony D. Smith, The Ethnic Revil-al, 1981; and Edward Tiryakian and Ronald Rogowski, eds,
New Nationalisms of the De1·eloped West. 1985.
38 Natipn Formmion
space themselves, became lived in a more abstract way. The overlay of levels
used in this sense was not intended, then, to be understood simply as levels of
extension, as mental maps,59 or as a political geography of time-space dis
tantiation.60To do so would be to conceive of the different levels, treated here
as levels constitutive of ontological being, as if they merely extend across
a single plane. 61 (This point is crucial to later discussion.) It would be, in
other words, to treat the levels of the face-to-face, agency-extended and
disembodied-extended as if they were progressively larger circles of demarc
ated social activity able to be marked on a IT1flp, without recognizing how the
more abstract extensions of social relations are part of the overlay or recon
stitution even of the form of one's circle of day-to-day associations.
In short, to talk of constitutive levels is not the same as talking of degrees
of time-space distantiation. Neither, as mentioned earlier, can the position
being developed here be understood as setting up a series of ideal types. The
phrase used earlier, intersections-in-dominance, encapsulates the proposition
that given the intricate complexity of any specific social formation a society
can only be conditionally summarized in terms of its dominant level(s) of
integration. The same point has to be made in relation to describing the cat
egorical formations of tradition, modernity and postmodernity. (Just to
formalize the use of terms, the concept of 'intersection' is used throughout
more abstractly than that of 'conjunction' even though they have parallel
meanings.62) There is the ever-present proviso that any analysis remain sensi
tive to the contradictory processes of that level-in-dominance and to the
complicating intersections of forms of social practice, however they may be
framed: whether it be forms of identity grounded in face-to-face relations
such as gender and the embodied differences of race, or other more abstract
forms of association such as class. To do otherwise is (again making the point
in short-hand) to reduce the complexities of social life to an analysis couched
on one plane.
With regard to the national question, the key emphasis then is not just that
the processes of extension allow an institutionalized association of people to
colonize and administer larger expanses of territory in a relatively even way.
The more far-reaching proposition is that the 'stages' of national formation
59. Peter Gould and Rodney White, Mental Maps, 1986.
60. Anthony Giddens defines time-space distantiation as the stretching and integration of
social systems across time and space. Writings even in critical political geography tend to leave
aside the issue of ontological levels of space and time. For example in Derek Gregory and John
Urry, eds, Social Relations and Spatial Structures, 1985, at the only point at which the question
of ontological depth is raised it is said that it 'simply means that the world is conceived as a multi
dimensional structure and not "squashed into a flat surface "' (p. 328). Derek Gregory develops
this further in his sensitively written 'Presences and Absences', 1989, but it is elaborated more as
a critique of Giddens than the development of an alternative.
61. For a more detailed explanation of this term, see Sharp, 'Constitutive Abstraction', 1985.
62. 'Intersection' tends, for example, to be used with reference to a description of social for
mations theorized as 'levels of social integration'; 'conjunction' is used with reference to the more
usual (conjunctural) analyses of social formations.
Nmional Formation in Theory 39
have been based upon the uneasy intersection of levels of social being, con
stituted in the emerging dominance and widening generality of the forces
and relations of disembodied extension. It is suggested that although the
modern (and to a lesser extent the postmodern) nation continues to be expe
rienced as a concrete, historically condensed relation between people, it is
only through a constitutive lift in the level of abstraction that it is possible to
feel comradeship with a national mass who, except for one's personally
known network of associations, will largely remain anonymous strangers. 63
The materiality of abstraction
Running through the present discussion has been the assumption that the
processes of abstraction occur in practice as well as in thought.To round off
this chapter I would now like to spell this out further, firstly in relation to the
early developments of the modern abstract community, and secondly through
reference to the ambiguous place of the intellectually related groupings within
these developments. In keeping with the spirit of Benedict Anderson's ma
terialism these pages will attempt to stave off any unintended, idealist
residuals that inhere in the phrase 'imagined communities'. It is doubtful, for
example, that Anderson would be comfortable with Anthony Smith's rendi
tion: 'Benedict Anderson ...has defined the new nation of our imagination
as a sovereign but limited community, an essentially abstract mental con
struct'64 (emphasis added).
Abstraction quite obviously does occur in thought and, more broadly, in the
modes of apprehending and imagining the world.The history of concepts like
'society' or 'state' bears this out.65 The word 'state' derived from a face-to-face
level of reference, the Latin stare, meaning 'to stand' , and the comparative
term, status, a standing or condition which related to specific qualities. The
basis of status in the medieval period was one's estate, position and property
bound up in heredity and kinship, as well as one's occupation or station in life.
Monarchy was the highest estate. In the writing of Niccolo Machiavelli
(1469-1527) we still find lo stato referring most often to the standing of the
prince, rarely to the body politic in the more abstract sense. However, by the
sixteenth century the highest estate had come to be tentatively connected to
63. This phrase 'anonymous strangers' is an allusion to Vance Packard's A Nation of
Strangers, 1972, a lamentation to the fragmentation of contemporary social life.
64. Smith, Ethnic Origins, 1986, p. 169. That Anderson has unfortunately left himself open to
this interpretation can be seen in Maclaughlin, 'Reflections', 1988.
65. Society', the most a':>stract and generalized term we now have for a 'body' of people li\'ing
in structured social relations, came into English in the fourteenth century from the Latin word for
companionship. Raymond Williams documents the progressively abstract uses of 'society'
(Keywords, 1976). By the late eighteenth century it came to predominantly mean a system of com
mon life, or 'that to which we all belong, even if it is also very general and impersonal' (ibid., pp.
243-247). On the etymology of'state', see Vincent. Theories of the Stare. 1987. pp. 16 19; and
Kenneth Dyson, The State Tradition in Western Europe, 1980, pp. 25 33. Cf. Alexander
d'Entri:ves, The Notion of the Stare, 1969. ch. 3.
40 Naiiq,1 Formation
the body politic, the patria and a limited version of the public good. By 1595,
Pierre Charron (1541-1603) could write of /'etat as the 'bond within society
which cannot exist without it, the vital essence which brings life to human and
natural association'.66 The transition to European absolutism of the seven
teenth and eighteenth centuries ,�as accompanied by a tension between the
monarch-as-the-state and the state as an impersonal administration abstracted
beyond the monarch.76 In the context of late absolutism, a theory of constitu
tional sovereignty was argued out which confirmed the modern sense of what
is now commonly referred to as the abstract state, that is,a structure of power
independent of ruler and ruled.So in part, I can agree with J.H.Shennan when
he says: 'The concept of the state as abstract above and distinct from both gov
ernment and governed ...was coming to be understood in Europe before the
end of the eighteenth century, when its alliance with the national idea pro
duced a dynamic new force' 86 (emphasis added). However, this idealist
emphasis,which is common across the theoretical spectrum,69 has very limited
explanatory force.The conjoining of the abstract state 70 and the national com
munity of strangers - that is, the formation of nation-states - which began to
consolidate in the nineteenth century, required much more than the state and
the nation becoming abstract ideas. They also became abstract in practice. To
explain the reconstitution of sovereignty through this period, Shennan has to
reach for an obfuscating label - the matryoshka syndrome.The abstract state,
like the matryoshka doll, he says, has 'one replica within another', an 'elu
sive ... ultimate source',17 the abstract idea. The dog and its tail chase each
other around in circles.
Alfred Sohn-Rethel has indicated how it is possible to conceive of abstrac
tion as a materia) process, 'abstraction other than by thought'.27 And as
66. Cited in Dyson, Slate Tradi1ion, p. 27.
67. It is interesting to note, given the concern of this book with the rise of the mass media, that
in the early nineteenth century the initially derogatory term 'the fourth estate', probably first used
by Edmund Burke ( 1729-97), came into currency to describe the press.
68. J.H. Shennan, The Origins of the Modern European State, /450-1725, 1974, p. 114.
69. For an example of the more conventional argument, see Anton C. Zijderveld, The Abs/rac/
Society, 1974, ch. 3; and Robert A. Nisbet, The Sociological Tradi1ion, 1970, ch. 2, part 3. Nisbet
directly relates abstraction to individualization but narrowly treats the process as referring to
ideas, 'primarily to moral values': 'Now these values were becoming - through processes of
technology, science and political democracy - abstract; removed from the particular and the con
crete' (p. 43). He then runs into the difficulty of resolving the contradiction of individualism and
nationalism (p. 44). For an example from the marxist tradition, see Derek Sayer, The Violence of
Abs1raction, 1987. However, Sayer parlly recognizes the limitations of treating abstraction as only
an ideational process when he says: '"Simple abstractions", in short, are neither so simple nor so
abstract as they at first sight appear. They always articulate, even as they obscure, some more
concrete "substratum" - dare I say it, some material basis?' (pp. 140-141).
70. The 'abstract state' is a commonly used concept. See for example Nairn, Break-up of BriJain,
1981, p. 17. It is used here with the reservation that all state forms are abstract, and that the
so-called 'abstract state' is in practice only the state form at which the desacralization and deper
sonalization of power, and the 'separation' between the public and private, are relatively manifest.
71. Shennan, Modern European State, 1974, p. 85.
72. Alfred Sohn-Rethel, In1e//ec1ual and Manual Labour, 1978, ch. 2 and passim.
National Formation in Theory 41
Geoff Sharp has developed, Marx's own excursions into how the commodity
and labour abstractions of capitalism can be shown to be relevant to issues
pertaining both to consciousness and practice. The arguments of Marx and
Sohn-Rethel can be extended as a way into theorizing social relations in gen
eral. In the earlier discussion of levels of social integration and forms of
national association, it became clear that we were discussing not only the
abstraction of ideas but also the abstraction of lived social relations. Jose
Ripalda similarly makes a faltering beginning at distancing himself from the
idealist approach lo abstraction. The following passage is relevant to his
thinking about the process of abstraction and the rise of the modern abstract
nation-state. It also confronts us with an issue still to be clarified:
The Enlightenment itself was not an absolute beginning but one stage in a long tra
dition. Even its vocabulary refers to a century old theme: Nation, Fatherland,
People, Tolerance, Freedom, Skepsis were already the key words in the Europe of
Charles V [Holy Roman Emperor, 1500-58]. What separated the Enlightenment
from the Renaissance did not concern their theories as much as the different real
ity which constituted the content of these themes. The inherited concepts win in an
easily recognizable development a new sensitivity. It was the force of a new form of
productive relations which had been developing an unstoppable forward thrust
since the second half of the Middle Ages. And its abstraction is not only derived
from abstract Rationality which human relationships acquire in book-keeping, cal
culation of costs, and the programming of investment.73
It is at this point that Ripalda starts to get into trouble. Ironically, it occurs,
firstly, because of a residual idealism and, secondly, because of the residual
problems of the conventional base-imperstructure metaphor. They are prob
lems which grow out of each other. The above passage continues:
There is a second level of abstraction [Ripalda here uses a quite different metaphor
of levels than I employ]: the new relations of production can only slowly attain
their new concretion, their new world. The 'New' thus appears as abstract in rela
tion to the concretion of the 'Old', which for its part does not have 'Reason'.
However, modern abstraction refers to its concrete world. The abstraction of the
modern world is not primarily an operation of thought, but above all a palpable
action. 74
Ripalda is concerned to understand the thought-formation of an
eighteenth-century intellectual, Hegel, swept before the onslaught of the
double reality of the new world, the divided nation cleaved by the 'loss of
ancient social solidarity' and the development of a new form of unity.
However, because of the conventional base-superstructure framework which
underlies the analysis of The Divided Nation, Ripalda overemphasizes chang
ing relations of production as fully determinant of intellectual thought and
practice. It restricts the implications of his (partial) insight that societies are
constituted in overlaying levels of abstraction.
73. Jose Ripalda, Tire Dfrided Na1ion, 1977, pp. 2-3.
74. Ibid.
42 Nation Formation
•
The abstraction of intellectual practice
It was said earlier that the limitations ofRipalda's analysis confront us with
an issue still requiring clarification. The issue is encapsulated in the question:
what is the relation of intellecttlal thought and practice to the dominant
level(s) of integration of any particular social formation. The question is
important to us for a number of reasons. Firstly, a substantial section of
Nation Formation concentrates on the question, why did nineteenth-century
intellectuals like Marx and Engels, Durkheim and Weber in effect take the
nation for granted as a form of social relations? Secondly, it is important to
keep in mind that intellectuals were central in the original formations of
nationes, patria and nations. In the twentieth century they are equally central
in neo-nationalist movements and in reproducing and managing the ideolo
gies of the new nationalism. 75 Thirdly, although the conjunction of nation and
state was forged in the period of the consolidating of the capitalist mode of
production, longer-run (material) processes made it possible for certain
groupings, particularly intellectuals, to conceive of the existence of nationes
well before the generalized onset of capitalist relations of production and
exchange. Such conceptions also occurred long before 'the people' to whom
they referred had any sense of their more extended associations being any
thing other than either an occasional, external encroachment. Their extended
relationships were certainly not understood in terms of the metaphors of
face-to-face ties. For example, the medieval 'Welsh' bishop, Geoffrey of
Monmouth (note how he was named in terms of a particularity of place), was
able, in writing his legendary History of the Kings of Britain (1136), to connect
the disparate tribes of the Britons across time and space as a once-great
people originating in ancient Troy. 76 Similarly, the unknown author of a ver
nacular translation of Cursor Mundi, made about 1300, could imagine some
sort of community of 'lngland [th]e nacioun'. 77 But whether the 'common
people' during the Middle Ages could themselves imagine this abstract com
monality, 'lngland', as a communion of compatriots is doubtful.
This issue can be handled in terms of the levels metaphor. Intellectual prac
tice, by definition, works to transcend the limitations of embodied interaction.
Even in oral, tribal societies, interpreters of the passing particulars of social
life have to abstract generalized explanations. 78 The practices of reading signs
75. See Anthony D. Smith, Theories of Nationalism, 1983, ch. 6; Ernest Gellner, Nations and
Nationalism, 1983; Nairn, Break-up of Britain, 1981, pp. 33fT., 99fT., 117ff. and passim; Eric
Hobsbawm, 'Some Reflections on Nationalism', 1972; and Peter Worsley, The Third World,
1978, ch. 2, who, among many others, testify to the centrality of intellectuals and intellectual
groupings for the national question.
76. Hugh MacDougall, Racial Myth in English History, 1982, ch. I.
77. Basil Cottle, The Triumph of English, 1350-/400, 1969, pp. 16-17.
78. This is not to question the distinction Levi-Strauss makes between the 'preliterate intel
lectual', the bricoleur who works through signs, and the intellectual who wrestles with concepts
(entangled with imagery as such concepts tend to be). See The Savage Mind, 1966, ch. I. It is
however to agree with Jack Goody's criticism of Levi-Strauss for continuing to write of the sci
ence of the concrete and the science of the abstract in overly dualistic terms.
National Formation in Theory 43
from nature, storing memories of seasonal cycles, ritualizmg knowledge of
things in place, telling stories down the generations, all allow tribal inter
preters to 'transcend' the immediacy of what Braudel distinguishes as
day-to-day time and life-time. It provides the basis for their understanding of
things out of place. (The ambiguous meaning of 'out of place' is interpreta
tively useful.) This practice of abstraction is lifted to a further stage by the
most important technique employed by the post-tribal intellectual, namely
writing. As we have already seen, at a time when the intersection of
face-to-face and agency-extended relations provided the constitutive setting
for philosophical debates over the meaning of sovereignty and the office of the
king, writing provided a medium of disembodied interchange held in place by,
but abstracting from, those dominant forms of social relations. In short, while
all social formations are constituted in the overlay of levels of abstraction,
there are groupings of people who by virtue of the form of their practice
work at a level more abstract than the dominant mode(s) of integration. It is
this capacity that makes intellectuals and the intellectually trained - from the
medieval cleric to the contemporary public-opinion pollster and advertising
executive - important to any discussion of abstract communities.
Without underestimating their centrality, the ambiguous place of intellec
tuals and the intellectually trained still needs to be stressed. The abstract
relations associated with intellectual practices are bound up with a form of
subjectivity which generates contradictory yet interlocking ideologies.
Traditionalism, nationalism, individualism and cosmopolitanism are related
as one such complex meld. This point was first made at the beginning of this
century by Friedrich Meinecke (1862-1954) but subsequent theorists have not
taken any further Meinecke's descriptions of how the 'nation drank the blood
of free personalities' . 79 The problem is to explain how the pre-eminent pur
veyors of nationalist ideologies, ideologies advocating the importance of
cultural boundaries, were born out of universalizing, cosmopolitan thought.
At the end of the eighteenth century, intellectuals, from the conservative
Edmund Burke (1729-97) writing in the Vindication ofNatural Society (1756)
to the libertarian William Godwin (17 56-1836) in Enquiry Concerning
Political Justice (1793), were advocating various forms of pre- or preter
national association. At the same time, other intellectuals no less cosmopoli
tan in practice, such as the German Romantics, were beginning to praise the
nation and its Volk as the natural, realized subject of history. l n the language
of the levels argument, while the process of abstraction allows people to
reflect upon the historical grounding of their immediate community in
face-to-face relations, at the same time it lifts the person doing the recogniz
ing onto a more abstract level which is just as likely to support
internationalism or cosmopolitanism as it is nationalism.
The ambiguous place of the intellectual closely relates to a further issue.
The process of intellectual abstraction can lead to an increased focus on the
79. Cosmopolitanism and the Na/Ion Stare, 1907, p. 15.
44 Nation Formation
particular, and on that which is being reconstituted. The reconstitution of
more concretely constituted practices often generates a sense of loss or
romantic nostalgia for a past way of life. 80 By the same process, and often as
part of a contradictory subjectivity, it engenders a sense of liberation and
detachment. The past becomes a •place to be visited either for verification of
contemporary progress or, more recently, as a source of comparative knowl
edge for humanists, anthropologists and tourists. It is only at a highly abstract
and generalized level of historicity that it has meaning to propose the build
ing of a replica of Stonehenge next to the closed-off original site so that
tourists can concretely feel its rough slabs. 81 It is only very recently in history,
as Benedict Anderson reminds us, that the nationalistic hallowing of the bar
ren cenotaphs of Unknown Soldiers has had any meaning. 82 Because,
according to the argument being developed here, the nation is formed in the
intersection of constitutive levels, it is fundamental to its subjective hold that
the abstract community echoes with the concrete murmurings of the hopes
and tragedies of embodied existence, including human mortality. The ongo
ing irony is that this 'recalling of the concrete' constantly works to undermine
itself.
The contradictory nature of the recalling of the concrete can best be illus
trated through a brief problem-raising example. Justus Moser (1720-94), a
German historian writing at the end of the eighteenth century, abstracted an
'exciting new' thematic unity in German history. The princes, he argued, did not
form the body (Karper) of the nation but were accidents to it. He singled out the
common landed-property owners (die Echten) as 'the authentic constituents of
the nation'. They were a single, integral agency supplying 'not only the unity,
the direction, and the power of an epic ... but also the origin, the development,
and the severaJ..pioportions of the national character amid all its changes'. 83
Moser thus anticipated the later, more sophisticated and more abstract, marx
ian class analysis. 84 He found a way of theorizing a continuity through the
discontinuity of German history. He thus, paradoxically, formulated a way of
conceiving of German unity which was more abstract and yet less universalis
tic than the conceptions of the Volk as used by the sixteenth-century German
80. The present argument thus accords with Anthony Smith's discussion of historicity but
attempts to explain it more broadly. See Smith, Ethnic Revival, 1981, pp. 871T.
81. Jean Baudrillard gives similar examples, such as the caves of Lascaux in 'The Precession
ofSimulacra', 1983. For a discussion of this process of'reviving the past', see E.R. Chamberlin,
Preserving the Past, 1979; and Patrick Wright, 011 Living in an Old Country, 1985. On the repli
cation of'reality', see Umberto Eco, Travels in Hyper-Reality, 1987.
82. Anderson, Imagined Communities, 1983, pp. 17-18.
83. Justus Moser, Siimtliche Werke, cited in Leonard Krieger's brilliant essay 'Germany',
1975, pp. 94-95. On Moser's concept of'property' (Eigentum) as allegorically a social quality and
only secondarily an economic one, see Mack Walker, German Home Towns, 1971, Introduction
and pp. l 7lff.
84. On the etymology of the concept of'class' in its development in the modem sense between
1770 and 1840 (the period of the Industrial Revolution), see Williams, Keywords, 1976, pp. 51-59.
Also, from a different sociological tradition, see Nisbet, Sociological Tradition, 1970, ch. 5.
National Formation in Theory 45
humanists. This paradox can be given a consistent logic: social relations con
stituted at a more abstract level sustain, indeed generate, a tendency to
'critically' reflect on the terms of prior abstractions of unity and to give that
unity a new particularity.85
In the course of this discussion, aspects of the argument that the nation is a
distinctive kind of abstract community have been briefly outlined, drawing
inferences for theorizing national formation over different periods. The
proposition baldly laid down at the outset can now be recapitulated with
some clearer terms of reference. National formation only becomes possible
within a social formation constituted in the emerging dominance of relations
of disembodied integration. This level of integration is abstracted from and
yet based in a manifold intersection with prior levels - relations formed in and
through the limitations and possibilities of relations of the face-to-face and
agency-extension.
'National' consciousness was voiced, for the most part by intellectuals and
later by the intellectually trained, well before the gradually consolidating and
naturalizing conjunction of nation and state gained momentum during the
nineteenth century. Even in the earliest settings which conditioned the 'recog
nition' that one's identity was bound up in the natio, for example in the
medieval university, the consciousness of this 'compatriotism with strangers'
depended upon its articulators being at one level of their existence lifted out,
abstracted from, the binding relations of the flesh or what has been called
face-to-face integration. Intellectual technique was founded upon disembod
ied relations of time and place. The earliest and most passionate articulators
of a connection between identity and the general place of one's birth tended,
paradoxically, to be persons who had not only worked via the abstracting
medium of writing but those who had also literally journeyed beyond the
boundaries of their natus. In the Middle Ages this was not the constitutive
medium of the general populace.
In the early modern period, generalized changes began to take effect. Place
was framed by new forces and relations of agency-extension, in particular by
the administrative apparatuses of the absolutist and abstract state. Thus.
while relations of kinship and reciprocity continued to give meaning and
structure to social existence, outside the village such relations were reconsti
tuted at a more abstract level and at the same time were drawn upon to give
meaning to that level. The social relations and subjectivities associated with
the emerging predominance of newer means of disembodied extension from
the nineteenth-century newspaper to the twentieth-century satellite-linked
television network took this further, speaking to abstract audiences while
85. That Moser was a 'German patriot' (Goethe's word for him) and yet early in life corre
sponded with his family in French and had a close contact with England through the prm,mit)
of Osnabriick and Hanover is also consistent with the present argument. See Hans Kohn, The
Idea of Nariona/ism, 1944. pp. 4231T.
46 Nation• Formation
addressing people as if the relationship was more concrete. It is from this
intersection that the modern nation gets its 'depth' . It is from this intersection
that it is possible to argue that the nation-state is both deeply embedded and
yet objectively modern. It is simply a contradictory process.
The processes of abstraction in It-forming the ontological setting and over
coming the limitations of prior levels have in the late twentieth century
thinned out the basis for the objective and subjective hold of the 'classical'
nation; even as the modern nation is afforded new means of social connection
it is undermined. To the extent that we are .witnessing this process at the
moment, particularly in the capitalist West, a further 'stage' of abstract com
munity is developing, a postmodern nation. This setting ushers in new
contradictions: the state more and more penetrates into the day-to-day life of
its citizens (despite the ideologies of minimal government) while on the other
hand the degree of one's commitment to the nation increasingly becomes a
question of autonomous choice.
The following chapters do not attempt to prove these propositions. Rather
they seek through an examination of the strengths and weaknesses of existing
theories of the nation and nation-state to explore the explanatory usefulness
of the central thesis that the nation is an abstract community. The foregoing
discussion has highlighted a number of issues with which an adequate
approach to theorizing the national question has to deal. These will provide
an undercurrent of themes for subsequent chapters which first of all examine
the limitations of nineteenth-century, classical social theory, and thereafter go
on to assess the contributions of various expressions of post-classical social
theory. The first theme is the relationship of the subjective and objective, the
relation between ideas, ways of imagining the world, and the social-relational
setting constituti¥e"of and influenced by such forms of imagining. The second
theme is the contradiction between the 'primordial depth' of the national
form and the objective modernity and discontinuous history of not only any
particular nation-state we might wish to examine but also the form of
nation-states as we contemporarily know them. The third theme is the role of
intellectuals. Although most commentators recognize the centrality of the
intelligentsia and the intellectually trained in the stages of national formation,
little has been done explicitly to theorize the grounding conditions which
make it possible for them to abstract a community among strangers prior to
the generalization of a popular national consciousness, and through subse
quent periods of the reconstitution of national integration.
PART TWO: CLASSICAL THEORY
3
Marx and Engels: 'Seeing through
the Veil'?
The bourgeoisie has through its exploitation of the world-market given a
cosmopolitan character to production and consumption in every country.
To the great chagrin of Reactionists, it has drawn from under the feet of
industry the national ground on which it stood ... In place of the old
local and national seclusion and self-sufficiency, we have intercourse in
every direction, universal inter-dependence of nations. As in material, so
also in intellectual production. The intellectual creations of individual
nations become common property. National one-sidedness and narrow
mindedness become more and more impossible, and from the numerous
national and local literatures, there arises a world literature.
Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, Communist Manifesto, 1848
The Germanizing trend was negation, abstraction in the Hegelian sense.
It created abstract Germans by stripping off everything that had not
descended from national roots over sixty-four purely German genera
tions. Even its seemingly positive features were negative, for Germany
could only be led towards its ideals by negating a whole century and her
development and thus its intention was to push the nation back into the
German Middle Ages ... If this trend had been concretely German, if it
had taken the German for what he had become in two thousand years of
history, if it had not overlooked the truest element of our destiny, namely
to be a pointer on the scales of world history, to watch over the develop
ment of the neighbouring nations, it would have avoided all its mistakes.
Friedrich Engels, 'Ernst Moritz Arndt', 1841
Why, in the historical period that the intersection of nation and state was begin
ning to consolidate, did Marx and Engels appear to dismiss the nation-state as
a transitory form of association? And how at the same time could they effec
tively take the nation for granted as a category of social relations? This dilemma
should be recognized as basic to understanding the limitations of the marxist
theory of the nation, a dilemma with continuing implications. More than a
problem of emphases internal to their theory, the question points to the necessity
48 Nation Formation
I
of an explanation couched in terms of the period in which they were writing.
Asking why the writers of the period did not embark upon a project of theoret
ically taking apart the 'nation' is intended here to contribute to an overall
understanding of the nation in theory and practice. While the chapter does not
touch upon the way in which tht!'spectre of nationalism has, in the context of the
break-up of Eastern Europe and the Soviet Union, returned to haunt marxism,
this is the unspoken setting for the following retrospective questions.
Why wasn't the nation substantially theorized, as Marx so thoroughly initiated
in the sphere of political economy, or as Freud began a few decades later in rela
tion to the person? It was not until the beginning of the twentieth century with
the publication of Otto Bauer's controversial Die Nationalitiitenfrage und die
So:ialdemokratie (1907) that the 'first substantial Marxist analysis of nation
states and nationalism in relation to socialism' appeared.' In a sentence, Bauer's
approach emphasized the way in which the nation, persons 'bound together
through a common destiny into a community of character', were formed histor
ically and could not be taken for granted as natural. However, the history of
marxist theories of the nation is not the subject of this chapter. After a brief sec
tion on contemporary debates over the limitations of marxist theorizing, the
chapter will focus on the historical constitution of an elision in nineteenth
century theory. Consistent with the spirit of Marx's own theory, it is argued that
the author of the phrase 'social being determines consciousness' was consti
tuted within the determining conditions of his own history. 2 This contextualizing
has a double focus. Firstly, arising out of a discussion of the social and histori
cal conditions of the nineteenth century, it is suggested that the social form in
which the nation emerged contributed to masking Marx's recognition of what a
theory of the nation would entail. The nation emerged as a materially abstracted
community formed under the pressures of the globalizing extensions of social
relations, but also as a bounded community formed around subjectivities of
embodied connection. Marx was never able to reconcile these contradictory
modes of being. Secondly, arising out of a discussion of how the methodology
can be influenced by the conditions of its writing, it is suggested that in attempt
ing to delve beneath the surface of the dislocations and upheavals of social life
Marx fell back upon the abstract explanatory category of class. As important as
class analysis is, when reductively seen in terms of the base-superstructure frame
work. it closed off the possibility of a comprehensive theory of the nation-state.
A poverty of theory?
After the mid-nineteenth century, although still in the shadow of the
Enlightenment , the 'obviousness' of the nation changed from being a source
I. Tom Bottomore, 'Sociology', 1983, p. 112.
2. Paraphrase of Karl Marx, 'Preface to A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy'
(1859), in Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, Selected Works, vol. I, 1977, p. 503. Ian Cummins
(Marx, Engels and National Movements, 1980, p. 11) opens by making a comparable point, posit
ing it as the pivotal concern of his book, but it is only developed in terms of historical events, or
'directly political factors' (p. 179). See also his 'Marx, Engels, and the Springtime of Peoples', 1985.
Marx and Engels: 'Seeing through the Veil'? 49
of its taken-for-grantedness to the ground of a new agitation. Intense debate
ensued during the Second International, recasting Marx's view that 'nation
ality is already dead'. 3 But despite this interchange, marxism still
fundamentally failed to develop an adequate theory of the nation. Moreover,
if we come forward to the present, even as the fact of this poverty of theory
is being more commonly noted, little has been said by way of explanation for
the elision.4 Apart from Tom Nairn's 'thesis of the inevitability of the failure'5
and other scattered shafts of insight, discussion usually stays at the survey
of-literature level with its often narrowly conceived debates over the political
implications of this line or that. In some ways this appears to be merely a
change in style - a new, more exuberant archaeology has rediscovered previ
ously unheralded theorists, in particular Otto Bauer and Antonio Gramsci;
for others, the task begins with an amending of detail within Lenin's open
pragmatism. 6
Among most contemporary marxist commentators it has become manda
tory to clear the ground, and like Nairn, Bottomore, Miliband and Debray, say
something to the effect that: 'In a way, [the problem of theorizing the nation)
combines all the impasses of a traditional variant of Marxism. In fact, we have
to recognize that there is no Marxist theory ofthe nation; and despite the pas
sionate debates on the subject that have taken place within the workers'
movement, it would be far too evasive to say that Marxism has underestimated
the reality of the nation' 7 (emphasis added).
Arguments against these assertions of a poverty of theory, against this
3. Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, The German Ideology' (1846), in Selected Works, vol. I.
1977, p. 62. The context of the phrase reads: 'Generally speaking, big industry created everywhere
the same relations between classes of society, and thus destroyed the particular individuality of the
various nationalities. And finally, while the bourgeoisie of each nation still retained separate
national interests, big industry created a class, which in all nations has the same interest and with
which nationality is already dead.'
4. Anthony Giddens is one person who asks 'Why should this be?' ( The Nation-State and
Violence, I 985, p. 22). But he doesn't take an explanation beyond a history of ideas in attribut
ing it to the limitations of the legacy of earlier theoretical thinking: 'Saint Simon in political
theory and to the influence of classical political economy' (p. 26). John Ehrenreich has argued
that 'The deeper difficulty Marxists of all varieties have had in comprehending nationalism .
lies in Marx's own conception of the proletariat' ('Socialism. Nationalism and Capitalist
Development', 1983, p. 5), but this is still restricted to discussing theoretical log,c.
5. Tom Nairn, The Break-up of Britain: Crisis and Neo-Nationalism, 1981, pp. 329-331, 337.
He says 'Historical development had not al that time produced certain things necessary for such
a "theory'". Unfortunately these 'things' are hardly discussed by Nairn except lo say that marx
ism was unable to 'foresee the real contradictions of Progress' (p. 337).
6. For example, Brian Jenkins and Gunter Minnerup, Citi=ens and Comrades, 1984.
7. The words of Nicos Poulantzas, State, Power. Socialism, (1978) 1980, p. 93. Sec also for
example John Ehrenreich, 'The Theory of Nationalism: A Case of Underdevelopment', 1975. pp.
57--61, and Benedict Anderson, Imagined Communities, 1983. pp. 13-15; Nairn. Break-up of
Britain, 1981, 'Sociology', ch. 9; Bottomore, 'Sociology', 1983, p. 140. Ralph Miliband, cited m
Horace B. Davis, Toward a Marxist Theory of Nationalism, 1978, p. I; Regis Debray. 'Marxi,m
and the National Question', 1977, p. 30; Michael Dann, 'Marxism and the National Question',
1975, p. 29; J.L. Talmon, The Myth of the Nation and the Vision of Revolution, 1981. p. 6-t
50 Nation Formation
'ritual breast-beating',8 and for a return to orthodoxy continue to be written.
But they are a decreasing minority. J.N. Blaut, for example, maintains that,
'Bringing (the marxist theory of nationalism] up to date will not render it per
fect or complete.' In this respect he is right. 9 Blaut's next sentence however
firmly places him in the neo-orthodox camp: 'At the present juncture,' he
says, 'I think it is more important to recognize the strength, and essential
adequacy, of our theory of nationalism than worry about its imperfections.' 10
In much the same way that Ernest Gellner is sophisticated in reworking lib
eral orthodoxy while remaining within it-s limited terms, Blaut has only
rethought the content, not the form, of the proposition that nationalism is a
mechanism of class struggle.
Proponents of neo-orthodoxy in the main have very low expectations of
what a theory can be expected to explain. Take Pierre Vilar's breakdown of
Marx's sentence, 'the workingmen have no country':
[fhis] dense sentence [he says) demands a scrupulous analysis: I. the nation exists;
2. it is a political fact; 3. each dominant class erects itself as a national class; 4. each
national class identifies itself with the nation; 5. the bourgeoisie has done as much,
and the proletariat must do so; 6. in accordance with the class that assumes power,
the national fact can assume new meaning.
In my view that constitutes a theory, and one, moreover, confirmed by practice.
The elaboration depends on the historian. 11
As a sociologist-historian Vilar begs a thousand questions. In particular,
many other theorists would disagree with Vilar's view about what makes a
theory. Asserting the social (or political) factuality of the nation has a
Durkheimian echo; it only provides the barest beginning of an explanation .
Neo-orthodoxy can be distinguished from a further response, post
orthodoxy. I raise this distinction because there are at least two
post-orthodox points of partial dissension from the way in which the
poverty-of-theory proposition is formulated. From one direction, the
claim that there is no marxist theory of the nation is criticized for inadver
tently supporting the commonly held assumption that Marx and Engels'
contradictory and apparently ad hoc conclusions can be explained away
by pointing to the conditioning pressures of political exigency. Ephraim
Nimni argues that despite the fragmentary nature of their writings on the
nation there is an underpinning coherence. This coherence (and thus the
'legacy' of problems bequeathed to subsequent generations of marxist
8. Eric Hobsbawm, 'Some Reflections on "The Break-up of Britain'", 1977, p. 8.
9. Even the natural sciences have entered {what the post-structuralists happily call) the age
of indeterminacy: relativity, quantum mechanics and Godel's theorem in mathematics all entail
the recognition that theory will always be incomplete.
10. James M. Blau!, 'Nationalism as an Autonomous Force', 1982, p. 20. It should be noted
that even this doyen of orthodoxy does acknowledge that 'Marx-Engels' theory of state
viability ... was, by the way, the closest they came to a theory of nations' {p. 5). See also his The
National Question, 1987.
11. Pierre Vilar, 'On Nations and Nationalism', 1979, p. 22.
Marx and Engels: 'Seeing through the Veil'? 51
theorists) 12 was sustained within a 'form of economic reductionism com
bined with a social evolutionary paradigm'. 13 While it would be both circular
and idealist to claim that these limitations in themselves explain the poverty
of theory, the problems with a reductionist base-superstructure approach
have to be tackled as one of the impasses of marxism (Poulantzas' phrase).
Other positions or variations offering only new cul-de-sacs which are dis
cussed later in more detail can here be noted only cryptically: they range
from Ernest Gellner's ineffective inversion of the base-superstructure
metaphor, to Fredric Jameson's category contortions in collapsing sub
stantive changes in the structural-cultural form into changes between the
theoretical spheres of structure and culture. 14
From a second post-orthodox direction, the proposition that there is no
marxist theory of the nation is partially questioned by those who might be
called the new archaeologists. Ronaldo Munck provides a bridging example.
He begins his book, The Difficult Dialogue: Marxism and Nationalism, by
echoing Poulantzas: 'Essentially,' says Munck, 'Marxism has no theory of
nationalism.' But, after running through the myriad of classical to contem
porary marxist contributions, he is satisfied to turn back to Bauer and
Gramsci, to the socialist-Zionist, Ber Borochov, and the Irish socialist
republican, James Connolly. It remains a rhetorical gesture in that it comes at
the conclusion of his book and remains undeveloped. His assessment that
these writers provide the material 'to forge some kind of coherent Marxist
approach to nationalism' 15 is made on the basis that bits and pieces of their
work are relevant to a theory of the nation.
One of the tasks of the sixth chapter will be to assess the extent to which
contemporary marxist theorists, in particular Tom Nairn, have contributed
to overcoming 'Marxism's great historical failure'. Instead of going over
ground covered step by step in the numerous and comprehensive exigetical
histories of marxism on the national question, 16 we will take up themes
12. The notion of a 'legacy' of problems is put in inverted commas advisedly. A 'legacy' in this
sense is only such by virtue of it continuing to be actively adhered to and cannot be in itself an
explanation for its continuing theoretical hold.
13. Ephraim Nimni, 'Great Historical Failure: Marxist Theories of Nationalism', 1985, p. 59.
Sec also his Marxism and Nationalism, 1991.
14. These will be discussed in Chapter 6: Ernest Gellner, 'Scale and Nation·, 1974; Fredric
Jameson, 'Postmodernism, or the Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism', 1984, p. 86.
15. Ronaldo Munck, The Difficult Dialogue: Marxism and Nationalism, 1986, quotes from pp.
2, 168.
16. See for example: Samad Shaheen, The Communist ( Bolshevik) Theory of l\'ational
Self-Determination, 1956; Demetrio Boersner, The Bolsheviks and the National and Colonial
Queslion, 1957; Maxime Rodinson, 'Le Marxisme et la Nation', 1968; Michael Lowy, 'Marxists
and the National Question', 1976, pp. 81 100; Horace Davis, Theory of /l'alionalism, 1978, and
Nationalism and Socialism, 1967; Eric Cahm and Vladimir Claude Fiscra, Socialism and
Nationalism, 1978; Dave Holmes, 'Marxism and the National Question', 1979; Jcnkms and
Minnerup, Citizens and Comrades, 1984; Walker Connor, The National Qu,·.,tion in
Marxist-Leninist Theory and Strategy, 1984; Nimni, 'Historical Failure', 1985; Munck. Diffic11/J
Dialogue, 1986; and Ephraim Nimni, 'Marx. Engels and the National Question·. 1989.
52 Na,ion Formation
already touched upon, themes which have become increasingly important in
contemporary social theory: the constitution of and relationship between
social forms and subjectivity; the analytical connection between structure
and culture, base and superstructure; the problem of bringing the debates
about the 'rise of the cultural' and the 'invention of tradition' into contact
with discussions of longer-run social forms; the issue of how to take account
of the social categories of space and time; and the dilemma of how to under
stand the work of intellectuals as formed in an historical context and yet
pushing at the constitutive edges of that -particular context. The present
chapter begins by discussing marxism's classical roots.
Marx and Engels in the age of nationalism
Karl Marx (1818-83) and Friedrich Engels (1820-95) lived and worked
through the period commonly called the age of nationalism. 17 It was during
their lifetimes that the place of their birth, the Rhineland, was incorporated
in a unified Germany (the 'Second' Reich). They had argued over many years
for this outcome, though not for the form that unification eventually took
under the Prussian Junker, Otto von Bismarck ( I 815-98). Their position on
German unification expressed a theoretical logic which can neither be called
nationalistic nor be glibly criticized as contradictory. Engels may have been a
German nationalist in his youth, 1 8 and Marx a Young Hegelian; 19 however,
even their early writings were quite distinct from the directions taken by con
temporary German nationalist movements such as Young Germany, the
Burschenschaft and the Turnverein. 20 None the less, the crossovers between the
internationalil,t leanings of Marx and Engels' work and the age of national
ism are striking: the publication of their Manifesto of the Communist Party
'occurred quite ironically in the same year made famous by an early mani
festation of nationalism's rapid spread, namely the revolutions of 1848. From
17. The preface of Hans Kohn's impressive 'encyclopedic' book The Idea of Nationalism
(1944, p. vii) begins with the sentence: 'The age of nationalism represents the first period of uni
versal history.'
18. Davis, Nationalism and Socialism, 1967, pp. 2-3, 46. Engels wrote regularly for the 'Young
Germany' journal Telegraph fur Deutsch/and. See Marx and Engels, Collected Works, vol. 2,
1976, e.g. p. 149.
19. David Mclellan notes that Marx's first contribution to the Rheinische Zeitung followed
Hegel in seeing the state as an 'expression of Reason and the highest incarnation of morality'
(Karl Marx: Early Tex1s, 1972, p. xvii).
20. The Burschenschaft was a radical student association founded in 1815 to work for German
unity; the Turnverein 'Gymnastic Movement' was begun by Friedrich Jahn in 1811 to raise a
'regenerative elite' for the German nation. Engels was critical of Jahn and the Gymnasts as
one-sided extremists (see Marx and Engels, Co/lec1ed Works. vol. 2, 1976, pp. 138-141, 166). As
we might have expected, more populist nationalistic associations did not emerge until much
later (in the 1880s) and even then the most active members of organizations like the Pan-German
League were drawn from the academically educated. See Roger Chickering, We Men Who Feel
Mos/ German, 1984, chs I and 5.
Marx and Engels: 'Seeing through the Veil'? 53
this point on, nationalism and Marxism were contemporaries.' 21 For example,
Marx was exiled in London at the same time as the Italian nationalist,
Giuseppe Mazzini (1805-72). Except for Mazzini's brief returns to the conti
nent, both men lived in London for the remainder of their working lives,
arguing for 'opposing' forms of abstract community. 22
In order to highlight the tenor of the period in which Marx was writing, it
is instructive to slice into the nineteenth century at a particular juncture. No
overriding methodological pre-eminence is claimed for this approach. It is
simply a means of confining the illustrative historical detail described at the
level of empirical generalization, while more graphically pointing up the con
junctures, overlapping levels and contradictions in the broader sweep of
change. The year 1871 is somewhat arbitrarily chosen; it is symbolic because
it was the year of German unification and of the Paris Commune, and perti
nent because it is within the most productive period of Marx's writing.
The section about to be embarked upon, 'Contradictions and transforma
tions', will argue that Marx for good reasons overestimated the flattening
force of late nineteenth-century internationalization. The subsequent section,
'Intersection of levels', will suggest that despite this he remained ambiguous
in his treatment of the historical specificity of the nation-state, both overem
phasizing its consolidation in the late nineteenth century and overasserting
the potential of the bourgeois revolution to sweep away national difference.
Together these points will be used to suggest the beginnings of an explanation
for the limitations of his theory of the nation.
1871: contradictions and transformations
In 1871 Marx's writings were readily circulated to an international, or rather,
a number of language-bound, reading publics: the Russian translation of
Das Kapita/ went to press, the Communist Manifesto was published in the
feminist New York journal, Woodhull and Claflin's Weekly; and the Civil War
in France (May 1871) was printed as a pamphlet in London and serialized in
several countries of Europe, including the German and Belgian journals.
ironically called, respectively, Volksstaat and L'Jnternationale. 23 The broader
point is that 1871 was caught in the midst of the extension of the means of
21. Connor, The Narional Quesrion, 1984, p. 6. Interestingly it was Engels who, long before
Connor, first drew attention to this coincidence: 'Preface to the First Italian edition of 1893', in
Marx and Engels, Selected Works, vol. I, 1977, p. 106. Engels added that consequent upon the
1848 revolutions 'these two great nations (Italy and Germany] were reconstituted and somehow
again put on their own ... the men who suppressed the Revolution of 1848 were. nevertheless,
its testamentary executors in spite of themselves'.
22. From 1868 Mazzini lived at Lugano, only fifteen miles outside Italy, and in 1872 he made
his way across the border disguised as an Englishman, to die at Pisa in his 'homeland'. For an
introduction to Mazzini's writings, and his advocacy of nationality and the 'holy Fatherland' as
the association best moving toward a universal and moral "Catholicism of Humanity', see his The
Duties of Man and Other Essays, ( 1844 70) 1924.
23. Hal Draper, The Marx-Engels Chronicle, 1985. pp. 162 173; Thomas Guback and Ronald
Rettig, 'Translating the Manifesto into English', 1987.
54 Ntxion Formation
spreading ideas, simultaneously within, across and beyond nation-states.
Internationalism and nationalism (as well as, and in cultural contradiction
with the processes of internationalism, the 'rediscovery' of the spirit of the
village) were facets of the sam�process of the extension and abstraction of
social relations. The rediscovery of prior forms of association had quietly
burgeoned with the Philosophes, but bloomed in the century that Marx's life
was to span. It is not an accident, as they say, that nineteenth-century his
toriography became exuberant in its research of comparative and nationally
couched histories. Examples can be drawn from our chosen year of 187 I:
Henry Maine (1822-88), English jurist and historian, published Village
Communities; Pierre Le Play (1806-82), French mining engineer and sociol
ogist, published The Organization of the Family; also, between 1868 and
1913 the German jurist Otto von Gierke (1844-1921) wrote his multi
volume German Law of Associations. This was the period in which the Great
Divide between the 'archaic' and the 'modern' was first given theoretical
force.
On the one hand, there was the internationalizing of academic and pub
lishing networks and such developments as the emergence of the concept of
world news. In 1870-71 the world was carved up into exclusive news territo
ries by a European cartel headed by Reuters. 24 Marx was still more concerned
about the older, rapidly consolidating forms of transport - railways - than the
new, more abstract and disembodied means of communication such as the
telegraph. He failed to note that the world was for the first time being inter
connected in a way that, unlike even the circulation across a world market of
abstracted commodities, detached the mode of communication from the var
ious means of embodied transport. 25 For example, in 1871, less than three
decades aftet the construction of the first overland telegraph lines, the fur
thest interlinking of the British Empire was achieved with an underwater line
to Australia. Messages no longer had to be carried by people, either person
ally or by conveyancing agents.
On the other hand, even these processes were not simply forces of interna
tionalization. The first information revolution, 'begun' at the time of Johann
Gutenberg (c.1394-1468) and confirmed in the burgeoning of print
capitalism, was also contributing fundamentally to the process of delimiting
national boundaries. This included the establishment of wide-circulation,
largely metropolitan-based daily newspapers as well as, at the other end of the
literary spectrum, the initially less market-oriented activities of a new pro
fession of intellectuals, the 'vernacularizing lexicographers, grammarians,
philologists and litterateurs' . 26 Lexicographers, such as the American Noah
Webster, subtly contributed to marking the difference between kindred
24. Jeremy Tunstall, The Media are American, 1977, ch. I.
25. Giddens, Nation-State and Violence, 1985, makes something of this point, emphasizing its
significance in the consolidation of the nation-state (pp. 172-178).
26. Anderson, Imagined Communities, 1991,passim and quoted from p. 71. He calls the nine
teenth century the 'golden age' of this lexicographic revolution.
Marx and Engels: 'Seeing through the Veil'? 55
national cultures, down to choosing different patterns of spelling, 27 while
others, such as those from the Academie Fram;;aise, acted in not-so-subtle
ways to break the hold ofthe regional dialects.
Marx and Engels emphasized the process of internationalization, the
'breaking down ofbarriers', and the penetration ofand drawing into a world
capitalist economy of all that was regional, 'backward', or isolated. But this
led to an underestimation of the fact that those same processes which gener
ated internationalism were (in more than an interim way) also reconstituting
peasants as national citizens. 28 Secondly, it led to the acceptance ofa doctrine
which, although logically subsumable within their theory of international
ization, further retarded the possibility of Marx and Engels thinking their
way out of the image of Monsieur Capital marching insouciantly across the
globe, trailing behind him the increasingly tattered remnants of nationality. I
am referring to the Hegelian doctrine of historical and 'historyless peoples',
progressive and unprogressive peoples, the latter said to have a future only as
ethnographic movements. 29
These relics of a nation mercilessly trampled under foot in the course of history,
as Hegel says, these residual fragments of peoples have always become fanatical
standard-bearers of counter-revolution and remain so until their complete extirp
ation or loss of their national character, just as their whole existence in general is
itself a protest against a great historical revolution. 30
Much can and has been made of Marx and Engels' ethnocentrism and the
dominance in their work ofan ideology ofprogress, but neither detailing the
doctrine ofhistoryless peoples nor debating whether or not Marx and Engels
were latent racists will take us very far in understanding the limitations of
their theory of the nation.
Marx and Engels' views on the reach, penetration and historical depth of
capitalism have in many ways been confirmed by recent research . Theorists
like Immanuel Wallerstein and Eric Wolfhave criticized the tendency ofsocial
science as it heads in both its universalizing and particularizing directions to
underplay the homogenizing force ofcapitalism and to assume the nation, or
people, or state as the basic unit ofanalysis. They, like Marx and Engels, have
argued instead for a world-capitalist system which had its origins prior to the
sixteenth century. 31 Leaving aside intense debate over methodology and
27. V.P. Bynack, 'Noah Webster's Linguistic Though I and 1he Idea of an American National
Culture', 1984.
28. Eugen Weber, Peasants into Frenchmen, 1976.
29. Engels was more prone 10 this position than Mar,. See Solomon Bloom, The World of
Nations, 1941, ch. 3; Charles C. Herod. The Nation in the lli.rtory of Marxian Thought, 1976;
Anthony D. Smith, Theories of Nationalism, 1983, pp. 72-74; Silva Meznaric, 'A Neo-Mamsl
Approach 10 the Sociology of Nationalism, Doomed Nations and Doomed Schemes', 1987;
Roman Rosdolsky, Engels and the 'Non/ristoric' Peoples, 1964.
30. Engels, 'The Magyar Struggle' from lhe Neue Rheinische Zeitung. edited by Marx in
Collected Works, vol. 8, 1977, p. 234.
31. Immanuel Wallerslein, The Modern World System, 1976; and Eric R. Wolf. Europe and the
People Without History, 1982. See also William N. Parker, writing oul of a dilTerenl lrad111on. in
Europe, America and the Wider World, 1984.
56 Na,ion Formation
details of emphasis, their critique of bounded states as the basic analytic unit
has, for the most part, been convincing. 32
However, concentrating on the homogenizing, internationalizing force of
capitalism can have the effect ofJreating social life as if it were constituted on
one plane. 33 We have to be careful for example not to overstate the coherent
interconnectedness of the world system (or at least, and this is the crucial
point, not to confuse the levels at which and for whom the connection is
made). The complexity of levels can be illustrated through a brief excursion
into the dominant ontologies of time and space current in the late nineteenth
century. Even at the late point in history now under discussion conceptions of
the globe remained unstable. In 1871 there was for example still no stan
dardization of time within England, France or Germany, let alone across
Europe or the globe. World Standard Time was not introduced until 1884,
and then it came mainly through commercial pressure from North America.
It was not really adopted until after the 1912 conference in Paris. An 1870
pamphlet by Charles Ferdinand Dowd, A System of National Time for
Railroads, listed over eighty different time standards in America alone. 34
Most people certainly did not think of themselves as located in a single,
nationally bound time-frame, or in one time-phase relative to a systematically
graded, global schema. The exceptions were found in the intellectually related
groupings and aristocratic and business classes. Global circumnavigation, as
distinct from transcontinental migration, was in practice restricted to an iso
lated aristocrat-intellectual such as Sir Charles Wentworth Dilke or an
entrepreneur-adventurer such as the Boston businessman George Francis
Train. For the reading classes, global voyagers had come into literary vogue,
climaxing with Jules Verne's international bestseller, Around the World in
Eighty Days (written 1871-2), but the appeal of such novels was based on
their novelty. Verne's books, of which there are more than sixty, were collec
tively written as Les Voyages Extraordinaires, and subtitled 'Known and
Unknown Worlds' . Sir Charles Wentworth Dilke's world-tour memoirs pub
lished in 1868 were modestly called Greater Britain: A Record of Travel in
English-Speaking Countries; and William Perry Fogg was lashing out when in
1872 he called his book Round the World. The aristocratic grand tour was not
displaced by world discovery tourism until the end of the epoch of discovery
at the turn of the century, and most people were only semi-literate and would
not have read their accounts. Even Jules Verne himself remained uncomfort
able about the emerging concept of global space. His central character,
Phileas Fogg, a fetishist for punctuality, and the personification of Verne's
32. For a useful overview of the debates see Robert S. Du Plessis, 'The Partial Transition to
World Systems Analysis in Early Modern European History', 1987, pp. 11-27.
33. This is not to say that emphasizing the processes of internationalization makes one prone
by definition to 'treating social life as if it were constituted on one plane'. See the section above
in Chapter 2 entitled 'Integrative Levels as Levels of Abstraction'.
34. See Stephen Kern, The Culture of Time and Space, 1983, pp. 12-16, 74-75; and Giddens,
Nation-State and Violence, 1985, pp. 172-178.
Marx and Engels: 'Seeing through the Veil'? 57
theme of time-regulated humanity, 35 rounded the world in the specified time
and won his bet helped by the 'fact' that by 'journeying toward the east, [he]
was going toward the sun, and consequently the days became as many times
four minutes less for him as he crossed degrees in that direction'.36 Obviously
it is not possible. Verne (1828-1905) is as confused as the popular conceptions
were bemused. None the less, behind the confusion there is here the barest
beginnings of the view that time and space are relative, that time can be dis
embodied. However, for intellectuals of that period, even such as Marx and
Engels, the sweeping power and apparently liberatory consequences of 'the
breaking down of [spatial] barriers' was self-evident in a way that the onto
logical relativity of these categories of space and time was not.
A further point needs to be made. The abstraction of time and space
involved not only a looking out beyond the limits of the old horizons, but also
a closing in, a new means of focusing the meaning of place. Articles published
as early as the 1830s spoke of the gradual annihilation of space and time.
This is important to the conception of national space.One author wrote of the
devastating effect of the railways, saying that 'on the map of the imagination
[every house, village, town and territory] would finally be reproduced and
reduced down to the infinitely small!' Employing a different hyperbole another
said that 'the whole population of the country would, speaking metaphori
cally, at once advance en masse, and place their chairs nearer to the fireside of
their metropolis'.37 This contraction of space and time is experienced simulta
neously with (in fact by virtue of) the extension of the means of incorporating
more space into an experiential ambit. The contraction of rural areas 'into a
metropolis ...conversely appears as an expansion of the metropolis: by estab
lishing transport lines to ever more outlying areas it tends to incorporate the
whole nation'. 38 Thus writers, intellectuals, began to reformulate this changing
sense of time and space in terms of the intersection of nation and state.In the
twenty years prior to 1871, German railroad mileage tripled; it was one, small,
c
self-conscious part of the transfiguration of 'hometown society' (Natiirlil1e
Gemeinschaften) and the consolidation of the nation-state. 40 By 1871 the
39
same logic was beginning to apply to the subjective sense of the globe.
35. Jean Chesneaux comments that the character of Phileas Fogg was the 'man-machine' who in
Verne's words functioned 'without friction' (The Political and Social Ideas ofJules Vi•me, 1972, p. 42).
36. Jules Verne, A Tour of the World in Eighty Days, (1873) n.d. Sec Kern, Culture of Time and
Space, 1983, p. 218.
37. Economie Sociale, 1839, and Quarterly Review, 1839, cited in Wolfgang Schivelbusch,
'Railroad Space and Railroad Time', 1978, p. 32.
38. Shivelbusch, 'Railroad Space', 1978, p. 33.
39. The hometown lost political relevance and was drawn into an extended setting e,en
though the nostalgic 'recuperation' of Gemeinsc/raft values proceeded apace. Mack Walker.
German Home Towns, 1971, ch. 12, 'Death and Transfiguration'. Fascism of course brought the
'longings of intellectuals for national community and hometownsmcn's parochial values' into a
new intersection.
40. For a more extensive discussion of the relation between time and the nation-state see
David Gross, 'Space, Time, and Modern Culture', 1981 82, and his 'Temporality and the
Modern State', 1985.
58 Nation Formation
Taking just the issue of the sense of space, it can be concluded that by a
process of abstraction in thought and practice, contraction and extension
were being experienced simultaneously. Marshall McLuhan's vision of a
shrinking global village was in .ine sense beginning to be conceivable by the
late nineteenth-century intellectual. But imagining, much less producing, the
form of that writer's community, with its new level of time-space simultaneity
mediated by the computer and satellite-broadcasting was still a long way
off.41
We have to enter the twentieth century lo find the generalization of this
quite new subjectivity of time and space. In Remembrance of Things Past, a
novel by Marcel Proust (born in 1871 ), telephone operators act as the 'priest
esses of the Invisible' bringing the sound of a stark contradiction: 'distance
overcome' but through communication with the truncated abstraction of a
dying relative. 42 In Proust's work as much as through Einstein's (1879-1955)
touchcd upon in the next chapter - it is possible to see the dawning of the age
of relativity where time and space are self-consciously located on relative and
shifting planes. Back in 1871, even though Marx and Engels were able to the
oretically take partial hold of the extension and fragmentation of social
relations, and despite Marx's paradigm-breaking analysis of the abstraction
of time in the production, fetishism and circulation of commodities, they
were still nevertheless bound within the same broad ontological view of exten
sion and internationalization as the bourgeois globe-trotter, Jules Verne. That
is, extension was conceived of as occurring on one plane. 43 This is basic to
understanding the first part of the dilemma with which we began, namely that
Marx saw the development of a global class-structure through which 'nation
ality is already dead' .
In a theoty which recognizes the globalizing impact of capitalism but
remains set on one plane, however much the dialectic is invoked internation
alization and the levelling effect of capitalism will perforce appear the
dominant, and the basic, constitutive logic. It is particularly so given that
Marx and Engels, like Darwin (1809-82) and even, in his own way, Nietzsche
(1844-1900), were concerned to develop an underlying theoretical explana
tion and practical synthesis of the process of fragmentation. The subjectivity
of the extension of social relations as levelling, continues to be expressed in
the present: we can cite equally the contemporary, conservative ideology of
41. Marshall McLuhan, Understanding Media: The Extensions of Man, 1964.
42. Discussed by Kern, Time and Space, 1983, ch. 8. Compare this to Jules Verne's The
Begum"s Fortune where in his futuristic millennial city, significantly called Franceville (the Village
of France), the town council hold their meetings by telephone. See Kenneth Allot!, Jules Verne,
(n.d.) c.1940, passim on science, technics and the themes of time in Verne's work.
43. This is a related but narrower point than that made by Geoff Sharp when he says: 'A gen
eral way of stating the limits within which Marx's theory was constrained is to represent his
conception of society as set within one constitutive plane. While the theory of the commodity
breaks into a further constitutive layer, the image of society as composed of an intersection of
constitutive layers is never explicitly generalized.' ('Constitutive Abstraction and Social Practice',
1985, p. 59).
Marx and Engels: 'Seeing through the Veil'? 59
the end of class, as well as a contemporary marxist like Marshall Berman who
when describing Marx's era says, 'For the first time in history, all confront
themselves and each other on a single plane of being.' 44 It is not that they are
wrong, but having a theory of this levelling of subjectivity is a different mat
ter. More of this later.
1871: intersection of levels
Just as we have to be careful about not overstating the interconnectedness of
the world system, equally the consolidation of the nation and state, even as
late as I 871, should not be exaggerated. Ascribing full significance to this in
one sense complicates the problem of explaining Marx's approach. It appears
to confound the second part of the dilemma, namely that although national
ity is said to be 'already dead', Marx and Engels effectively take the nation for
granted, treating it as a long-run, post-tribal form of association. They use
the term 'nation' as equally applicable to polities from the Phoenicians to the
Germans both before and after unification under Prussia. 45 Connor argues
that Marx was 'given to slipshod terminology, often using nation to apply to
a state or to an ethnically heterogeneous society' .46 But whether or not this
point is accepted the problem still remains. Why is there such an ambiguity in
Marx's writing? To explain this it is helpful to recognize the nation as being
a contingent, though logical, outcome of the intersection between a consti
tutive level of social integration which in 1871 was still far from moving into
dominance and prior levels which hold continuing force. This formalistic
metaphor of intersecting levels is limited in itself, but here as always it is in
tended only to open the way to discussing issues that the base-superstructure
metaphor closes off. Marx and Engels variously described the nation in terms
of these different levels, although not named as such, without having a theory
which made sense of, or was even sensitive to, the ambiguity it engendered.
For them a nation was at once a tribe of people bound by face-to-face ties of
kinship and mutual history, and a community of strangers connected by
more abstract means of integration including commodity exchange. In the
context of a general culture which had not resolved the definition of the
nation, Marx and Engels, understandably then, remained unconcerned about
the implications of this ambiguity for the politics of the national question.
Rather than confounding the problem, recognizing the uneven consolida
tion of the nation-state brings us closer to an explanation of the poverty of
theory. The argument about intersection of levels needs expanding but it can
be done partly in the context of arguing through the still undemonstrated
44. Marshall Berman, All rha1 is Su/id Mells in/0 Air, 1983, p. 116.
45. See for example Selected Works, vol. I, 1977, pp. 55, 111, 112, 304, 307, 321.
46. Connor, The National Queslion, 1984, p. xiv. See also the more sympathetic "TIiings of
Bloom. 'The Social Conception of the Modern Nation', ch. 2 in The Jl,,r/d oj Na/ions, I941: and
Roman Rosdolsky, 'Worker and Fatherland', 1965. The ambiguity of the nation as community
and as nation-state was prevalent across the world. For example sec Erik S. Lunde, The
Ambiguity of the National Idea: The Presidential Campaign of 1872", 1978.
60 Nafion Formation
assertion that even towards the end of the nineteenth century the nation-state
was still in transition from the absolutist state and the polyethnic empire. The
diverse examples of'Germany', 'Italy', 'England' and 'Japan' will be used. It
is hopefully clear by now that th.ls does not mean I am arguing that the nation
is simply an invention of late nineteenth-century Europe and that processes
going on outside Europe, or cultural changes going back to the late Middle
Ages within Europe such as the vemacularization of literary expression, are
irrelevant. In fact, quite the opposite. But those writers who insist on the view
that nationalism was a visible force in the medieval world are yet to theorize
how it is that such a force is so tentatively established eight centuries later.'7
Perhaps it is no wonder that Marx remained ambiguous on the question.
In 1871, dynastic states and empires, admittedly becoming less absolutist in
their control, still made up the large majority of the world's political sover
eignties. It has been noted already that it was the year of German national
unification. Universal male enfranchisement, excluding the full range of mod
em 'deviants' such as political exiles like Marx, was announced in that country
as well as in France. However, a couple of additional remarks put the German
unification and its extension of the rights of citizenship into a different per
spective. Germany was not unified as the outcome of its cultural nationalism.
We are thus faced with what John Breuilly calls the 'thorny problem ofthe lack
of congruency between "cultural" and "political" nationalism'. 48 A parallel
and more paradoxical problem is that unification initially gave the monarchy
enormous power while, increasingly, such personally embodied, agency
extended power, sustained in part by force of arms, lost political legitimacy
with the citizenry who had been given new rights by unification.
It is significant that the Second Reich was formally inaugurated on I 8
January 187 I with the crowning of the King of Prussia, Wilhelm I, as the
Emperor ofGermany; it was conducted onforeign soil by the German princes
assembled in the Hall of Mirrors of the royal French Palace at Versailles. This
was not empty ritual. Wilhelm I received the Imperial German crown without
any allusion to the sovereignty of the German people. Germany's newly insti
tuted constitution recognized an autocratic monarch (the Kaiser) over a
relatively powerless parliament. It was to the Kaiser only and not to the par
liament or the people that the chancellor was responsible. 49 The first and
most powerful chancellor, Bismarck, was able to be dismissed nineteen years
later by Kaiser Wilhelm II (1859-1941) even though monarchical power was
by then beginning to wane.
The details of history disturb the usual, neat sense of progressive change.
Anachronistic by some criteria, monarchy persisted even as it was reconsti
tuted in its relationship to sovereignty, political power and to popular culture.
47. See C. Leon Tipton, ed., Nationalism in the Middle Ages, 1972; and Halvdan Kohl, 'The
Dawn of Nationalism in Europe', 1947.
48. See John Breuilly, Nationalism and the State, 1994, ch. 2. Quoted from John Breuilly,
'Reflections on Nationalism', 1985, p. 72.
49. Stephen Roberts, History of Modern Europe, 1950, pp. 319-321, 343-348.
Marx and Engels: 'Seeing lhrough the Veil'? 61
This poses problems for Marx's proposition that: 'With the change of eco
nomic foundation the entire immense superstructure is more or less rapidly
transformed.'50 How would the base-superstructure framework handle the
fact that the Kaiser, Wilhelm II, who we will see in another connection in a
moment, was one of the first 'statesmen' to utilize the management of 'pub
licity'. Publicity emerged as a new 'necessity' as a relationship developed
between the form of diplomacy, still largely conducted among a 'transna
tional', often blood-related, ruling elite, and the citizenry, a technologically
extended, mass electorate increasingly integrated through the popular press? 51
It is an example of the intersection of levels.Even at the end of the nineteenth
century, kinship-based, face-to-face relations crossed still-consolidating
national boundaries. After Bismarck, 'it was still possible for the Prince
Chlodwig zu Hohenlohe-Schillingsfilrst to be German Chancellor, for one of
his brothers to be a Cardinal of the Roman curia, for one of his nephews to
be an Austrian minister, and for another to be an Austrian general and diplo
mat who later on became Ambassador in Berlin'.52
Italy, labelled by Marx and Engels a revolutionary nation, provides a sim
ilar picture. In 1871 monarchy was being institutionalized and thus
secularized; religion was retreating to the periphery of political power.
Italian unity was seen by all except the Italia irredenta to be at least on the
way to completion. However, the nation was not simply leaving all prior
forms in its wake. Seton-Watson makes clear it is 'not a gross distortion to
describe "Italy" as a colony of the Piedmontese'. 53 In 1871 Vittorio
Emmanuele (1820-78), the erstwhile Piedmontese King of Sardinia, and by
this time King of Italy, addressed the first Italian parliament in Rome saying
that, 'The work to which we consecrated our life is accomplished ...our
people, after centuries of separation, find themselves for the first time
solemnly reunited in the person of their representative . .. '54 (emphasis added).
There are in these words two matters of note.There is the implicit reference
to an immemorial national existence, if not an unrealized, underlying unity.
Secondly, there is the continuation in a more secular-abstract form of the
medieval assurance of the king's sacred body as representing the unity of the
50. From the 'Preface to A Critique of Political Economy' ( I 859), in Marx and Engels,
Selected Works, vol. I, 1977, p.504; cf. Marx and Engels, where they say that 'History is noth
ing but the succession of separate generations, each of which ... continues the traditional
activity in completely changed circumstances and, on the other [hand) modifies the old circum
stances with a completely changed activity' ('The German Ideology' (1846), in Selected Harks,
vol.I, 1977, p.38).
51. David Thompson, Europe Since Napoleon, 1957, ch. 16, and pp. 374-375; Eric Hobsbawm,
'Mass-Producing Traditions: Europe I870-1914', 1983. On the limitations of absolutism and the
'myth of the omnipotent ruler' see Walter Hubatsch, Studies in Medie,·al and Modern German
History, 1985, ch. 8. Hubatsch cites Friedrich Naumann's 1899 Berlin lecture where, ironically.
he said that mass communications had given rise to a nascent third force in politics 'beside
Parliament and the Federal Council', namely the Kaiseramt (Imperial Office) (p. )54).
52. Hans Morgenthau, Politics AmonJ? Nations, (1948) 1976. p. 244.
53. Hugh Seton-Watson, Nations and States, 1977, p. 108.
54. Document in M.Christine Walsh, ed., ProlaJ?Ue, 1968, p. 103.
62 Nalion Formation
body politic. 55 Behind chose words are further issues: the settlement of 1870
had placed the parliament in Rome, destroying the temporal power of the
papacy. It was part of the general world-wide remaking of the sacred-secu
lar relation. (On the other hanq. the Law of Guarantees declared the pope's
person inviolable: the Vatican for its part refused to recognize the Italian
state until the Lateran Treaty of 1929.) Secondly, despite the movement for
unification being more populist than its German equivalent, monarchical
power rather than power conferred by the people was still predominant.
T hirdly, regional self-interest and provincialism was still extremely strong.
When Giuseppe Garibaldi ( 1807-82) handed over the southern half of 'Italy'
to his king he was deferring to a fellow Piedmontese. Garibaldi, the 'great
Italian nationalist' , was himself born at Nice, a French citizen, and chris
tened Joseph Marie. Nice reverted to the kingdom of Piedmont in 1815.
Fourthly, Risorgimento, a literary term applied to the movement for unifi
cation, came to be commonly reserved for those like Cavour (1810-61), who
were loyal monarchists, aristocratic, elitist, cynically pragmatic and 'decently
nationalist'.56 Fifthly, though I think this is a case of pushing the thesis of
cultural invention to straining point, there was not, according to Eric
Hobsbawm, any obvious cultural continuity of symbols and practices that
the Risorgimento could draw upon to solve the problem summarized by
Massimo d' Azeglio (1798-1866) when he said, perhaps apocryphally, that,
'we have made Italy: now we must make ltalians' .57 It is certainly true that at
the time of unification from amongst a 'forest of dialects' only 2.5 per cent
of 'Italians' spoke 'ltalian'. 58
It might be objected that the previous examples of Germany and Italy are
drawn from outside the group of 'old continuous nations' (Seton-Watson's
phrase). But,�while it should be conceded that the objection has some valid
ity, more significantly for the purposes of the present discussion, Marx and
Engels treated those polities as part of their revamped version of the Hegelian
category of great historical nations. Though not as unrellectively as the King
of Italy, they implicitly wrote in quite untheorized terms of there being a
deeper continuous historical unity underlying political disunity. 59 Bloom tries
55. Ernst Kantorowicz, The King's Two Bodies, 1957; Bryan S. Turner, 'Personhood and
Citizenship', 1986, pp. 1-15.
56. Raymond Grew, 'How Success Spoiled the Risorgimento', 1967.
57. Hobsbawm, 'Mass-producing Traditions', 1983, p. 267.
58. Geoff Eley, 'Nationalism and Social History', 1981, p. 91.
59. This is not to say that 'nationality' or 'nation' were conceived in essentialist terms, nor as
an unchanging historical fact. Bloom (1941, pp. 14-15) comments that although 'Marx fre
quently spoke of nations and races as "natural" entities', the 'natural' was not used as a term of
fixity. This has a lineage which goes back to Vice's New Science where, according to Erich
Auerbach's paraphrase, he said that, 'The history of mankind, or the "world of nations" (in con
trast to the world of nature, which God created), was made by men themselves; accordingly men
themselves can know it' (Literary Language and its Public, 1965, p. 7, and 'Introduction',passim).
If this seems a very early period to be questioning the natural, it is underscored by the fact that
Vico (1668-1774) was all but ignored until a century after his death.
Marx and Engels: 'Seeing through the Veil'? 63
to explain this by pointing out that Marx and Engels implicitly distinguished
between two categories of human nature, a generic sense (human nature in
general) and a historical sense (human nature in continuous transforma
tion).60 But it just takes us further into the problem rather than offering a way
out of it.
Further to this, the objection to the choice of examples can be met by
extending their range. Similar points about intersecting levels can be made in
relation to England, the so-called first nation. 61
The land where Marx and Mazzini were exiles had a territorial integrity
and a relative continuity of effective, centralized authority, certainly going
back to the English Revolution in the seventeenth century. Going back fur
ther, in the sixteenth century during the Reformation, Catholic Christendom
was subordinated to the authority of the crown and parliament. The Roman
Church in England became the Church of England. It was also in the I 530s
that the state came to be spoken of impersonally as the locus of the political
loyalty, and owed 'next to God a natural and humble obedience'. 62 And going
back further still, in the fourteenth century Chaucer (1343?-1400), like Dante
(1265-1321) and Petrarch (1304--74), was writing in the vernacular. Despite
all this, in 1871 the monarchy continued to be politically powerful. 63 In that
year the growing republican movement flickered and died back, partly due to
the public response to an unsuccessful regicide attempt. Victoria von
Saxe-Coburg-Gotha (1819-1901), Queen of Great Britain and Ireland, later
appointed Empress of India, rose again in one of her many fluctuations of
popularity.
Victoria is interesting not just because her title 'represents emblematically
the thickened metal of a weld between nation and empire'. 64 Firstly, her blood
ties testify to the continuing national bastardy of the European dynasties.
60. Bloom, World of Nations, 1941, ch. I.
61.Nairn says of the United Kingdom that it 'was the first state-form of an industrialized
nation' (Break-up of Britain, 1981, p.14). 'Because it was the first, the English - later British -
experience remained distinct.Because they came second ...later bourgeois societies could not
repeat this early development. Their study and imitation engendered something substantially dif
ferent: the truly modern doctrine of the abstract or "impersonal" state which because of its
abstract nature could be imitated in subsequent history' (p. 17).
62.From the preamble to the 1533 Act of Appeals drafted by Thomas Cromwell
(1485?-1540), son of a Putney blacksmith, fuller of cloth, and alehouse keeper, himself a lawyer
and intellectual, who rose to be the second most powerful person in England, after Henry VIII,
that is, until he was executed for treason. Discussed in Philip Corrigan and Derek Sayer, The
Grea/ Arch, 1985, ch. 2. See also Alan G.R. Smith, The Emergence of a Nation-State, 1984.
63. Between the I870s and World War I there was a fundamental change in the basis of
British and other monarchies: an increase in publicly oriented, ostentatious ritual ironically
marked the decline of monarchical power. Similarly the Church of England moved towards
more ceremonial grandeur. See David Cannadine's documentation of the material changes and
dislocations by which 'the "preservation of anachronism", the deliberate, ceremonial presentation
of an impotent but venerated monarch as a unifying symbol of permanence and national com
munity became both possible and necessary' ('The Context, Performance and Meaning of
Ritual', 1983, quoted from p.122). See also Tom Nairn, The Enc/ranted Gian, 1988, pp. 3�7tT.
64. Anderson, /111agi111•d Comn11111ities, 1991, p. 88.
64 Nqtion Formation
Secondly, leaving aside the changing response to her husband, Albert, her
reign is indicative of the minimal but culturally contradictory concern that the
'common people' had for the nationality of their monarchs. 65 It was impor
tant that Victoria be born in the precinct of England - her pregnant Bavarian
mother-to-be was rushed aero� the Channel - but it was irrelevant whether
or not she was born of English blood. There was a greater furore over
Victoria's class-crossing dalliance with John Brown than her nuptial parading
of a German who looked like a swarthy operatic-tenor. 66
Thirdly, she represents the overlap of levels of integration: despite the pre
viously discussed, more abstract extension of social relations in the
mid-to-late nineteenth century (when social integration became mediated by
such developments as the railway and telegraph, the press, and an interna
tional circulation of commodities), we find embodied in the person of
Victoria face-to-face associations and concrete ties of blood stretching across
Europe from Balmoral to Belgium, Bavaria and Bulgaria. Victoria was the
patrilineal descendant of the (German) House of Hanover. And on her
mother's side, she was a daughter of the Bavarian House of Coburg (whence
she was related to the kings of Belgium from 1831, of Portugual from 1837 to
1910 and of Bulgaria from 1908 to 1946). Uncle Leopold (1790--1865) was the
first king of the Belgians. Wilhelm II, already discussed as one of the first
wielders of the power of publicity, was her grandchild, as was Princess Alix of
Hesse, the wife of the last Czar of Russia, Nicholas II (1868-1918). Victoria
married her cousin, Albert, Crown Prince of Prussia (1819-61). And if she
had been a man she might have also been crowned king of Hanover instead of
her Uncle Ernest. Moreover, to compound the stretch of associations,
Victoria spent a!1 increasing amount of time at Balmoral Castle, where Albert
massacred Highland deer and she came to emphasize the thin stream of
Scottish blood in her veins. She had the floors of Balmoral carpeted in tartan.
In short, calling Queen Victoria 'English' or even 'German' is inappropriate.
It is only marginally more appropriate than saying that God is an
Englishman. And yet the life of Victoria von Saxe-Coburg-Gotha was in the
middle of what Anthony Smith has called the ethnic revival. 67
65. Cf. the Constitution ofthe United States (Article 2, Section I): 'No Person except a natural
born Citizen, or a Citizen of the United States, at the time of the Adoption of this Constitution,
shall be eligible to the office of President' (1787) in Richard B. Morris, Basic Documents in
American History, 1965.
66. Certainly, we should keep in mind Bernard Guenee's point (States and Rulers in Later
Medieval Europe, 1988, p. 49) that from the beginning of the fourteenth century the possibility of
one king ruling both England and France was negligible. By the nineteenth century this incipi
ent sense of'national' difference had sharpened so that, in contrast to King George I (1714-27),
who never learnt to speak English, Albert was denied the title of king because of his foreignness.
Nevertheless my argument in relation to Victoria remains. Birth on British soil was the only sign
of her 'Englishness': face-to-face connections were elevated as the dominant source of her iden
tity in a context where face-to-face integration was subordinant.
67. Anthony D. Smith, The Ethnic Revival, 1981. Among the many monographs on Victoria
see for example Elizabeth Longford, Victoria R. l., 1966.
Marx and Engels: 'Seeing through the Veil'? 65
Using 187 I as the point of reference, examples of still-consolidating
nationhood can be drawn from far and wide. It is important that we take an
example from outside Europe. In anticipation of the later chapters on con
temporary theorists, my argument here is that in a place like Japan it was
not simply Western influence which affected the transformation to a
nation-state: changes were occurring in social form. In 1871 the Meiji
Restoration, consciously following the Hohenzollern Prussian-German
model, centralized all local, 'feudal', military units in Japan, giving Tokyo a
monopoly over the means of violence. 68 Max Weber (1864-1920) was yet to
define this monopoly as basic to the nation-state. 69 Though in quite a dis
tinct setting, some similar processes to those described for Italy, Germany
and England were at work: from the dialectic of consolidating nationaliza
tion and stretching internationalization to the overlay of levels graphically
evidenced in the intersection of the emperor as embodied, sacred represen
tative and yet mediated by a growing bureaucratic apparatus.70 To conjure
this up in an example rich in connections: the overthrow of the Tokugawa
Shogunate was a modernizing push from above, certainly influenced in part
by Western-educated intellectuals, but which restored the traditional
emperor as the essence of the national polity, or kokutai. It began as an
attempt to expel the European barbarians but ended by effecting an open
door to Western influence. It emphasized its traditional basis but imposed
national loyalty above clan loyalty. T hus in an event which was indicative of
the intersection of levels, the Emperor Meiji, as part of his ancient ritual of
ascension, read a new oath which included the principle that: 'Knowledge
shall be sought among the nations of the world.'71 T his possibility of such an
oath entails a relativization of knowledge and a rationalization of the sacred.
a changing subjective-objective practice of being-in-the-world.
One last point: it was also in 1871 that the Japanese established a depart
ment of education to begin for the first time a compulsory public school
system. Japan was in the forefront of change. In July of that year, Bismarck's
state policy of cultural-national unification, Kulturkampf, had only just
begun, paralleling a less self-conscious policy going on throughout Europe of
wresting education away from the Church and towards what Ernest Gellner
68. Anderson, Imagined Communities, 1991, pp. 95-97. While this may have in one sense
been a conscious process I tend to agree with John Breuilly's criticism of Anderson for (implic
itly) treating the Meiji Restoration as a straightforward case of 'Official Nationalism'. See
Breuilly, 'Renections', 1985, p. 72.
69. Definition from Max Weber, The Theory of Social and Economic Organi:ation, (1910 20).
I 945, p. 156.
70. Though it recognizes that there arc unique features ahout Japanese 'ultra-nationalism· this
argument is thus quite distinct from those positions which categorically distinguish betY>ecn
nationalism of the East and West. For example see John Plamenatz, 'Two Types of Nationalism'.
1973.
71. Reproduced in Arthur Tiedemann, Modem Japan, 1955, pp. 99 100. See also: Bernard
Eccleston, 'The State and Modernisation in Japan·. 1986: Kazuta Kurauchi, 'Durkheim's
lnlluence on Japanese Sociology', 1964; and Carol Gluck. Japan·s Modem Myth,, 1985.
66 Nation Formation
(Chapter 6 below) argues is the basis of the nation-state, namely, centralized
·exo-education' with generalized and generic intellectual training. 72
All that is solid melts into air •
So far, two main issues have been discussed in relation to Marx's relative
inattention to developing a theory of the nation. Firstly, I argued that Marx
was embroiled in the processes of internationalization; that he conceived of
the extension of social relations as if it were occurring only on one plane; and
that this led him to theorize capital as completely remaking the world in its
own image. Secondly, I stressed that, despite overemphasizing the single-level
dominance of internationalization, Marx remained ambiguous in his treat
ment of the historical specificity of the nation.73 It was implied that this might
have had something to do with the complexity of the nation itself. This can
now be put more directly.
Part of the basis of Marx's ambiguity was the fact that on one level the
nation appeared as primordial, and yet, in intersection with new levels of inte
grative extension, it was still in the process of consolidating even as it was
being reconstituted. Absolutist monarchy was, as we discussed earlier, an
example of a social institution formed in an earlier intersection of face-to-face
and agency-mediated relations. While being reconstituted through the six
teenth to nineteenth centuries in terms of new intersections, monarchy was all
the while an active rather than archaic. viable rather than residual, contem
porary force. 74 Monarchy was as Arno Mayer has argued a centrepiece of the
persistence of the anciens regimes. 75 This puts into perspective the paradox
72. Ernest Gellner, Nations and Nationalism, l 983, ch. 3. On Kulturkampf see GeolT Eley,
'State Formation, Nationalism and Political Culture in Nineteenth-Century Germany', 1982. On
the relationship between class and intellectual training in Germany see Derek van Abbe, Image
of a People, 1964, ch. 3. On France see Jonathan Scott, 'Inculcation or Nationalism in French
Schools after 1870', 1964. The British had only the year before passed their Education Act
(1870), elTectively to the same end. See John Lawson and Harold Silver, A Social History of
Education in England, 1973, ch. IX. In 1871 the British Religious Tests were repealed: they had
previously meant that Catholics such as Lord Acton, English baronet, later Regius Professor of
History at Cambridge, did his tertiary studies outside England. Acton's kinship ties, like
Victoria's, crossed Europe: his mother was a Bavarian countess while his father held office under
the King of Naples; an uncle was a Roman cardinal. His maternal grandfather, of Habsburg
descent, became a French citizen during the revolution, and his paternal grandfather was an
English adventurer who became prime minister of Naples.
73. This explains how writers such as Rosdolsky, '"Nonhistoric" Peoples', 1964 and 'Worker
and Fatherland' , 1965, and Joseph Petrus, ·Marx and Engels on the National Question', 1971,
could dilTer so fundamentally over whether Marx believed that capitalism and the bourgeois rev
olution were going to bring the demise of national dilTerencc.
74. This is implicitly a way of restating the terms used by Raymond Williams in his discussion
of cultural processes while retaining much of the spirit of his analysis (Marxism and Literature,
1977, ch. 8). For more historical detail on the 'transition' from monarchy to nationalism see
Reinhard Bendix, Kings or People, 1978.
75. Arno J. Mayer, The Persistence of the Old Regime, 1981, ch. 3. Mayer, however, places
more emphasis on the Schumpeterian notion of 'carry-over' than I think is viable.
Marx and Engels: 'Seeing through the Veil'? 67
that the Tudor Revolution, in investing the monarchy with the title Head of
the Church o/England, brought to it vast new power, but that concomitantly
this was in England the beginning of the end of absolute monarchism. The
change was part of the inauguration of a more abstract sense of national
place. To reassert an ongoing theme, this abstraction of an earlier sense of
place was restricted largely to the clerisy and intellectual groupings whose
outlook paradoxically was most likely to be universalistic.
In the nineteenth century the nation, formed in this setting of overlapping
levels, appeared as the natural equivalent to society. It was 'there' , underlying
changing forms of state. It was simply the association in which people lived,
an association that according to some writers (like Mazzini) needed politically
framing, and for others, such as Lord Acton (I 834-1902) who criticized
Mazzini's conception, had become an oppressive 'fictitious unity' . The nation
became an artifice, according to Acton, as soon as it was self-consciously the
orized that each nationality needed to be politically coextensive with a single
state.76 Thus even the great liberal critic of the nation, like the socialist critic,
as well as the fervent nationalist, shared the unquestioned assumption that
the nation was a pre-political, historically natural form of association going
through stages of development. In Acton's lifetime, and in his own thinking,
the assumption of a pre-political, racial, natural natio became less secure.
Acton assumed and extolled the existence of an English race of Teutonic
descent. He tersely dismissed H.T. Buckle's 1857 History of Civilization in
England for stating that 'the original distinctions of race are altogether hypo
thetic' . However, Hugh MacDougall points out that in Acton's later private
notes there is the recognition that his dearly held Teutonic myth may have
been overthrown.77
What Marx and Engels offered which went beyond this was a theory of
economic (and political) stages. They could quite consistently say that the
nation-state was, in its present form, a quite modern phenomenon with 'the
whole structure of the nation itself [depending] on the stage of development
reached by its production and its internal and external intercourse' .78 But it
was this question rather than the nation-state as a form of social integration
that remained more central to their theory.
This whole area can be approached from a complementary angle, one
through which it is intended to complicate and extend the preceding discus
sion. Marx and Engels, like their politically distant contemporaries Nietzsche,
Baudelaire, Turgenev, Verne, Dostoevsky, Monet. and even Acton and Hardy,
experienced this period-in-transition as one of upheaval. Modernity was per
ceived in varying ways as effecting a dissolution of solidity. It has
wide-reaching implications.
The second half of the present chapter develops the argument that Marx
and Engels were as intellectuals (and as persons caught in the maelstrom of
76. John Acton, Essays on Freedom and Pow,•,, 1862.
77. Hugh MacDougall, Racial Myth in English lli.<tory, 1982, ch. ,i.
78. Marx and Engels, The German ld,•ology, 1846, in St'lected Jlor>..1, vol. I. 1977, p. 21
68 Na'cion Formation
late nineteenth-century capitalism) doubly constituted in a process of disso
lution of old certainties and upheaval of prior forms of social life. The chapter
will broaden the abstraction thesis to indicate the complexity of the nexus
between subjectivity and objecti1te social relations, even for those intellectu
als who appeared outside it all. Upheaval and dissolution were reflected in
various aspects of their work from Marx's early romantic poetry to their
'mature' discussions of analytic methodology. It involved a process of what
will be called 'lifting out', the materially grounded tendency to abstract from
the particular. 79 This drive to 'discover' abstract categories such as class or
mode of production which provide a new level of unity was common in the
late nineteenth century across a diversity of intellectual fields. After drawing
examples from both literature and science, I suggest that it had the effect of
blinding them to the fact that, though the nation-state had its roots in the
structures of the 'old world', it was very much constituted by the new and
thus would not be so easily dissolved in the undoubted rush to globalize
social and economic interchange.
At the outset it is necessary to insert a word of warning. It should be
remembered that in the mid-to-late nineteenth century there were prominent
movements in art, history, theology, philosophy and science, all apparently
working in a contradictory direction to the one I have been describing. That
is, we find reassertions of continuity, certainty and solidity. In Marx and
Engels' homeland many instances can be found, from the historicism of
Leopold von Ranke (1795-1886) and his ilk which asserted the solidity of his
torical facts, 80 to the concerns of the famous Meininger theatre troupe to
reproduce the detail and reality of period dramas: actors wearing real suits of
armour exited through stage-prop doors which closed without wobbling. 81
But these reassertions, I would argue, were beginning to be just that:
reassertions. In the empiricist and positivist social and natural sciences (as in
the theatre) having to assert the verity of facts was in part a continuing con
sequence of the lifting of factuality out of what Benedict Anderson, following
Walter Benjamin, has called Messianic time, that is, time as carrying a sacred
connection between universal truth and particular historial facts. 82 This lift
ing out meant that the significance of factual detail was brought starkly into
the limelight. It was subjected to the possibility of contestation. More
far-reachingly, in the late nineteenth century it insinuated the possibility that
the grounding of factuality could itself be up for rethinking. Even classical
79.The concept of 'lifting out' is not intended to carry any vestiges of Hegel's concept of
Aujhebung.
80.On Ranke's national sensibility see Friedrich Meinecke, Cosmopolitanism and the Nation
State, (1907) 1970, ch. 12.
81.Van Abbe,('The Breakdown of 19th Century Certainty',ch.4 in Image of a People, 1964.
On the new drive for dramatic authenticity see Richard Sennett, The Fall of Public Man, 1977,
pp.26--27,174--176,202-205.
82.Walter Benjamin,Illuminations, discussed by Anderson (Imagined Communities, 1991),in
an inspiring passage talking about the changing 'apprehensions of time' (pp. 2211).
Marx and Engels: 'Seeing through the Veil'? 69
secular science had to argue increasingly for the grounding of its under
standing of the natural order. Theatre-goers were inadvertently faced with the
self-conscious experience of suspension of belief: previously the play had
largely created its own reality, but now, ironically, the new verisimilitude cast
the (disturbing) shadow that verity could only be the result of careful simu
lation. So, for many philosophers, scientists, and theatre-goers alike the real
was no longer an absolute certainty. At the very least it could be said that
reality could no longer simply be assumed. 83 Alternatively it could be argued,
and was argued by some intellectuals like Nietzsche, that reality needed to be
re-grounded.
Marx and his readers in this way became open, firstly, to the need to
develop a more secure basis for considering reality, but secondly, they became
caught up in a problematic distinction between the real and the imaginary. As
will be discussed towards the end of this section, ideologies like nationalism
were in Marx's writing often reduced to imaginary or fictitious representa
tions of the really real. Marx was able to use phrases such as the opiate of the
people, the camera obscura, the veil before our eyes, phantoms formed in the
human brain, false consciousness, and so on, phrases which even though
associated with significant theoretical problems signalled a completely new
way. 84 Little more than a decade after Marx's death, Emile Durkheim (as
discussed in the next chapter) was able similarly to revolutionize mainstream
social theory. Despite Durkheim's inheritance of Comtean positivism, and
despite (or, in another sense, because of) his intention to 'establish the foun
dations of science on solid ground and not on shifting sand' , Durkheim was
able to write that we are, as individuals, 'victims of the illusion of having our
selves created that which actually forced itself from without' . The exteriority
of social facts consisted according to Durkheim of representations and prac
tices based upon a substratum which 'can be no other than society'. 85 The
Commonsense Philosophers would continue for a long time yet to prove the
existence of reality by holding up a hand and saying that 'here is a physical
object in the external world' , 86 but elsewhere that debate had been largely
bypassed. The shell had been cracked. Even by Marx's time the phenomenal
world was at least in many of the predominant streams of intellectual thought
only an apparent dimension of reality, though of course what constituted its
83. For qualifications of this in relation to the third quarter of the nineteenth century see
Robert C. Binkley, Realism and Nationalism: 1852-1871, (1935) 1963.
84. Marx completely reworked the concept of ideology from any previous formulations. More
sophisticated in implication than his own metaphors suggest, the concept served to emphasize
that even when the increasing acuteness of contradictions exposed deliberate distortions by the
ruling classes, ideology was always a relationship between the objective and subjective (Jorge
Lorrain, The Concept of Ideology, 1979, chs 1-2).
85. Emile Durkheim, The Rules of Sociological Method, (1895) 1966, quoted from pp. 46, 5,
and 3.
86. From the much discussed paper by G.E. Moore, 'A Defense of Common Sense', 1925.
More recently see R.E. Tully, 'Moore's Defense of Common Sense: A Reappraisal After Fifty
Years', 1976.
70 Nation Formation
'real foundation' continued to be contested. And for Nietzsche,
Schopenhauer, Feuerbach, the older David Strauss, as well as Marx, all quite
different bedfellows, these dimensions were no longer held together in time by
an Absolute, beyond reality, G.od. 'God is dead.' Thus, at least, spoke
Zarathustra with relief.87
Dissolution of phenomenal certainty would, Marx and Engels believed,
force people to face a reality unencumbered by such historical constructions
as the modern nation-state:
All fixed, fast-frozen relations, with their train of ancient and venerable prejudices
and opinions, are swept away, all new ones become antiquated before they can ossify.
All that is solid melts into air, all that is holy is profaned, and man is at last compelled
to face with sober senses, his real conditions of life, and his relations with his kind...
In place of old local and national seclusion, we have intercourse in every direc
tion, universal interdependence of nations. And as in material, so also in intellectual
production. 88
This passage can be linked to the earlier suggestion I was making about the
nation-state as still in a process of consolidation. Across Europe and the world,
as we have seen, the nation as part of the changing constitutive form of social
integration had barely solidified. While the 'abstract egalitarianism of citi
zens'89 was ideologically entrenched in the treatises of intellectuals from John
Locke (1632-1704) to contemporaries of Marx and Engels, like Alexis de
Tocqueville (1805-59), it was still a radical doctrine. It was always being qual
ified and only hesitantly enacted in state policy. For Marx and Engels these
barely established changes would be consolidated by the bourgeoisie only to be
dissolved. Given this socially conditioned, theoretical logic it was unlikely that
Marx and Engels.would spend time theorizing the reasons why the nation-state
continued to rrame people's lives. In bald terms, for Marx and Engels the
nation-state in its modern form had become antiquated before it could ossify.
The passage also evidences the idea of a more fundamental reality: it is
unclear whether the connected phrase, 'relations with his kind', refers to a
more fundamental national relation or to a relation of humankind. Later
references in the Manifesto do not give us much help.90 It is indicative of the
ambiguity discussed earlier. Over and above this theme, but in uneasy relation
to it, the passage is brimming with the sense of upheaval. It is as frenetic in its
description of the 'moving chaos' as is the synaesthesic poetry of Charles
Pierre Baudelaire (1821-67).91 As Louis Dupre has argued, Marx was the first
87. Friedrich Nietzsche, Thus Spake Zarathustra, (1891-92) 1985, p. 125.
88. Marx and Engels, The Communist Manifesto (1848), in their Selected Works, vol. I, 1977,
pp.111-112. See the extended discussion of this passage in Marshall Berman, All that is Solid,
1983, passim.
89. This is Tom Nairn's phrase (Break-up of Britain, 1981, p.24). In Chapter 6 below the way
in which he uses it will be questioned.
90.For example, 'Though not in substance, yet in form, the struggle of the proletariat with the
bourgeoisie is at first a national struggle' (The Communist Manifesto, (1848) 1977, p. I 18).
91. On the connection between Marx and Baudelaire see Walter Benjamin, Charles
Baudelaire, 1973; and Berman, All that is Solid, 1983, part III.
Marx and Engels: 'Seeing through the Veil'? 71
major critic of the very processes of cultural development, including the rad
ical subjectification of the real and the fragmented character of modern
culture, processes that made his own work possible.92 I want to concentrate
now on this theme of upheaval and the relation between the subjective and
objective, filling it out by relating some of the more direct, framing influences
upon Marx's thought - 'as in material, so also in intellectual production'. It
is intended eventually to tie back into the argument concerning the abstrac
tion of social life and the intersection of levels of integrative extension.93
The nineteenth century was a time of unprecedented, generalized disloca
tion: more than even the earlier upheavals of plague. war and famine, it
challenged the sense of attachment to place. Marx and Engels were born in
Trier and Barmen, old metropolitan centres within a region which was not
only part of the core of the post-feudal economic transformations. but also
one which acutely experienced the transprovincial changes and shifts in the
form and placement of European political boundaries.94 The Rhineland. orig
inally part of the Holy Roman Empire of the German Nation. 95 was after the
Middle Ages a Stiindestaat, or 'polity of Estatcs' . 96 For a time it was incor
porated in post-revolutionary Napoleonic France, a state in transition to a
nation-state. In 1815 it was ceded to Prussia, part of a form of absolutist
Stiindestaat known as the Holy Alliance of Princes. Finally in 1871, as already
discussed, it was drawn by Bismark into a unified Germany with a Prussian
king; this was clearly an act of military and monarchical power-pragmatics
rather than the logical outcome of the end of a nationalist telos. The new
German Chancellor's biography is instructive on this point. Bismarck
(I 815-98) lived for a time in Leicester and then Scotland; he entertained the
idea of enlisting in the British Army in India. In 1862. in response to an invi
tation from the Czar to enter the Russian diplomatic corps. an offer that in
the post World War period would be considered an invitation to national trea
son, Bismarck 'courteously' declined. 97
In the case of Marx's family the experience of 'storm and stress'9K generated
92. Louis Dupre, Marx's Social Cririque of Cu/1ure, 1983.
93. Throughout the discussion it is recognized that social change is ah,ays relati\'e: it i, those
people who. for whatever reason, are lifted into an abstract overview of the long11e durt'e who are
prone to talk of cultural crisis. For example, Wolfram Eberhard ( Conqm•rors and Ru/en, I 965. p.
15) records that Chinese intellectuals of the fifteenth century had complained about the pace of
change in their lifetime. Ne\'ertheless. broad historical comparisons can still be made.
94. For a discussion of this from a focus on Trier. see Jerrold Seigel, \!ar,s Far,•. I 978, ch. 2,
part I. This book exhibits the strengths (and limitations) of the best kmd of psycholog1cal h1,
tory.
95. The expression dates from the mid-fifteenth century: Da., lwil,ge rim11ffht· Rt•ith dl'Ur,-cllt'r
Nation.
96. Here I am drawing upon the typology elaborated by Gianfranco Poggi m Th,· Dndopm<'11t
of 1/ze Madern Stare, 1978.
97. See Edward Crankshaw, Bmnarck, 1981, and l\·lorgcnthau, Po/111cJ Amot1g \a/1011.,. 19-IS,
pp. 244-245.
98. Sturm und Drang was the name of a play with theme, charactcnsuc of a htcrar; mo,cment
in Germany, 1770 82. The phrase mcrea,ed m ns currency during :\Ian·, time
72 Nci'tion Formation
quite profound responses. With Prussian control in 1815 and the restricting of
civil liberties. Heinrich and Henrietta Marx decided for pragmatic reasons to
·remake' their public identity. They severed their respective rabbinic genealo
gies and converted from JudaismJo Christianity. Henrietta Marx was further
out of place: she was born in Holland and never completely mastered the
German language.
Karl Marx was born into the period of the death and transfiguration of
German hometown society (to again use Mack Walker's phrase). It was the
period of the great German emigrations, the Auswanderung. Upheavals of
population occurred across Europe in ways unprecedented prior to the nine
teenth century. The Augsburg Allgemeine Zeitung (1816) recorded the
following words of alarm: 'In the richest and fairest parts of Europe there
rules such discontent that whole families resolve to quit their fatherland. The
spirit of restlessness and dissatisfaction is so general and so widespread that
it must have a more profound cause than human foolishness.' 99
As an intellectual, and later an exile, Marx was doubly moved by the
sweeping extensions and reformations of social life. From the vantage point
of knowing his later work it may seem surprising but in his youth Marx wrote
poetry which was influenced by the same motifs as those which intoxicated
early nineteenth-century Romanticism: the Dionysian longing for eternal flu
idity; the romantic irony of emancipation of the self by subjection to the
infinite Self. 100 When Romanticism is described with a different focus the
subjective connection between Marx's early poetry and his 'mature' project of
mapping the abstract connections between the fragments of social life
becomes more apparent. As August Wilhelm von Schlegel (l 767-1845) put it,
Romanticism involved the desire to 'soar on the wings of poetic reflection...
to abstract from every single thing, to grasp hoveringly the general, to survey
a mass, to seize the totality' . 101 Marx's poem 'The Awakening' sets the indi
vidual in a fluid state, ' yo ur beaming eye breaks' , being lifted upwards,
Upwards through the veil,
Of primeval night,
Then flash from above
Eternal Stars
Lovingly inwards102
99. Cited in �lack Walker, Germany and 1he Emigralion, 1816-/885, 1964, p. xii. Between 1871
and 1885, at least a million-and-a-half Germans emigrated, predominantly to the United States.
Contrary to commonsense, emigration was more pronounced during times of high economic
activity (p. I 81).
100. A Jess respectful Althusser would find a new 'subject' for his ideology in particular/
Ideology in general, subject/Subject distinctions.
IOI. Leonard P. Wessell, Karl Marx, Romantic Irony and 1he Prole1ariat, 1919, passim;
Schlegel quoted p. 55. While this is a useful book, it is not to say that I want to have anything to
do \\ith his overall thesis that marxism has a mythopoetic basis and is thus a 'Vital Lie'.
l02. Reproduced in full in Wessell, ibid., pp. 231-232. See also Feelings (p. 259): 'Never can I
carry out in peace/ What has seized my soul so intensely,/ Never remain comfortably quiet,/
And I storm without rest.' Note the implicit reference to 'Storm and Stress'.
Marx and Engels. 'Seeing through the Veil'.' 73
As well as the image of the stars carrying the sense of the Romantic, infinite
Self, they are depicted as flashing brightly from above a veil. It recalls the
metaphors of the older Marx, previously referred to as depicting reality as
veiled. 103 Going further into the poem, the third stanza momentarily snuffs
out the 'soul's rippling flame', and reflects the crisis of self-aggrandizement/
self-negation which Romanticism was going through at that time:
Your Awakening
Is endless rising,
Your rising,
Eternal fall.
Marx soon embarked upon a project that would leave behind the clammy,
self-negating underside of Romanticism. However, it was by the same rise and
fall, the same lifting-in-abstraction that Nietzsche took in the diverging direc
tion of a neo-nationalist nihilism, that Marx and Engels drew upon to seize
the totality and to explain it in terms of itself. They set out through a method
ology which Marx referred to as a movement from the 'abstract to the
concrete'.104 Derek Sayer in his book The Violence of Abstraction argues that:
Marx persistently relates the abstraction of social phenomena from their historical
integument - he speaks of the abstraction of the state, abstract labour, the abstract
individual, and so on, in ways that are too consistent and too frequent to be coinci·
dental - to the particular social conditions of capitalist production and the world
of fetishized appearances they sustain. Reification is for him a real process. It is.
then , the nature of bourgeois reality itself - the di.ffrepancy be/Ileen its appearance
and its reality, its real and its idealform.s - which renders a scientific analysis of such
forms necessary. 1" (emphasis added)
Part of their aim was to explain in materialist terms the structures and
processes of transformation that constituted the e;,;perience that, 'Things fall
apart; the centre cannot hold'.106 However, what limited their analysis was a
tendency to conceive of the process of abstraction as a process of the reifying
of ideas, or, in other words, the lifting of concrete processes into the realm of
fictitious phenomena. The so-called real ties of the past, according to this
103. For example sec Marx, 'Preface' to Capi1al. vol. I, 11867) 1977, p. 20, 'But they ra1,c the
veil just enough to let us catch a glim1>5C of the Medusa head behind it.·
104. Marx carefully distinguished this method from Hegel's abstract Jdeahsm, but as Seigel
reminds us, Marx later became uneasy C\'en about the ·abstract to concrete' dC!oCTlpl1on (Marx·,
Faie, 1978, p. 37t). It was left out of the 1859 'Preface· 11,h1ch replaced the 1857 mtroduct1on to
'A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy' �1arx said 'on cl�r rdkct1on an) an11c
ipat1on of results still to be prO\'ed appears to me disturbing. and the reader ,. ho on the ,. hole
desires to follow me must be resolved to ascend from the parucular to the general" ( Ma.n and
Engel s, Selu1ed Worb, vol. I, 1977, p. 502) The issue remains the Mime. Sote the metaphor of
ascension.
105. Derek Sayer, The Violence of Ab<ITaCllon, 1987, pp. 130 131
106. This phra,c was written a generation on h 1s from a poem, 'The Second Commg', com
po,cd m 1921 by a 'sporadic fascist' from Ireland. W B Yeats (1856 1939) S,gn,ficantl) •
generation further on again, Chmua Achebe cho,c tilt phra,c as the lltle for his ant1-colomahst
novel, ThingJ Fall Aparl, 1958.
74 Nation Formation
view, were being dissolved, and the person was becoming a 'fictitious phe
nomenon. In the state ...he is the imaginary member of an illusory
sovereignty, is deprived of his real individual life and endowed with an unreal
universality.' 01 7
Continuity, unity and the abstract avant-garde
This line of discussion on upheaval, dissolution and abstraction could be
taken much further in its own terms, but it is becoming clearer that for a the
orist (or a poet) to have a vantage point from which to even describe
upheaval, they have to be materially constituted at a level already removed
from that which they conceive as dissolving.It is not just that Marx was a
deracinated individual.And it is not that he was being lifted into a 'fictitious'
realm of reified ideas.The intellectual is always in quite significant ways con
stituted within the limitations of the present.And yet because intellectual
work is conducted in the main at the level of disembodied extension - that is,
for example, via the medium of the printed word which materially transcends
some of the limitations of time and space - intellectuals, perhaps more than
anyone else, are pushed to find generalized, abstract categories which connect
the vagaries of day-to-day life. This became intensified as the old verities and
the old hierarchies were dismantled.Jose Ripalda writes:
The enormous and lucid distance of Marx before the historical epoch in which he
found himself historically identified is the distance of uprooted individuality. His
reflection, at the same time that it is the result of this uprooting, reflects the activ
ity that produced it dissqlving the totalitar_ian bonds of the old precapitalist
organism. Tjlere is the radical separation of people and the means of production,
the formal separation between economic society and state, the inversion of social
relations into impersonal ones and vice-versa, and consequently the transfer of
human substance to impersonal mechanisms. Marx's radical demystification is the
same that allowed Adam Smith to identify king and priest with cooks and whores
in the same category of the unproductive class.108
Ripalda places Marx firmly within the bounds of his time, but he also
indicates the level at which Marx steps beyond it.A parallel can be found to
earlier writers like Hegel or Adam Smith (1723-90).Identifying 'king and
priest with cooks and whores', as opposed to locating them on a hierarchy of
being (itself obviously a categorical abstraction), entails a further abstrac
tion.109 Like calling Queen Victoria von Saxe-Coburg-Gotha 'Mrs Brown', it
is a move not possible within the cultural bounding of an unquestioned and
107. From 'On the Jewish Question', 1843, cited in Sayer, Violence of Abstraction, 1987, p. 104.
For a more sympathetic reading of Marx on the process of abstraction see Carol Gould's path
breaking book Marx's Social Ontology, 1972, ch. I.
108. Jose Maria Ripalda, The Divided Nation, 1977, p. !58. The paragraph concludes in a vein
that reflects the spirit of this thesis: 'Marx will belong to the past not when he is refuted ... but
when others have come to realize what he only anticipated.'
I09. Ripalda uses this notion of abstraction to great effect in some instances and in others pro
ceeds with unrealized, loose-but-brilliant assertions.
Murx and Engels: 'Seeing through the Veil'? 75
sacred Great Chain of Being. 1 JO The process of I referred to earlier as lifting
out, and which now is being broadened and referred to as abstraction, is cru
cial, I suggest, to understanding the experience of upheaval and the nature of
intellectual practice; it is fundamental to responding to the dilemma of why
there is no nineteenth-century theory of the nation, as well to explaining the
quite novel form of social relations which begin to bond a nation of strangers
in the first place.
The constitutive abstraction argument allows us to make some sense of the
paradox of continuity-in-discontinuity} 11 Earlier I said that Marx and his
contemporaries experienced the nineteenth century as a period of upheaval.
On the other hand, one of the implications of the foregoing discussion is
that through the process of abstraction a level can be 'discovered' , and lived,
at which a continuity with the past is conceived. How are these propositions
connected?
It is true to say that despite the political discontinuities of German history
described earlier there was a sense of abstract continuity across time and
place being perceived in some quarters of intellectual life such as in German
historiography. It was a cultural continuity which went beyond that of the
province or borough. This was so as early as the new humanism of the fif.
teenth. and sixteenth centuries. In turn, certainly by the 1500s, intellectuals
could refer back to the recently unearthed manuscript by the Roman writer,
Publius Tacitus (AD 55--c.120)_1 12 However, perceiving this continuity which
linked some of the tribes of the Roman Empire to the principalities of the
Second Reich as a national history entailed a lift in the level of abstrnction
beyond that of the face-to-face or the agency-extended. I will expand upon
this by way of an example in a moment, but the point is that conceiving of
such a continuity entailed a mode of apprehending the world, discontinuous
with past modes. Moreover there were discontinuous ways of conceiving of
continuity: the Renaissance humanists, some of whom began to speak highly
of a German character, range from Brant (c.1458-1521), Wimpfeling
(1450-1528) and Desiderius Erasmus (1466-1536) to the bathetic chronicler
who traced the connection between the Vestal Virgin and the Westphalian
nuns, 113 but they can be compared as a group to Hegel or Justus Moser, and
contrasted even more starkly with Marx. The linking of cultural with legal
and institutional history such as in Moser's proto-historicism (discussed in
Chapter 2) required a qualitative intellectual upheaval, a paradigm shift in
subjectivity, and Marx took this even further.
110. Arthur 0. Lovejoy (The Great Chain of Being, 1936) shows how the 'idea' stretched
from Greek philosophy to the eighteenth century.
l l l. It is not a new problem. Corrigan and Sayer describe it as the 'dialectic of continuity and
change' (The Greal Arch, 1985,p. 201).
l 12. Germania written c.20. Marx and Engels often refer to Tacitus' writmgs on the 'ancient
tribes of Germany'. See particularly Engels, The Origin of /he Fami�\', Pri1•a1e Propal)' and /he
S1a1e, (1884), in Marx and Engels, Selected Works, vol. J,1977, pp. 37,46, 56,125,172 181.
113. A.G. Dickens, The German Na1ion a11d Marlin Lu1her, 1974, ch. 2, 'Humanism and the
National Myth'; Boyd Shafer, Na1io11ulism: Myth and Rn1/i1y, 1955. pp. 87ff.
76 Nation Formation
A further response can be posted which runs parallel with the earlier recog
nition that upheaval was accompanied by assertions of a new solidity in
various quarters from positivism to the performing arts. By the early nine
teenth century those who most.ardently summoned the continuity of the
Volksgeist were the self-conscious inheritors of the spirit of discontinuity,
that of Sturm und Drang. The now commonplace saying, 'the more things
change, the more they stay the same', was carefully drafted by a now largely
forgotten writer in the months that followed the publication of the Communist
Manifesto. 114 Similarly, for a significant -number of nineteenth-century
German intellectuals, anarchic individualism was seen to be complemented
by total community. 115
Hegel provides us with an apposite example of the paradox of continuity
in-discontinuity. The Hegelian dialectic is an attempt to theorize just such a
paradox. It does so through a dexterous but inconsistent juggling of the exis
tential and ideal, where all existence is (supposedly) moved by the dialectic of
continuous-discontinuous change. Simkhovitch writes that Hegel 'makes
chemical processes testify to the "truth" of his conception; he causes stones to
cry aloud, and the flowers that bloom in spring crown the dialectic glory'. 116
All existence is moved by the dialectic process, that is, significantly, all exis
tence except the realization of the State. Hegel, official Prussian
Restaurationsphilosoph, believed that the State is the way of God and the
realization of Reason. As Simkhovitch put it, 'The Universal Spirit, which is
so dialectically brisk elsewhere, seems to be quiescent in its capacity as
Volksgeist' . 117
The nation-state formed in the intersection of levels thus becomes for
Hegel the concrete embodiment of the totality of past history and the social
order of the present (Sittlichkeit). Marx, writing later, is able to find a way of
synthesizing the continuity-in-discontinuity at a level which for reasons
argued earlier can, paradoxically, by being more abstract than Hegel's
idealist universalism, criticize his form of approach as confirming the 'cultus
of abstract man'. 118 But while Marx and Engels dismissed the immanent
force of the national Volksgeist they took for granted the historical force of
the nation-state. The passage about to be quoted from Engels' early writings
shows how the continuity is assumed while an idealist way of perceiving
that continuity is criticized. Keep in mind that except for the analysis of the
commodity and labour abstraction Marx and Engels themselves tended to
114. Alphonse Karr (1808-90), Les Guepes, January 1849, cited in John Bartlett, Familiar
Quotations, (I 882) 1977. Charles Tilly suggests that the writer was Talleyrand (personal com
munication July 1991).
115. Hans Kohn, Prelude to Nation-States, 1967, p. 170.
116. Vladimir G. Simkhovitch, 'Approaches to History: 3', 1932, p. 429. On the internal
antinomies of Hegel's work on the Volksgeist see Georg Lukacs, History and Class Consciousness,
1922, pp. 146--149 particularly.
117. Ibid. This is not to say that Hegel was an 'ardent nationalist': see Shlomo Avineri,
Hegel's Theory of the Modern State, 1972, ch. 3.
118. Marx, Capital, (1867) 1977, p. 83.
Marx and Engels: 'Seeing through the Veil'? 77
treat abstraction in the Hegelian sense as a process only occurring in the
realms of ideas. Their approach on this issue, however critical, is out of the
lineage of Auguste Comte (1798-1857) and his three stages of history: (I)
theological or fictitious; (2) metaphysical or abstract; (3) scientific or posi
tive. Engels writes:
The Germanising trend was negation, abstraction in the Hegelian sense. It created
abstract Germans by stripping off everything that had not descended from national
roots over sixty-four purely German generations. Even its seemingly positive fea
tures were negative, for Germany could only be led towards its ideals by negating a
whole century and her development and thus its intention was to push the nation
back into the German Middle Ages. 119
Marx and Engels, at least in their capacity of being intellectuals, worked at
a level which was abstract in relation to the practice and discourse of people
whose lives were dominated by the relative constraints of the day-to-day.
Marx and Engels were not even representative of contemporary intellectuals
qua intellectuals. However, the direction of their work generated a resonance
among many of their contemporaries. It was in fact representative of a drive
within a diversity of fields to discover abstract categories or categorizations,
to theorize a new level of unity which could be said to underlay (or overlay,
depending upon the chosen metaphor) the phenomenal world. To indicate the
breadth of this drive I would like to cite two examples, one from science and
one from literature.
In 1871, Dimitri Mendeleyev (1834--1907) presented a paper which delin
eated his most developed formulation of what was to be received as the
pre-eminent schema of a unitary, abstract totality devised in chemistry up to
the end of the nineteenth century. It was an eight-column schema which
connected all the elements of the natural world and was called the periodic
table of atomic elements. 120 The point being made here as with the other
examples is only highlighted by and not dependent upon the fact that it is
drawn from the year 1871. This 'invention' was continuous with the past
and at the same time part of a specific disjunction from its precursors.
Mendeleyev's table took the dominant mode of inquiry, modern science in all
its universalizing, regularizing splendour, to its limit. It was a limit which was
not anticipated by Isaac Newton (1642-1727) in his exemplary work on the
logic of order in the Principia. Similarly, the famous Second Law of
Thermodynamics -- entropy always increases in any closed system not in
119. Engels, 'Ernst Moritz Arndt' (1841) in Marx and Engels, Collected Works, vol. �.
p. 140-141. See also Marx, The German Ideology , in Marx and Engels, Selected llorks, vol. I.
1977, pp.39,49, 76.
120. See Geoff Sharp 'Constitutive Abstraction', 1985. where he uses the eumple of the peri
odic table to draw attention to the way in which the practical cross-conte,tuality of the
intellectual mode makes possible the building of interpretative models (p. 64 and pp. 48 82 pas
sim). Cross-contextuality or the bisociation of different frames of reference is the subject and
theoretical base of Arthur Koestler's book The Act of Creation, 1964 With much insight. though
none of it critical or polit,cally sensitive. Koestler attempts a theory to e,pla,n crea11v1ty rangmg
across the basis of laughter and the aesthetic e,perience to the proce" of sc1enttfic 1nvent1on.
78 Natjon Formation
equilibrium - was a modern law of universalism which was part of the tran
sition to a science abstracting from an already abstract, long-run ideology of
universal regularity.121
In literature a similar point can be made, but it is a little more complicated
because the abstract unity of th; novel is not one of the foremost intentions
of the author. In George Eliot's Middlemarch (published in December 1871),
the textual form is of barely interacting central characters living out their sep
arate lives as described in widely diffused narratives. There is little effort to tie
these characters together: they meet at funerals and marriages. Still there is a
powerful sense of unity. As one critic contends it is a unity not of place, but
of 'moral scene' .122 The method of writing allows the author and thus the
reader to be everywhere as the 'centred subject of her own decentred fic
tion' .123 This depends on a change in the form of subjectivity, and, as Benedict
Anderson has argued relevant to the rise of the nation, this changed subjec
tivity includes a changed sense of simultaneity. Homogeneous empty time
(Benjamin's phrase)- where simultaneity is 'transverse cross-time, marked not
by prefiguring and fulfilment, but by temporal coincidence and measured by
clock and calendar'124 - comes to overlay and, in a long-run transformation,
to largely reconstitute what was earlier referred to as Messianic or traditional
time.
Let me restate the proposition with a different slant. Intellectual works, as
apparently unrelated as Capital, Middlemarch and the Periodic Table of the
Elements, were produced within a common constitutive form, and yet they
were not necessarily representative of the overtly dominant ideologies of the
period. This is not to dispute Eagleton's (1978) comment that 'George Eliot
delineates a "spa_ce" constituted by the insertion of "pastoral", religious and
Romantic ide'Ological sub-ensembles into an ideological formation domi
nated by liberalism, scientific rationalism and empiricism' .125 Quite the
opposite. But it is an attempt to have something to say about the form, and
not just textual form, through which such contradictory ideologies are
brought together. It tries to go further than Eagleton's jumbled conclusion
that 'This contradictory unity of ideological structures provides the produc
tive matrix of her fiction; yet the ideology of her texts is not, of course,
reducible to it. For Eliot's literary production must be situated, not only at the
121. It is interesting to note that Ernest Gellner's theory of the nation 'reflects' the Second
Law of Thermodynamics in arguing that nation-states arise out of 'entropy-resistant traits' as
structure is supposedly replaced by an 'internally random and fluid totality' (Nations and
Nationalism, 1983, p. 63, and ch. 6, passim). See also the discussion in Zygmunt Bauman's
Culture as Praxis, 1973, pp. 58-67. For marxist examples of drawing explanatory analogies from
science and the Second Law of Thermodynamics see Nikolai Bukharin, Historical Materialism,
1921; or more recently Debray, 'Marxism and the National Question', 1977.
122. Mark Schorer, 'The Structure of the Novel', 1967.
123. Terry Eagleton, Criticism and Ideology, 1978, p. 120. He indicates that the web, a natural
and organicist metaphor of complex fragility, is one of the central images of the novel.
124. Anderson, Imagined Communities, 1991, p. 24.
125. Eagleton, Criticism and Ideology, 1978, p. 112.
Marx and Engels: 'Seeing through the Veil'? 79
level of '·general" ideology , but also at the relatively autonomous level of the
mutation of literary forms.' 126 I do not want to return to the orthodox model
of determinism, nor reject the constant possibility of contingent outcomes,
but on the other hand, though I agree with the tenor of Eagleton's final para
graphs, his talk of a 'certain curvature in the ideological space in which texts
play' 127 is hardly a great leap forward in literary or social theory. In terms of
the present argument, those people, in this case theorists, novelists or scien
tists, who are trained (always within the terms of their society's dominant
configuration of levels of integration) to operate on the boundaries of exist
ing discourse and practice, work on a level which allows them to abstract
from that society. 128 This is overdetermined by multifarious processes, some of
which have already been discussed, including the extension of social rela
tions sustained by print-capitalism.
It can be linked to the continuity-in-discontinuity proposition. For exam
ple, for Rousseau (1712-78) to explain the foundations of his new society and
advocating the establishment of self-conscious political nations 129 required
that he abstract from the socio-cultural qualities of mankind. In his words,
it required that he 'strip this being, thus constituted' to arrive at our 'natural
foundations' . Rousseau was able fleetingly to muse that this was a state
which 'perhaps never did exist'. 130 Significantly , however, he never explored
the implications of such a statement. 131 It is hard to see how, given the cul
tural conditions of his time, this would have been likely. Even if any such
analytic move is made possible by the relationship-in-general of intellectuals
to their society - it goes back at least to Plato's use of the image of the shad
ows on the cave wall to argue for philosophers being the keepers of their
state - it is however constrained by the particularity of circumstances of the
time.
Because the experience of being lifted upwards through the veil is condi
tioned by material influences with overlapping and long-run cultural histories
it is easy to see why it is necessary to talk of continuity-in-discontinuity. From
Rousseau's to Marx's century there was the developing and self-conscious
126. Ibid., p. 113, emphasis added.
127. Ibid., p. 180.
128. It is those people who have pushed against boundaries and been able to draw connections
between levels of constitutive being from the most concrete to, within contemporary limita
tions, the most abstract that, alongside the princes of political pol'.er. have been given a
significant place in what we still conventionally call 'history'. But that is a different story.
129. Anne Cohler, Rousseau and Nationalism, 1970.
130. Jean-Jacques Rousseau cited in Irving Zciiland. ldenlogy and the Dere/opm,•n/ of
Sodo/ogica/ Theory, 1968, pp. 24--25. See also F.M. Barnard. 'National Culture and Poliucal
Legitimacy: Herder and Rousseau', 1983.
131. It would be interesting at another time to trace the history of the notion of the original
condition. From the Book of Genesis and the 'Epic of Gilgamesh' through Rousseau's 'Origin of
Inequality ', to the ambiguous status of Freud's primal-horde my th and then to John Rawls'
abstract conception of an 'Original Position' (see his A Th,•ory ofJ11.11ice, 1972) there are strik
ing qualitative changes, with each becoming progressively more abstract.
80 Nation Formation
post-patronage abstraction of the writer, litterateur and artist. 132 For
Tocqueville in Marx's time, or Montesquieu (1689-1755) in Rousseau's, it was
travel which they singled out as facilitating their sense of 'looking down from
above' . 133 Marx and Mazziiji, and going back further, Machiavelli
(1469-1527), Petrarch and Dante, were all exiles from their native locales.
With Marx, as I have argued, the abstraction was further intensified. Marx's
century began with the discovery of the Wild Child of Aveyron and by its end
was overtaken by various rethinkings of human nature exemplified in
Darwinism and Freudianism. Marx's approach as evinced in the concept of
'species being' was in one sense continuous with the limitations and openings
of the Rousseauian stripping away of content. But he moved past Rousseau
and took the faltering eighteenth-century critique of religious-based essen
tialism to a new level. 134
In summary, it has been argued that Marx was pushed by both his constitu
tive medium and by the form of his intellectual practice to search for 'deeper'
or 'higher' , more abstract categories of explanation. T his proposition I argue
adds to an understanding of how the nation could be taken for granted as an
historically natural form of association, and, at the same time, be conceived
as passing into history, melting into air. 135 In the first chapter I suggested that
despite all of its discontinuities the modem nation is subjectively experienced
as a community of known strangers bound within a specifiable time and
space continuity. If it is right to say that the nation is experienced as a con
crete and condensed relation between real people (despite the fact that they
never meet as-a-community except via materially abstracted, extended rela
tions), then Marx's seeing through the veil of this subjectivity was a profound
insight. But it had for Marx the effect of blinding him to the fact that the
national subjectivity of the concrete, drawing upon the ontological level of the
face-to-face, was integral to the intersection of more abstract levels of social
integration. With the realization that this subjectivity could be seen through,
the contemporary precariousness of the national form (even before it had
solidified) could not help but come to the fore. But without something like a
132. Even the history of such words as 'art' and 'artist' throws light on the change. It was in
the late eighteenth century that a generalized distinction was for the first time drawn between
artist and artisan - the former said to have a higher 'intellectual' or 'imaginative' purpose. See
Raymond Williams, Keyll'ords, 1976, pp. 32-35.
133. This is Konrad Burdoch's metaphor summarizing Petrarch's literary sense of 'Italia
Mia'. See Kohn, Idea of Nationalism, (1944) 1956, pp. 97-98, 600-601.
134. This is still largely in agreement with Norman Geras in Marx and Human Nature, 1983.
135. Keep in mind that Marx's use of the term 'natural' is always ambiguous; it is not an
immutable or God-given essence. Marx at one stage was taken with the theories of the French
scientist, PierreTremaux. In a book published in 1867,Tremaux suggested that racial differences
were produced by variations in geological settings. Bloom notes that: 'Without distinguishing
between race and nationality, Marx commented that "for certain questions, like nationality,
etc., it is here alone that we may find the natural basis "' (The World of Nations, 1941, p. 15).
Marx and Engels: ·seeing 1hrough the Veil'? 81
theory of levels it had the double effect of ambiguously leaving the national
form hanging in its relatively taken-for-granted, relatively untheorized obvi
ousness, and yet highlighting the novel qualities ofthe modern slate in which,
according to the comment earlier cited from Marx, citizens are 'imaginary
member(s) ofan illusory sovereignty'.
On the other hand, the nation could not be written off as simply an ideo
logical phantom perpetrated by the leading national class. Marx and Engels
were too aware ofthe vagaries ofhistory and the exigencies ofcontemporary
politics to do that. The doctrine of historyless peoples became an inade
quate but logical way of bypassing this tension. From this side of the
contradiction the nation was implicitly treated as the post-tribal, transhis
torical name for associations between people. 'Nation' and 'society' were
interchangeable terms. Either way, the nation disappeared into its own
prominence.
Instead of theorizing the constitutive levels which in intersection provide
the subjective force of national formations, Marx and Engels - working as I
have indicated at a level ofabstraction which allowed them to 'strip this being
thus constituted' - set themselves in Engels' phrase to 'discover the law of
development ofhuman history'.136 They were able to analyse history in terms
ofan abstract analytic categorization ofthe structural relations ofpersons liv
ing and working within the determinations ofspecific modes ofproduction:
namely, class relations. Class provided the missing (abstract) category through
which post-tribal history could be both unified and taken apart. Their theory
got to the point ofalluding to the fact that it was the mode ofproduction and
its associated leading class which gave form to the nation in history. But
that was the stumbling point. Just as extension was theorized as occurring
along a single plane (the flattening out ofthe constitutive levels oftime and
associations-with-place were examples discussed earlier), the implications for
social being, highlighted by a theory which talks of constitutive levels, were
never realized.
Because of the milieu in which Marx and Engels worked, a number of
themes dominated their analysis: world history as progressive stages of
upheaval, capitalism as the predominant economic form globalizing human
existence, and class as the basic (abstract) category ofsocial relations. Thus
the extensions and abstractions ofsocial relations were conceived as occur
ring on one plane. The word 'plane' is used in distinction to the notion of
'levels' to indicate that such a conception involves the collapsing of levels
into each other, not simply the forgetting that there are various levels of
social existence that can be analytically distinguished. For though Marx
was brilliant enough to work beyond the limitations ofhis own position. it
was not a matter of forgetting but of having no realizable way of going a fur
ther synthetic step. It was not just, as Nairn has implied, that Marx was
136. Engels, 'Speech at the graveside of Karl Marx' ( 1883). in Marx and Engels, 1977, .'>rl,·ctrcl
Works, vol. I. p. 162.
82 Ntttion Formation
unable to 'foresee the real contradictions of Progress'. The limitations were
fundamental and historically framed ones related to the theorizing of social
form. They were not simply lack of prescient knowledge of the content of
future history. These continuiQg limitations left marxism, for the most part,
stumbling around in the glare of its own insight. unable to conceive of a
political practice which could be enacted except on a single constitutive
plane.
4
Durkheim and Weber: The Antinomies of
Abstract Nationalism
A nationality is a group of human beings, who for ethnica[I), or perhaps
merely for historical reasons desire to live under the same laws, and to
form a single State, large or small as it may be; and it is now a recognized
principle among civilized peoples that, when this common desire has
been persistently affirmed, it commands respect, and is indeed the only
solid basis of a State.
Emile Durkheim, 'Germany Above Alf':
German Mentality and the War, 1915
If the concept of 'nation' can in any way be defined unambiguously, it
certainly cannot be stated in terms of empirical qualities common to
those who count as members of the nation. In the sense of those using the
term at a given time, the concept undoubtedly means, above all, that one
may exact from certain groups of men a specific sentiment of solidarity in
the face of other groups. Thus, the concept belongs in the sphere of val
ues.
Max Weber, The Theory of Social and Economic Organi:ation, 1921
Neither Durkheim nor Weber, nor any of their contemporaries associated
with the nascent fields of sociology and political science, Simmel, Tonnies,
Pareto, Mosca or Cooley, developed anything approaching what we might
call a theory of the nation. 1 This chapter examines some of the reasons why,
a generation after Marx and Engels, and at a time when it was clear that in
the foreseeable future the nation was not going to fade away, there was a con
tinuing poverty of theory in this area.
Certainly in selected quarters, conceptions of the naturalness and
immutability of the nation-state were beginning to be challenged. and many
traditions were being pressed by an urgency of debate. Second-International
marxism was broadening its terms of enquiry. Through Bauer, Kautsky.
Lenin, Stalin and others, it was beginning, even if in problematic ways. to go
I. Robert Michels (1876---1936)) might be considered a limited exception to this generalization
with the publication in 1917 of Notes sur /es Mo yens de Constater la Nationahte and in 1929 of
his study Der Patriotismus. However, his theorizing still had the quality of simply enumerating
the 'components of the Fatherland concept', with, in the final analysis, a deferent bow to Ernest
Renan·s (1832-92) concept of a 'community of will' as subordinating all other components. See
Michels' First Lectures in Political SocioloKy, (1927) 1965, ch. VIII, 'Patriotism'.
84 Nation Formation
beyond treating national formation as on the one hand a historical given
and, on the other hand, a narrowly political question. 2 Anarchists such as
Kropotkin and Redus working outside institutional settings were defying
the nationalist assumptions oCthe new academic social sciences, particularly
of geography3 and history.4 Concurrently, even though many mainstream his
torical studies continued until well after World War I to be premised on the
natural or morally logical basis of the progression from tribe to nation, his
torians of ideas such as Meinecke, Muir, Oakesmith and Rose were at least
beginning to give direct attention to chronicling the complexities of the nation
in history. 5 Yet in classical sociology, a discipline which was opening up so
many areas of social relations either to the first light of abstract secular
enquiry or to the second light of painstaking recension, almost no work was
being done on theorizing the processes of national formation. It was not that
social theory was being left behind by a handful of insightful historians, but
rather that given the work of social theory in other areas it seems strange that
social theorists were giving no lead in this one. While they were interested in
history, the early social theorists in general did not think highly of the work
of historians: in Herbert Spencer's words, 'The highest office which the his
torian can discharge is that of so narrating the lives of nations, as to furnish
materials for Comparative Sociology. ' 6
By comparison with how they treated the question of the nation, the clas
sical social theorists treated religion - the taken-for-granted ethos of an earlier
period and still commanding considerable dominion - as one of many social
phenomena that 'are covered by a veil that we must first remove if we are to
get at them and bring them to light' . 7 On occasion, nationalism came to be
called the new. religion. And nationality was unveiled as a social fact rather
than a social essence. However, there was no analysis of the national form
even distantly comparable to Max Weber's or Emile Durkheim's analyses of
2. Ephraim Nimni, 'Great Historical Failure: Marxist Theories of Nationalism', 1985.
3. Jim Maclaughlin, 'State-Centred Social Science and the Anarchist Critique', 1986.
4. On the nationalism of the German neo-Rankeans see John Moses, The Politics of Illusion,
1975.
5. Friedrich Meinecke (1862-1954), Cosmopolitanism and the Nation State, 1907; Ramsay
Muir (1872-1941), Nationalism and Internationalism, 1916; John O akesmith, Race and
Nationality, I 9 I 9; and J. Holland Rose (1855-1942), Nationality as a Factor in Modern History,
1916. After a detailed history and a short but convincing critique of the racialist,
language-based and Hegelian 'World-Spirit' theories of the nation, Rose however can do no
better than to say that nationality 'is an instinct, and cannot be exactly defined; it is the recog
nition as kinsmen of those who were deemed strangers; it is the apotheosis of family feeling,
and begets a resolve never again to separate; it leads to the founding of a polity on a natural
basis.' (1916, pp. 152-153). For a sense of the range of studies of the nation written in the
pre-war period, see Carlton Hayes' 'Bibliographical Note' at the end of his Essays on
Nationalism, (1926) 1966.
6. Cited in Peter Burke, Sociology and History, 1980, p. 19.
7. Emile Durkheim, Montesquieu and Rousseau, (1892) 1965, p. 62. Weber is also fond of the
veil metaphor, and recall Marx's use of the same image, quoted and discussed in Chapter 3, pp.
69, 73, 80, above.
Durkheim and Weber: Antinomies of Abstract Nationalism 85
religion, respectively in The Protestant Ethic (1904-5) and The Elementary
Forms of Religious Life (1912).
What were the theoretical and material constraints engendering such a
continuing limitation of theory? As was discussed in relation to the late nine
teenth century, the necessity of theorizing the nation was in part obviated by
the very prominence of the category of the nation, but by the beginning of the
twentieth century this was complicated by an often intense advocacy for the
moral primacy of the national interest. It seems as we look back from the late
twentieth century that Hegel's aphorism that the owl of Minerva flies at twi
light is still apposite. Examining this question of the continuing limitation of
theory is intended to take us through a descriptive history of ideas and
beyond the tendency of such a description to over-accentuate the role of the
oretical heritage. It entails looking at issues which bear upon the relation
between intellectual work across the turn of the century and the form of the
nation during that period. 8 In the previous chapter, the focus was the world in
which Marx lived, drawing examples from the year 187I. The subject of the
present chapter is 'mainstream' social theory during the decades up to and
including World War I. The chapter develops lines of examination begun in
the earlier chapters, and hence assumes that the various aspects of the con
stitutive abstraction argument do not require quite as detailed an exposition
of their relevance for understanding Durkheim and Weber.
In relation to the continuing poverty of theory it mattered little which
overt methodological pathway the classical sociologists took. Emile
Durkheim (1858-1917) emphasized the collective basis of subjectivity and
social practice, whereas Max Weber (1864-1920) was ultimately a proponent
of methodological individualism. 9 Georg Simmel (1858-1918) and Charles
Cooley (1864-1929) made their overriding concerns the 'meaningful forms of
sociation' , centring on relationships in face-to-face interaction and group
affiliation rather than on abstract, extended communities such as the nation; 10
whereas Gaetano Mosca (1858-1941) was interested in the theory and prac
tice of larger political structures. None of these theorists spent more than a
few paragraphs on theorizing the nation. Likewise, it made little difference
which political leanings each of the classical theorists espoused: Weber was a
conservative liberal-nationalist and an early member of the Pan German
League; Ferdinand Tonnies (1855-1936) was a kind of socialist; Vilfredo
Pareto (I848-1923) accepted nomination shortly before his death as a sena-
8. For some beginnings in this area, see Anthony Smith, 'Ethnocentrism, Nationalism and
Social Change', 1972; and his 'Nationalism and Classical Social Theory', 1983.
9. J. Agassi, 'Methodological Individualism', 1960.
10. This is not to suggest that they have nothing to say about extended communities. Simmel,
for example, writes: 'The characteristics of the large group can, to a considernblc e.,tent, be
explained as surrogates for the personal and immediate cohesion typical of the small group. The
large group creates organs which channel and mediate the interactions of its members and thus
operate as the vehicles of a societal unity.... They are the abstract form of group cohesion whose
concrete form can no longer exist after the group has reached a certain size.' From Tire Sacialof{y
of Georg Simme/ ( 1902-7) 1950, p. 96 (emphasis added).
86 Nntion Formation
tor in Italy's new Fascist government. None of these theorists who were to be
the progenitors of mainstream sociology, social theory and political science
was able to pose the question as to why it was nations administered by insti
tutions of state (and empire) that were becoming, at least in the capitalist
West, the pre-eminent, extended social form constitutive of cultural identity.
World War I partly changed this Iacuna. 11 The classical sociologists were
deeply affected by the carnage; it was the first war in history to totalize
involvement by the citizenry, dragging in non-combatants including those
from the so-called ivory tower. However, although they became involved in
the politics of patriotism, 12 the classical theorists were not prompted to follow
up substantially the question of why during this war, and particularly in its
early stages, were so many millions of people willingly prepared to die in the
name of their nation. Theorists remained content with continuing the sort of
descriptive, ahistorical part-truths that they had forwarded, however pre
sciently, before 1914: 'Wars, in quickening the sense of patriotism,
subordinate preoccupation with the self. The image of the threatened father
land occupies a place in one's consciousness that it does not have in peace
time.'13
Undeveloped theories of the nation were projected. Simmel in his discovery
of the integrative forces of conflict says that 'Essentially, France owes the con
sciousness of its national unity only to its fight against the English, and only
the Moorish war made the Spanish regions into one people'. 14 But, like
Tennies' explanation that 'it is through the merchants that the technical con
ditions for the national union of independent individuals and for capitalist
production are created', 15 such direct comments were usually oddments. They
only occasionally surfaced out of analyses that were permeated by the nation
as one of their implicit framing categories. Much more relevant to the
quandary of the nation of strangers was Simmel's work on the city of
strangers. It is tempting then to reduce the problem of preclusion to the lim
itations of an unacknowledged kind of methodological nationalism, that is, to
a tendency to equate society with nation. 16 However, we have to be clear
about the complexities of this.
It was not that the classical sociologists completely lacked awareness of the
increasing centrality of the nation and nation-state in bounding social life.
Gaetano Mosca was characteristic in suggesting that nationalism was replac
ing religion 'as the chief factor of moral and intellectual cohesion within the
various countries of Europe'. He says:
11. However, see Carlton Hayes, 'The War of Nations', I 914, a review essay of the 'pseudo
scientific obscurantism ...from the minds of the so-called intellectual classes of all nations'.
12. Durkheim, for example, wrote political pamphlets during the war including, 'Germany
Above All', 1915 and (with E. Dennis) Who Wanted War?, 1915.
13. Emile Durkheim, Moral Education, (1902-3) 1973, p. 68.
14. Georg Simmel, Conflict and the Web of Group-Affiliations. (1908) 1955, p. 100.
15. Ferdinand Tonnies, Community and Society, (1887) 1963, p. 225.
16. See Anthony D. Smith, Theories of Nationalism, 1983; and Zygrnunt Bauman, Culture as
Praxis, 1973, pp.78-79.
i
Durkheim and Weber. Anrinomies of Abstract Nationalsm 87
It satisfies, finally, a yearning of the human soul to love the group to which it
belongs above all other groups ...Unfortunately, love of country, and a natural
desire that one's country should make its innuence more and more felt in the world,
often goes hand in hand with diffidence toward other countries and sometimes with
hatred of them. The over-excitation of these patriotic sentiments undoubtedly
helped to create the moral and intellectual atmosphere that brought on the World
War.71
Secondly, it cannot be said that all the classical theorists were oblivious to
the limitations of their theorizing. Weber, for example, indicates a partial
recognition of his lack of direct attention to theorizing the nation when at one
point he writes:
In the face of these value concepts of the 'idea of the nation', which empirically are
entirely ambiguous, a sociological typology would have to analyse all sorts of com
munity sentiments of solidarity in their genetic conditions and in the consequences
for the concerted action of the participants.This cannot be attempted here.81
Weber never did attempt such a project.And it may well be that subsequent
attempts to take up his challenge and approach the theory of the nation
through typologies, taxonomies and indices of the ideal-type helped carry on
the poverty of theory.19 However, though Weber's comment does not go
beyond recognizing the enormity of the task, he clearly was aware that there
was more to be done.
Thirdly, we can even find instances when the classical sociologists were
partially and momentarily aware of their tendency to treat an untheorized
category as the basis of their discussions of society. Mosca is disarmingly
candid about it: the theorist, he says, 'has to look objectively upon national
ities ... treating them merely as a phenomenon of the human mind. But the
precept is more easily given to others than applied by one's self.' 20
Moreover, it is not that it is impossible to reconstruct a theory of the
nation from their broader writings. Ernest Gellner's work over the last twenty
years (examined in Chapter 6) is a case in point. It developed, with critical
17. Gaetano Mosca, The Ruling Class, (1896, 1923 edition) 1965, p. 482.
18. Max Weber, From Max Weber, (essays from 1904-20), 1968, pp. 175-176. H.H. Gerth and
C. Wright Mills, editors of this selection, suggest that notes written in the margins of the manu
script or Economy and Society 'indicate that Weber intended to deal with the idea and
development or the national state throughout history' (p. 448).
19. In initiating this tradition we can include Max Sylvius Handman, 'The Sentiment or
Nationalism' , 1921; and Louis Wirth's seminal essay, 'Types or Nationalism', 1936. I do not
mean to be overly critical or these writers. They were doing more than most of their contempo
raries.
20. Mosca, The Ruling Class, 1965, p. 41. Ironically, in the very next paragraph he implicitly
equates 'society' and 'nation'. Similarly, Durkheim and Dennis ( Who Wanted War?, 1915, p. 5)
write that, 'We, and our readers in particular must therefore be on guard against the possible
influence of a national partiality, however natural it may be' . They still manage to conclude that
their native France was right, Germany wrong: 'The guilt of Germany stands out in strong
relief. Everything proves it and nothing either weakens or attenuates it' (p. 60). In this they were
no different from Gustave Le Bon, Tire Psychology uf the Great War, 1916. Compare the very
careful ambiguity in Sigmund Freud, 'Thoughts for the Times on War and Death' (1915).
88 Nation Formmion
divergences, out of the Weberian-Durkheimian lineage,21 as did the work of
others such as Anthony Smith and Liah Greenfeld. 22
In the following discussion, the work and life of two of the most prominent
classical social theorists, Du'1cheim and Weber, provide the dual centres of
focus for attempting to take these introductory comments a little further.
Durkheim and Weber are singled out both because of their prominence and
because they develop general theories of social forms. After a biographical
note, written with reference to how they treated national integration as a
moral or political imperative, the discussion elaborates the bearing of their
respective methodologies upon the national question. In the previous chapter
considerable space was given over to exploring the way in which Marx's
approach to understanding the nation was limited by a tendency to treat
questions of social relations as if they were couched on one plane. While it
would be unnecessarily repetitive to show in a detailed way how neither
Durkheim nor Weber manage adequately to overcome this problem, that
theme nevertheless remains as an undercurrent, surfacing occasionally.
Overall, the chapter contextualizes the writings of Durkheim and Weber as
two abstracted yet politically engaged intellectuals, attempting to understand
a rapidly changing world. It returns to their writings from this angle to draw
some conclusions about the ambiguous, untheorized place of the nation in
their theories of societal forms.
The differences between Durkheim and Weber are marked. However, I will
argue that these differences are set within a common set of assumptions and
a common constitutive milieu which crossed the borders of France and
Germany, even as those nation-states became increasingly antagonistic.
The imperative of national integration
Emile Durkheim was born in the Vosges, that part of Lorraine not taken over
by the Germans when in 1871 they annexed Alsace-Lorraine. This eastern
region was an important source of Third-Republic nationalism. Professed
cosmopolitan writers such as Gustave Flaubert (1821-80) were deeply
affected by the 1871 defeat and annexation. In that year (already discussed in
a broader context) Ernest Renan, a cosmopolite who had previously claimed
his patrie to be the 'human spirit', now embraced the sort of patriotic alle
giance he had earlier condemned: 'Those even who are philosophers before
21. From his Thought and Change, 1964, to his Encounters with Nationalism, 1994.
22. Anthony D. Smith, National Identity, 1991, and Liah Greenfeld, Nationalism, 1992. I
stress this point because a couple of my critics in reading the manuscript skipped over this para
graph, suggesting that I mistakenly focus on passages from the classical theorists that arc 'beside
the point': books which hardly mention the nation-state, such as The Elementary Forms of
Religious Life, they suggest, have profoundly influenced subsequent generations of commentators
on the nation. However, this is precisely my point: when later writers out of the Durkheimian and
Weberian traditions construct theories of national formation they rarely refer to Weber's explicit
writings on the nation and never to Durkheim's.
Durkheim and Weber: Antinomies of Abstract Nationalism 89
being patriots, cannot be insensible to the cry of two million men whom we
were obliged to throw in the sea in order to save the rest from drowning, but
who were bound to us for life and death. France, therefore, has a point of steel
embedded in her flesh which will no longer let her sleep. ' 23 Annexation
prompted one grouping which included the Vosges litterateur Maurice Barres
(1862-1923) towards revanchisme, dedicating their lives to restoring the des
ecrated lost territories.
Another grouping, apparently opposed to the philosophy of revenge,
included easterners such as Jules Ferry ( 1832-93), twice prime minister of
France. Their nationalism took a different guise. They moved to emphasize
the national-technocratic goal of modernization, particularly, following the
manner of Bismarck's Kulturkampf, the consolidation of mass, national, sec
ular education. In the _1880s, state funds were offered to scholars to bring
back ideas from Germany for effecting educational renovation. One recipient
of state sponsorship was Durkheim. Ironically, though born in Lorraine, he
felt little of the overt nationalist passion felt by others such as Renan and
Flaubert whose connection to those easterners 'thrown into the sea' of
German sovereignty was much more tenuous. By the time of his scholarship
to Germany, Durkheim had developed a dispassionate though complex rela
tionship to blood and soil: he had for example thoroughly left behind his
family's rabbinic tradition and the possibility of following his father as Grand
Rabbin des Vosges. His aim was quietly to change the world from a distance
through the abstract medium of writing. 24
Max Weber was similarly born into a changing world, a world of which he
became rigorously critical without challenging one of its grounding assump
tions. Like Durkheim he was both a cosmopolite and a contradictorily
dispassionate nationalist. No doubt it would be possible, along the lines of
Arthur Mitzman's psycho-social biography, partly to explain this antinomy
in terms of Weber's ambivalent response firstly to his father's subordination
of his National Liberalism to the Junker power-state (Machtstaat), and sec
ondly to his mother's passive withdrawal from her patriarchal husband into
her Calvinist orthodoxy. 25 However, the issue flows wider. In Germany, as in
France, there were active political debates over the ideological and practical
consequences of the conjunction of the national community and the
Machtstaat, debates over the nature and importance of tariffs and other
economic boundaries, discussions about the fate of the national minorities,
and critiques of traditional institutions such as the Church and monarchy.
These debates, however, tended not to cut any deeper than immediate policy
23. Renan, La Reforme /111el/ectuelle et Morale, cited in William Buthman, The Rise of
/11tegra/ Nationalism in France, 1970, p. 15. See also Chapter 6 below for a discussion of Renan's
'Qu'est-ce qu'une Nation?'
24. On Durkheim's life see Kenneth Thompson, Emile Durkheim, 1982. ch. I; Edward
Tiryakian, 'Emile Durkheim', 1970; and Henri Peyre, 'Durkheim: The Man, His Time and Ills
Intellectual Background', 1964. On the complicated and changing ideologies of nationalism in
pre-war France see Eugen Weber, The Nationalist Revfral in France. /905-19/4, 1968.
25. Arthur Mitzman, The Iron Cage, 1969.
90 Nation Formarion
considerations. Nation and nation-state were largely taken for granted as
forming an unexamined cultural base.
Numerous extra-parliamentary movements in Germany took national con
siderations as their reason for.being. Such groups included the Pan-German
League which Weber left, not because of its ultra-nationalism, but on the
grounds of its sectarian-leaning towards equating the national interest with
the interests of the Junker class. All claimed to be above 'mere politics'. The
League's aim remained as Weber's ongoing credo - to 'bring together the
nationally-minded citizens without considerations of party in the thought
that the accomplished fact of the unification of the German race is only the
beginning of a larger national development' .26 The difference was that Weber's
theoretical perspective made it possible for him to at least recognize that the
issue of national integration was intensely political. For him it was politics
carried out at a deeper level than that reached by arguing over the possible
institutional arrangements of the means of agency-extension.
Thus from the beginning, the politics of the national question formed the
background to Durkheim's and Weber's writing. In Weber's inaugural lecture
at Freiburg, 'The National State and Economic Policy' (May 1895), he pre
sented an academic but militant, social-Darwinist argument for the primacy
of the nation. He addressed the issue of how Germany, through political
education and the 'social unification of the nation', might be led by a matur
ing bourgeoisie to an even greater epoch of imperial expansion. Germany, he
says, 'must remain sensitive to the grand passions nature has placed within
us'.27 He concludes:
A great nation does not age beneath the burden ofa thousand years ofglorious his
tory. It remairis young ifit has the capacity and the courage to keep faith with itself
and with the grand instincts it has been given, and when its leading strata are able
to raise themselves into the hard and clear atmosphere in which the sober activity
of German politics flourishes, an atmosphere which is also pervaded by the solemn
splendour ofnational sentiment.28
Just as Durkheim constantly argues for 'a national catechism which will
include the elementary teaching of principles which serve as the basis of social
organization,' 29 Weber emphasizes that the future rested upon the central role
of education in national integration: 'The aim of our socio-political activity is
not world happiness but the social unification of the nation.' 30 In this they
26. Stephen Turner and Regis Factor, M ax Weber and the Dispute over Reason and Value,
1984, p. 13.
27. Max Weber, Inaugural Lecture, Freiburg, 1895, 'The National State and Economic Policy'.
W.G. Runciman notes that, even at the time, the address was received as an 'aggressive and con
troversial statement of liberal imperialism'. See Max Weber, Weber: Selections in Translation,
(1895-1920), 1978, p. 211.
28. Weber, Inaugural Lecture, (1895) I 980, p. 448.
29. These are in fact the words Henri de Saint-Simon (1760-1825) cited favourably in Emile
Durkheim, Soci alism and Saint-Simon, (1896) 1959, p. 142. The argument is spelt out in
Durkheim, Moral Education, (1902-3) 1973.
30. Weber, Inaugural Lecture, p. 447.
Durkheim and Weber: Antinomies of Abstract Nationalism 91
reinforced the already existent trends of modernity. Mass, state-funded, pri
mary education was being instituted across Europe; basic intellectual training
even for girls and working-class children was increasingly accepted as necessary
for instilling the 'scientific' ethic of social solidarity over and above religious
obedience.31 This is not to say that Durkheim and Weber were vacantly
mouthing current ideologies. Weber, for example, rejected the incursions made
into intellectual liberty by Kulturkampf Both had an avowedly dispassionate,
though in their own terms ultimately non-scientific argument, for the 'careful
cultivation of national character'.32 The rationale for their advocacy of the
abstract state and for the abstract nation (concepts I initially use here in the
sense implied by Durkheim and Weber as more abstract in thought) was in part
the logical outcome of their general theories of society and of the methods by
which they believed that social relations could be understood.
Different approaches, convergent appreciations
Durkheim begins from the premise that individuals are controlled by coercive
external categories of representation and practice which have their source,
their 'substratum', in society itself. At the point where these collective mani
festations or social facts appear to be natural, we have fallen 'victims to the
illusion of having ourselves created that which actually forced itself from
without'. 33 Categories as totalizing and ontologically basic as time and space
are mutable facts, part of the 'abstract and impersonal frame', intelligible
through concrete signs such as the changing of the seasons, and self-con
sciously accessible through the 'conscience collective'. 34 They originate out of
the way in which the social is organized, particularly its demographic volume
and density. In attempting to explain the source of social facts, Durkheim
departs from the narrow functionalism and explicit teleology of Auguste
Comte (1798-1857) and Herbert Spencer (1820-1903). He dismisses the claim
that willed actions could of themselves bring social facts into being.35
Nationality is used as a key example. Responding to those such as Gustave Le
Bon (1841-1931) who suggest that social phenomena can be explained by the
psychology of individuals or groups, Durkheim replies:
In reality, as far back as one goes in history, the principle of association is the most
imperative of all, for it is the source of all other compulsions. As a consequence of
31. Robert Gildea, Barricades and Borders: Europe /800-1914, 1987, ch. 13, 'The Management
of Society'. See also J.E.G. de Montmorency, State Intenen1ion in English Education, 1902. The
preface rings with the urgency of the task. However, this trend was not simply ushered in on a
wave of complete change: taking up a university post in Prague, Albert Einstein had to wear a mil
itary uniform, avow his belief in God and swear allegiance to the Habsburgs.
32. Weber, Inaugural Lecture, (1895) 1980, p. 438.
33. Emile Durkheim, The Rules of Sociological Method, (1895) 1966, p. 5 and ch. I pa.uim. See
also Chapter 3, pp. 69-70 above.
34. Durkheim, Forms of Religious Life, (1912) 1976, pp. IOIT.. 4401T.
35. For a qualification of the force of this rejection see fn. 44 below.
92 Nation Formation
my birth, I am obliged to associate with a given group. It may be said that later, as
an adult, I acquiesce in this obligation by the very fact that I continue to live in my
country. But what difference does that make? This 'acquiescence' is still imperative.
Pressure accepted and submitted to with good grace is still pressure ... For the pre
sent, it is most certainly imposed upon me, for in the vast majority of cases it is
materially and morally impossible for us to strip off our nationality.36 (emphasis
added)
Durkheim's conclusion about the impossibility, 'for the present' , of strip
ping away one's nationality is couched her� on one plane. That is, while he is
well aware that nationality is a socially formed 'imperative' , he reduces the
ontological depth of national formation to the fact of living within the con
fines of a particular country in association with others. Nevertheless, it is
clear from his premises that for Durkheim the nation is natural only in the
sense that it is a social fact determined by preceding social facts. 37 This at least
provides the space for a theory of the nation. However, he does not take it any
further. 38 Durkheim remains, along with many contemporary writers in other
fields and from other places including the heretic English economist John
Hobson (1858-1940)39 or the novelist D.H. Lawrence (1885-1930), a cos
mopolitan supporter of the national ideal, critical of his own nation. We can
cite again Meinecke's paradoxical comment made in 1907 that the nation
drank of the blood of free personalities.
While we are still to place the nation in Durkheim's overall theory of soci
etal forms, at this stage we have sufficient detail to respond to the question as
to why Durkheim treats the nation as the repository of the highest ideals,
how, given his extolling of the ideals of a generalized humanitarianism, he can
justify the more particularizing cultivation of national character. Two points
can be made,-By his own logic, the fact of humanitarianism must derive from
already-given social facts. Therefore they must be embodied in an
already-existent social grouping. Secondly, in his words, 'in contrast with the
nation, mankind as source and object of morality suffers this deficiency:
there is no constituted society' .40 Thus there is one association that pre-emi
nently promotes moral conduct, namely the abstract nation, that is, 'the
nation - but the nation conceived of as a partial embodiment of the idea of
36. Durkheim, Sociological Method, (1895), pp. 104-105.
37. Ibid., pp. 110, 124.
38. It is not surprising then that Marion Mitchell's article, 'Emile Durkheim and the
Philosophy of Nationalism', 1931, has no discussion of Durkheim's theory of the nation: her
analysis is confined to philosophy and ethics.
39. See the introductory section, 'Nationalism and Imperialism', in John A. Hobson's
Imperialism, (1902) 1968.
40. Durkheim, Moral Education, (1902-3) 1973, p. 76. In the following passage (pp. 77-79) he
goes on to show how the ideals of the abstraction, 'humanity', and of the existing society orga
nized as a nation-state can coalesce. In narrow political terms at least, his argument runs in
complete opposition to Weber's assertion that what is important for national posterity is 'the
amount of elbow-room we conquer for [our nation] and leave behind us' (Inaugural Lecture,
(1895) 1980, p. 438).
Durkheim and Weber: Antinomies of Abstract Nationalism 93
humanity'.41 According to Durkheim, through the fact of its increasingly
extended form and by what today would be called multiculturalism, the
nation 'becomes more abstract, and more general and consequently closer to
the human ideal'. 42 Elsewhere he says: 'We must see in the fatherland in
abstracto the normal and indispensable milieu ofhuman life. ' 41
However, Durkheim runs into problems ofconsistency here for he is either
treating the abstract as materially constituted in the extension of social rela
tions - thus counteracting his tendency to relegate the process ofabstraction
to the realm ofideas44 - or, alternatively, he is treating the abstract as uncon
stituted, thus running counter to his basic premise that even the most abstract
laws of morality 'express the nature of concrete reality' founded in actually
existing collective practices. 45 Durkheim criticizes Rousseau for a kindred
problem:
Rousseau sees only two poles of human reality, the abstract, general individual who
is the agent and objective of social existence, and the concrete empirical individual
who is the antagonist of all collective existence. He fails to see that, though in a
sense these two poles are irreconcilable, the first without the second is no more than
a logical fiction. 46
Durkheim has a much more acute awareness than Rousseau of the prob
lems to be faced, but this does not resolve his dilemma. I want to expand
upon these points, but first let me bring Weber back into contention. Earlier
I said that Weber too has a dispassionate argument for supporting the pri
macy ofnational interest. However, unlike in Durkheim's approach, the links
in Weber's reasoning do not connect as a single chain.
One way into the problem is to note that Weber brackets off the study of
41. Durkheim, Moral Education,(1902-3) 1973, p. 80.
42. Ibid., p. 81.
43. Cited by Lewis Coser, 'Durkheim's Conservatism and its Implications for Sociological
Theory', 1964, p. 222. Durkheim's general argument for the abstract nation is expanded upon in
Professional Ethics and Civil Morals, (1890-1900) 1957, ch. 6 and passim. Cf. Ferdinand Tonnies,
Community and Society,(1887) 1963, p. 71 on Gesel/schafi as 'abstract reason'.
44. For example, see Durkheim and Dennis, Who Wanted War?, 1915: German conceptions of
national superiority 'sometimes bordering on delirium, did not arise spontaneously, none know
ing how or where; they are but expressions of a vital fact. This has justified us in saying that, in
spite of its abstract appearance, the idea of the State on which Treitschke's doctrine is based
masks a concrete and living sentiment; its soul is a certain attitude of will' (p. 44, emphasis
added). Durkheim would in substance agree with Vladimir Solovyof( l 853-1900) when in 1897
Solovyof wrote: 'At the stage of development now reached by humanity the fact of belonging to
a given nationality is to a certain extent confirmed by the individual's self-conscious will. Thus
nationality is an inner, inseparable property of the person - is something very dear and close to
him. It is impossible to stand in a moral relation to this person without recognizing the existence
of what is so important to him. The moral principle does not allow us to transform a concrete
person, a living man with his inseparable and essential national characteristics, into an empty
abstract subject with all his determining peculiarities left out.' Sec Solovyof, The Ju.rtification of
the Good, (1897) 1918, p. 297 and ch. 5 passim. Also cited in Eugene Kamcnka, 'Polillcal
Nationalism -The Evolution of the Idea', 1973, p. 9.
45. Durkheim, Moral Education, (1902-3) 1973, pp. 111-114, cited from p. 113.
46. Durkheim, Montesquieu and Rousseau, (1892) 1965, p. 131.
94 Nation Formation
collective associations and relations. He often writes of collective processes
and structures (used in the sense of institutions of agency extension), but his
methodological standpoint is the antithesis of Durkheim's. Weber begins
with an ahistorical category, t!Je action of' individual persons' (his empha
sis). When he refers to a state or a nation, or any other social form, he
means 'nothing more than a specifically structured outcome of the social
actions of individuals either actually performed or constructed as poss
ible' .47 In other words, collective processes or associations such as the
nation-state cannot be treated as sociologital facts. They reside in the 'hypo
thetical and fragmentary' realm of normative representations. They exist as
abstractions, real by virtue of being thought to be real. Thus acted upon,
they are able to be pieced together by interpretative sociology from an
understanding of the motives and actions of 'individual functionaries and
members of[the] community' in question. 48 Hence a particular nation can be
concretely analysed by a historian, while the form of the nation must be
treated as an abstract ideal-type. This has two consequences. The first is
methodological: 'The very first step towards a historical judgement is
thus ... ,' Weber says, 'a process of abstraction.' 49 The sociologist 'abstracts
himself[or herself] from reality and advances our knowledge of it by eluci
dating the degree of approximation to which a particular historical
phenomenon can be classified in terms of one or more of these ["very
abstract") concepts', or ideal types. 50 This confines the process of abstraction
to the realm of ideas.The second consequence (extending upon the critique
of ideal-type theorizing in Chapter 2) is that collective associations or com
munal relations are left with only a virtual existence.This has more limiting
implications fm:. his study of the nation than it does for his study of the state.
If Weber hactextended upon his sketchy notes on the 'idea of the nation' his
direction would have been thoroughly constrained by treating the nation as
a (virtual) object in the sphere of values:
If the concept of 'nation' can in any way be defined unambiguously, it certainly
cannot be stated in terms of empirical qualities common to those who count as
members of the nation. In the sense of those using the term at a given time, the con
cept undoubtedly means above all, that one may exact from certain groups of men
a specific sentiment of solidarity in the face of other groups. Thus the concept
belongs in the sphere of values. 51
47. Max Weber, 'The Nature of Social Action' in Weber: Selections, (1895-1920) 1978, p. 17.
48. Ibid., pp. I6fT. It should be made clear that for Weber, given his definition of an 'associa
tion' as a social relationship with exclusionary rules and which 'to "exist" depends entirely on the
presence of a head' (p. 33), a nation-state is an association ( Vergesellschaftrmg) while the nation
is not. The latter, to the extent that it is self-conscious comes under the heading of 'communal
relationship' ( Vergemeinschaftung), based on the 'subjective feeling of the parties'. These are more
active versions of Tonnies' Gesellschaft and Gemeinschaft. See Weber, Social and Economic
Organization, (1910--20) 1945, pp. 136-139.
49. Weber in Weber: Selections, (1895-1920) 1978, p. 118; also pp. 23, 117-119, 128, 130.
50. Ibid., p. 23; also pp. 117-119, 128, 130.
51. Weber, Essays in Sociology, 1968, p. 172.
Durkheim and Weber: Antinomies of Abstract Nationalism 95
Of course, Weber (following Renan) is right that the nation cannot be
defined in terms of empirical qualities, but his subsequent move reduces the
nation (a complex objective-subjective relation) to the held-in-common
'subjective feeling' of individual actors. 52 Coterminous with this methodolog
ical-individualist bracketing off of the status of interpretative theorizing is a
parallel separation of the status of value judgements. Although Weber agreed
with the calls for commitment to the glory of the nation such as espoused by
a predecessor at Freiburg, the ex-liberal, anti-semitic historian, Heinrich von
Treitschke ( 1834-96), 53 he was critical of Treitschke as one of the charismatic
prophets who confused fact and value. Herein lies a complicated qualification
of the statement that Weber has a dispassionate argument for the priority of
national interest.
At the centre of his methodology are two overlapping distinctions: one
between verifiable fact or logically deduced proposition and interpretative or
practical judgements, and the other between the science of culture and the
practice of politics. Although not always consistently invoked, they make it
possible for him to enunciate the view that the social sciences cannot deduce
ultimate values from its findings and, at the same time, to argue (practically)
for the nation-state as the ultimate 'power value'. 54 That is, for Weber, it is
logically possible within the realm of practical judgements and the practice of
politics to argue for the value of the nation-state while separating this issue
from the question of how one interprets the constitutive moments of national
community or state association. It leads, in summary, to Weber having a
logically deduced and dispassionate argument for his conclusion that (his)
commitment to the national interest ultimately cannot be reached by verifi
able, deductive argument. 55 He says:
We know of no scientifically demonstrable ideals. To be sure, our labours are now
rendered more difficult, since we must create our ideals from within our chests in
the very age of subjectivist culture . .. it is the stigma of our human dignity that the
peace of our souls cannot be as great as the peace of one who dreams of ['a fool's')
paradise. 56 (emphasis added)
This passage also leads us into the familiar theme of upheaval and dissolu
tion (Chapter 3). The contradiction between the rational, self-conscious
invention of meaning, creating 'ideals from within our chests' as Weber
expresses it, and the attendant loss of traditional meaning in the 'subjectivist
culture' was a common theme permeating the writing of avant-garde.
turn-of-the-century intellectuals. It can be found in its various manifestations
52. (Emphasis added.) This is not to say that he ignores material relations. but rather that they
are separated off as factors.
53. See Louis Snyder, German Nationalism, (1952) 1969, ch. 6. See also Durkheim and D.:nnis.
Who Wanted War?, 1915, for an extensive critique ofTreitschke"s writings.
54. Weber, 'Value-judgements in Social Science', 1913, in Weber: Selections. (1895 1920)
1978, pp. 69-98.
55 See Turner and Factor. Dispute over Reason, 1984. pp. 55ff.
56. Weber's 'Viennese declaration' cited in Lawrence Scaff, 'Fleeing the Iron Cage·, 1987,
p. 738.
96 Nhtion Formation
in writers from Friedrich Nietzsche (1844-1900) and Henri Bergson
(1859-1941) to Thomas Mann (1875-1955) and Lev Nikolayevich Tolstoy
(1828-1910). 57 It was, in effect, paralleled by the partial breakdown of the old
certainties of positivistic sciell€e, evidenced by the work of Albert Einstein
(1879-1955) and Max Planck (1858-1947). Although the grand synthesizing
projects of science continued on, such as Mendeleyev's periodic table (dis
cussed in the previous chapter) or Bertrand Russell's (1872-1970) and Alfred
Whitehead's (1861-1947) Principia Mathematica, they tended to become more
abstract. Just as the critical positivist Ernst ·Mach (1838-191�) argued that sci
entific laws and concepts were perverted by being held up as absolutes,58 Weber
too asserted that any doctrine of ultimate values would founder in contradic
tion.59 Thus, for Weber, the only other choice was the affirmation of existing
culture, or as Durkheim put it, society as constituted. In words with which
Durkheim would agree unqualifiedly, Weber says that the choice entails a pre
paredness to struggle with its '"antinomies" or "tensions" in order to achieve
clarity about the world as it "is "' _w The existing arena that Weber thought best
served this self-acknowledged, bourgeois struggle against the iron cage of
rationalization is a cultural-political arena (an arena itself brought into being
by the processes of rationalization) founded upon the conjunction of nation
and state.61
In short, though using an opposing methodology, Weber is all the time
looking through a common cultural-intellectual prism with Durkheim. And
from all the refracted possibilities, they both conclude by focusing on the
same source of political salvation - national unity.
Where does the 'nation' reside in Durkheim's and Weber's theories of
social forms?
Both of these classical theorists posit a basic distinction between traditional
and modern societies. This background is important to the discussion in
Chapter 6 of the work of Ernest Gellner, a theorist who was influenced by
Durkheim and Weber. Durkheim distinguishes between mechanical and
organic forms of solidarity, suggesting that with the division of labour and
concomitant individuation of social relations, societies formed by mechanical
repetition of aggregates inevitably gave way to societies organically coordi
nated as functionally and morally interdependent bodies (to use his metaphor
57. See William Barrett, Irrational Man, 1962.
58. See Michael Biddiss, The Age of the Masses, 1978, ch. 2.
59. It is a double contradiction given that such doctrines proclaim consistency. For an expo
sition of this step, see Weber, 'Politics as Vocation', 1919, in Weber: Selections, (1895-1920)
1978.
60. Scaff, 'Fleeing the Iron Cage', 1987, p. 745.
61. This contains a further tension. Neither Weber nor Durkheim loved their native Germany
or France as it presently existed.
Durkheim and Weber: Antinomies of Abstract Nationalism 97
of society as a living organism). 62 Weber's ideal-type methodology distin
guishes three relationships of political organization: traditional, charismatic
(always a transitional phase) and rational-legal (the modern side of the Great
Divide). Like Durkheim, Weber emphasizes the centrality of the division of
labour in the transition from tradition, but he formulates the basis of modern
solidarity as much in terms of the process of rationalism, the bureaucratiza
tion of the state and the centrality of trained specialists obeying rationally
formulated rules and principles, as in terms of a new, individual, moral ethic. 63
Where does the nation fit into these theoretical-historical schemes?
Although in Durkheim's case there is not enough direct discussion of the
formation of the nation to allow more than inferences to be drawn, the evi
dence again tends to point to the ambiguity of his position. The nation is
most often projected as an organic society, an association of people tending
towards or having their own state. Yet it is implicitly an organic society with
a moral homogeneity and an intensity of conscience collective more akin to
that generated within traditional (mechanical) society. This carries through
into his more straightforward historical description. On the one hand,
Durkheim writes of a transformation wrought in Europe during the
Renaissance from a generalized religious unity (there is no suggestion of any
metaphor of coexistent or intersecting forms in this segment of argument) to
a situation where 'each of the groups which had been formed had its own spe
cial mode of thought and feeling, its own national temperament':
By the sixteenth century the great nation states of Europe had been in large measure
established. Whereas in the Middle Ages there had been but one Europe, one
Christendom which was united and homogenous, there now existed great individ
ual collectivities with their own intellectual and moral characters. 64
On the other hand, the concepts of nation and nationality are also occasion
ally used in reference to quite different cultural associations, crossing history
from the Hellenic city-states65 and the 'barbaric nations' which 'could rightly
be called monarchies' , 66 to the clan 'nations of hunters and fishers' . 67
The nation is left in a position of comparable ambiguity in Weber's writings
62. See Emile Durkheim, The Division of labour in Soci{'(y, (1893) trans. 1933. This repre
sentation of Durkheim's theory is of course overly simplifying, for by the end of The Dfrision of
labour he came to see that the institutional stability of organic association depended upon cer
tain continuities of the earlier manifestations of the conscience collective.
63. The implicit comparative reference here is to how Weber differs from Durkheim's over
riding concern to show that organic solidarity is still a moral order even as the division of labour
produces a decline in the relevance of the traditional 'conscience collective'. Rather than attempt
to theorize the necessity of a moral basis to societal integration, Weber's The Protestant F.tltic and
the Spirit of Capitalism, (1904-5,trans. 1930) 1958, was a study of the rationalization of religion
in connection with the way 'new men' such as Benjamin Franklin were imbued with the capital
ist 'ethic' .
64. Emile Durkheim, The Erolution of Educational Thought, (1904-5) 1977, p. 171.
65. Durkheim, Socialism und Saint-Simon, (1896) 1959, pp. 173, 175.
66. Durkheim, Montesquieu and Rousseau, (1892) 1965, p. 9 and pp. 25, 26.
67. Durkheim, Forms of Religious life, (1912) 1976, pp. 233,415.
98 Nativn Formation
on social form, the difference being as already mentioned that Weber writes
directly of the 'entirely ambiguous' nature of the concept of the nation. The
only hints we get of a pointed theory of national formation are found in
Weber's comparative studies of Ii.ast and West:
The peculiar character of the Asian intellectual strata essentially prevented the
emergence of 'national' political formations, even of the kind which have developed
in the West from the later Middle Ages onward - although even in our case, the full
conception of the idea of the nation was first elaborated by the modern Western
intellectual strata. 68
The peculiar character of the Asian intellectual strata was not based on
their different relation to the process of rationality: intellectuals of both East
and West tended toward the rational side of the traditional (charismatic)
rational divide. It resided in the manifest separation of Asian intellectuals as
a stratum from the mass of the population: 'Only in Japan did the develop
ment of feudalism bring with it some hints of a genuinely "national"
consciousness, though this was mainly on the basis of the knightly class's
sense of status.' 69 Weber's use here of the centrality of status-orientation takes
us directly back into the realm of values and ideas. Elsewhere, Weber makes
the very interesting point that intellectuals are 'to a specific degree predes
tined to propagate the "nation ideal"'; 70 however, the depth of this
proposition is limited by his emphasis on power relations. This issue will
come up in different ways in later chapters on Ernest Gellner and Anthony
Giddens. The reason for this 'predestination' of the intellectual is reduced to
the fact that the power and prestige interests of intellectuals, amongst others,
are bound up with the preservation of cultural values and the cultivation of
the specificity of cultural association: 'Under the influence of these circles, the
naked prestige of "power" is unavoidably transformed into other special
forms of prestige and especially into the idea of the "nation".' 71 Intellectual
work as a materially abstract practice, and the nation as a form of abstract
social relations are thus left to one side.
Social form in the 'age of subjectMst culture'
The determinations and limiting conditions upon the fact that Durkheim
and Weber do not develop more than en passant theories of the nation, and
that by contrast they do have somewhat more to say about the nation-state,
are multifarious and many-layered. So far the chapter has focused upon the
constraints suggested by particular approaches to method and to value ori
entation. There are. of course, other ways of approaching the question. For
example, Lewis Coser in elaborating Kenneth Burke's aphorism that 'a way of
68. Weber, in Weber: Selections, (1895---1920) 1978, p. 203.
69 Ibid.
70. Weber, in From Max Weber (essays from 1904-20), 1968, p. 176.
71. Ibid., p. 172.
Durkheim and Weber. Antinomies of Abstract Nationalism 99
seeing is always a way of not seeing' , chooses to centre upon Durkheim's con
servatism. Coser's emphasis is a quite defensible way of taking up a particular
aspect of content. However, I would like to embed analysis of content in
questions of form. In a couple of provocative but undeveloped paragraphs
Coser provides us with a suggestive way of doing just that, confirming a
theme which has been running through the present chapter:
What has perhaps not been sufficiently discussed is the curiously abstract charac
ter of [Durkheim's] patriotism and his religion of society. Here it would seem
appropriate to introduce a consideration of Durkheim's background.
It is customary to find evidence in most patriotic writings of an attachment to
particular localities or regions, to particular historical or linguistic traditions. Not
so with Durkheim [or Weber]. We encounter in his writings a highly rational,
non-emotional attachment to la patrie. This intellectualized and abstract relation to
his country may well have had its source in his social origin. When this son of a
rabbi from the eastern fringes of France came to Paris to develop into one of the
guiding spirits of the Third Republic, he did not feel bound to any one subgroup,
class, stratum, or region. His loyalty went to France, which became for him the pro
totype of the society. His attachment was not mediated through tradition and
history, but was, so to speak, abstractly intellectual. 72
Coser makes an important point even if, in an overall sense, he over-accen
tuates the unmediated, single-level dominance of abstract intellectuality. His
position does not evidence a notion of the contradictory subjectivity of intel
lectuals. In terms of the metaphor of levels-in-intersection, intellectuals have
a 'double' ontology: however abstracted across time and space they may be
in the practice of their work, they remain constrained simultaneously as
mortal, embodied subjects. They experience the cultural contradictions
which arise out of being, at one level, intellectuals qua intellectuals convers
ing via the medium of print across space and time, while at another level
being bound, as Durkheim would acknowledge, by the fact of being born
into specific relations of blood, in a particular locale, at a particular time. It
is indicative that both Weber and Durkheim allowed the passions of war to
overcome partially the intellectual face of their abstract detachment. So
while Coser isolates a salient, even dominant, level of their being. given that
intellectual pursuits dominated their lives, it is a level beset by cultural con
tradictions. Weber, for example, followed in the intellectual cavalcade from
Dante and Petrarch to Montesquieu and de Tocqueville (mentioned in the
previous chapter) for whom travel was a significant aspect of this lifting
out. Weber's mental breakdown, attributable to attempting to resolve a man
ifold of contradictions, 73 was followed by years of almost continual
72. Coser, 'Durkheim's Conservatism', I964, p. 223. As Benedict Anderson points out (per
sonal communication), Coser misses the importance of Durkheim's Jewishness: 'All over Europe
Jews looked to the state to protect them from "society".'
73. Edward B. Portis (Ma., Weber and Po/i11cal Commitment, 1986) picks up on the antin
omy of overt political action and the social scientist's objectivity. but he is uncommcmg m
making it the central motif of Weber's life. Arthur M1tzman's attempt m The Iron Ca)!e ( 1969)
to make Weber's resolutions of oedipal connict the key to understanding is equall) one-<l ,men
sional.
100 Natfon Formation
European travelling. Later the war became Weber's 'great trip, serving the
same therapeutic functions as his earlier travels. Although well aware of its
horrors, having lost a brother, a brother-in-law and several friends, he nev
ertheless on a number of occasions referred to the war as "great and
wonderful".' 74
Weber's words are those of someone who, at least at one level of their
being, stands in a highly abstract relation to death and 'the shell-pocked
leagues of shit' 75 that were given the heroic_ names of Verdun, Somme and
Passchendaele. He faces a similar contradiction to Ulrich, the central char
acter in Robert Musil's novel The Man Without Qualities. Musil claims that
the 'Man Without Qualities' has less probability of experiencing the remark
able things of life than reading of them in the newspaper: 'In other words
[says Musil's narrator], it is in the realm of the abstract that the more impor
tant things happen in these times, and it is the unimportant that happens in
real life.' 76
The sad irony is that to the extent Weber abstractly glorifies war he does so
as an attempt to reclaim what abstract reflection and self-conscious historic
ity tend to dismantle. In this Weber was not so different from the ethnocentric
nationalist Maurice Barres. According to Philip Ouston, Barres was critical
of the tendency for political visionaries, 'by hypertrophy of one of its con
stituents, abstraction, at the expense of the other, sensation, to lose contact
altogether with the world of concrete and particular facts'. The hero of
Barres's Un Homme Libre finds 'that his unbridled imagination has carried
him into a finally uninhabitable void of pure subjectivity'. Nevertheless
Barres wants to find a way to move through 'Le passage du local a !'uni
verse!' .77 Was_§ily Kandinsky (1866-1944), the first painter to create
non-representational 'abstract art' , similarly described the dilemma of pur
suing the abstract to find the really real. He distinguished two processes in
modernism:
l. Disintegration of the soulless, materialistic life of the nineteenth century, i.e. the
collapse of the material supports that were considered the only solid ones and the
decay and dissolution of the various parts.
2. Construction of the spiritual and intellectual life of the twentieth century that we
experience and that is already manifested and embodied in strong, expressive, and
distinct forms. 78
These are examples of what was discussed at the end of Chapter 2 under
the rubric of the recalling of the concrete. They are attempts to reclaim the
more concrete sense-of-being, in Weber's case framed by a 'community unto
74. Portis, Political Commitment, p. 146. On the importance of travel see also pp. 49-50, 90, 92.
75. Thomas Pynchon cited by Paul Fussell, The Great War and Modern Memory, 1977, p. 330.
76. Robert Musil (1880-1942), The Man Without Qualities, vol. I, (1930) 1983, p. 76. Written
in the early 1920s, the novel was set in 1914 as the story of the patriotic campaign to celebrate the
idea of a Universal Austria.
77. Philip Ouston, The Imagination of Barres, 1974, quotes from pp. 9-10, 65ff.
78. Kandinsky, cited in Steven Holtzman, Digital Mantras: The Languages of Abstract and
Virtual Worlds, 1994, p. 70.
Durkheim and Weber: Antinomies of Abstract Nationalism 101
death'. They are attempts to reassert in the new age the spirit - though not
the structural form nor social content - which pervaded the period when
God was still in His Heaven and, as Tolstoy put it, meaningful death pro
vided the basis for meaningful life. 79 This continues to be an important
political project even if it is one perverted by fundamentalism, parochialism,
sectarianism and racism.Unfortunately Weber has no way of theorizing how
the 'abstract' can reclaim the 'concrete' , no way of demarcating his position
from the direction taken by the post-war theorists of fascism.He says: 'War
does something to the warrior which in its concrete meaning is unique: it
makes him experience a consecrated meaning of death which is characteris
tic only of death in war ... [creating] a community unto death, and the
greatest of its kind.'80
Notwithstanding the irony that Weber wrote about phenomena of such
existential power while absenting himself into the realms of abstract intellec
tuality, by so arguing for the possibility of social life grounded in more
concrete levels of association he opens for himself the possibility of a theory
of ontology which is neither primordialist nor set on one plane. Like
Durkheim, however, Weber fails to take this very far. Both their methodolo
gies of social factuality and methodological individualism did not do much
more than the historians of their time in describing the 'what is-ness' uf the
nation and nation-state.
If the period through which Karl Marx lived gave rise, for some, to the real
ization that all that is solid melts into air, the late nineteenth, early twentieth
century underscored this sense of flux.It marked the beginning of a period
when the avant-garde intellectual, whether social theorist, artist or scientist,
was confronted with the necessity of at least considering that he or she had
lost the ground that Marx had stood upon when so confidently analysing 'the
reality' behind the chimeras and veils.In the words of Durkheim's anti-repub
lican, nationalist contemporary Maurice Barres, a generation of Europeans
had lived through the transition 'from the absolute to the relative'. 81 'Our
thinking has no even, solid, safe basis', says one of Robert Musil s' characters,
'but goes along, as it were, over holes in the ground - shutting its eyes, ceas
ing to exist for a moment, and yet arriving safely at the other side.'82
Durkheim and Weber dealt with this in quite different ways.But they both, as
much as the host of other fin-de-siecle social theorists, felt the collective
melancholy that they considered to be a consequence of the disintegration
and far gmentation (Durkheim) or de-personalized rationalization (Weber) of
79. See Weber, 'Science as a Vocation', 1918, and 'Religious Rejections of the World', I 915. in
From Max Weber (essays from 1904-1920), 1968.
80. Ibid., p. 335.
81. Barres, Les Deracines (The Uprootea) published in 1897, cited in Tiryakian. 'Emile
Durkheim', 1970, p. 209.
82. Robert Musil, The Co11fusions of Young Tiir/ess, (1906) 1955, p. 177.
102 Natl'on Formation
the social bondY In all of this the nation held an ambiguous place. By not
having a way of directly confronting this ambiguity, Weber and Durkheim
further precluded the possibility of their adequately theorizing the pre
eminent abstract community of �e twentieth century and its contradictory
hold upon people.
Such a theory became all the more vital as, in the mid-twentieth century,
the subjectivities and institutions of the nation and nation-state consolidated
around the fragmenting networks of cultural life, while, under the banner of
the community unto death, the nations of ·the world embarked upon new
wars in the context of an ever-more dangerous, rationalized, militarized
'peace'. It is to the contribution of contemporary theory that the next three
chapters now turn.
83. Durkheim was able to document this 'melancholy' of disintegration, as he called it, in his
study of suicide, but we should keep in mind the distinction between the uneven pessimism of a
substantial proportion of the avant-garde and the responses of those for whom the promise of
progress and the breakdown of the old system were experienced either as release and liberation,
or as part of the 'civilizing process'.
PART THREE:
CONTEMPORARY THEORY
5
Nation Formation and the Janus Faces of
History: A Critique of Marxis1n
Because it was the first, the English - later British - experience remained
distinct. Because they came second, into a world where the English
Revolution had already succeeded and expanded, later bourgeois soci
eties could not repeat this early development. Their study and imitation
engendered something substantially different: the truly modern doctrine
of the abstract or 'impersonal' state which, because of its abstract nature,
could be imitated in subsequent history.
f
Tom Nairn, The Break-up o Britain, 1981
Within both mainstream and marxist traditions of theorizing the nation there
continues to be a tendency to fracture history into contradictory faces: the
primordial past and the culturally invented modern period. One of the central
themes of this book has been to question the terms of the primordialist
modernist split. The present chapter brings this theme to the fore, examining
the way in which, even within the work of quite sophisticated theorists, the
nation is pictured from mutually exclusive perspectives. Just as the old Roman
god Janus had two faces, the writings of many contemporary theorists arc
composed of opposing views of how history is lived and reproduced: one
face assumes the primordiality of its grounding forms; the other accentuates
the historicity of history and emphasizes its self-conscious invented quality.
Related expressions of the cleavage occur in positing distinctions between the
real or given and the artificial; or between the natural and the constructed.
These are representational splits with fundamental implications for historical
method and for political practice.
Some social theorists and historians have tried to go beyond either simply
accentuating one or other view, or implicitly accepting the terms of the clea\
ing. But with regards to the national question there has been not onl) little
success but also little awareness that it is indeed a problem.
104 Natitm Formalion
The mainstream tradition has been divided between, on the one hand,
those theorists who have been labelled as primordialists, including Edward
Shils and Clifford Geertz, 1 and on the other hand, a number of writers such
as Ernest Gellner who stress tlw invented nature of national formations.2
This second grouping was perhaps initiated with the ambiguous writings of
Lord Acton, a historian discussed earlier in the context of the period in which
Marx wrote.Acton's claim that the nation became artificial with the devel
opment of a self-conscious argument for the conjunction of nation and state
was an anomaly in its time, 3 but the cultural inventionist position (not neces
sarily expressed in the way that Acton does) has gained increasing credibility
for twentieth-century writers.It has certainly gained prominence since Elie
Kedourie first opened his book with the now often-quoted sentence,
'Nationalism is a doctrine invented in Europe at the beginning of the nine
teenth century ' ,4 and Kenneth Minogue concluded his with the words:
'Nationalism ...began by describing itself as the political and historical
consciousness of the nation, and came in time to the inventing of nations for
which it could act. ' 5
The marxist tradition has handled the Janus faces differently. It harbours
no primordialists as such. Nevertheless, the cleaving still occurs, much as it
still does in those lines of liberal theory which attempt to bypass the problem.
It occurs either by a particular theorist implicitly becoming divided against
him or herself, as I will argue is the case with Tom Nairn, or by the setting up
of an explicit and problematic distinction between the real and the artificial
or invented.For example, it is possible to find unabashed Janus-faced com
ments in the work of someone such as Raymond Williams. Usually a
methodologic<!llY careful theorist, he writes: 'All the real processes have been
cultural and historical, and all the artificial processes have been political, in
one after another dominative proclamation of a state and an identity' 6
(emphasis added).One of the key problems, as many marxists will readily
acknowledge, is that marxism, like mainstream theory, has still to develop an
adequate working approach to that cluster of phenomena - nationality,
nation, nation-state and nationalism - which can synthetically escape the
limitations of the present tendency towards disconnected, regionally focused,
separately periodized or single-level studies.
The nation is an abstract community of strangers who cannot hope to
have a face-to-face relation with each of their compatriots. And yet, as has
I. See for example Edward Shils, 'Primordial, Personal, Sacred and Civil Ties', I 957, pp.
130--145; Clifford Geertz, The Interpretation of Cultures, 1973, chs 9 and 10; Harold R. Isaacs,
'Nationality: "End of the Road"?' 1975; Richard Lynn, 'The Sociobiology of Nationalism',
1976, pp. 11-14. Clifford Geertz is more ambiguous than the conventional labelling suggests, and
might also be considered a Janus-faced theorist.
2. Ernest Gellner, Nations and Nationalism, 1983, pp. 40, 47, 48, 56, 65.
3. See above Chapter 3; also Acton's Essays on Freedom and Power, (1862) 1948.
4. Elie Kedourie, Nationalism, (1960) 1993, p. 9.
5. Kenneth Minogue, Nationalism, 1967, p. 154, also p. 33.
6. Raymond Williams, Towards 2000, 1985, p. 194.
Nation Formation and the Janus Faces of History 105
been discussed at length above, it is embedded in the very historical forms
from which it is already abstracted. The nation is structured through quite
material processes and yet by definition it exists, like a class-for-itself, by
virtue of its own sense of historicity. With those particular quandaries throw
in other issues such as the historically partial conjunction of the nation
with the institutional level embodied in the state, and existing theories are
faced with a practical and definitional imbroglio. For the most part, con
temporary marxists have handled the national question by separating the
theorizing of nation and national identity from nation-state and national
ism. This is an eminently defensible move except that it masks the lack of a
theory of their inter-relation. Through the eyes of the first face of Janus,
nationality is seen as a given, certainly an historically constituted given,
but one assumed rather than attended to with more than passing attention.
Through the eyes of the second, now-dominant face, the nation-state is
most often viewed as an ideological-institutional arrangement serving the
national market; and nationalism is considered to be a superstructural ide
ology, drawing upon invented or factitious traditions. Notwithstanding the
generality of these premises, in the last couple of decades, debates over the
theory and politics of the nation question have been raging, strong and
unresolved. This chapter begins with a contextualizing review of those
debates.
New nationalisms and the New Left
Through the late 1960s into the 1970s the orthodox marxist approach to the
nation question was beginning to be challenged. 7 Orthodoxy was confronted
directly and practically with explaining an 'inexplicable' second wave of
nationalist movements. It was a wave that had at least two places of origin:
post-colonial and Western. In the Third World it arose out of the struggles
and transformations that marked the end of formal empire; 8 and from within
the long-established nation-states of Europe and North America it issued
7. 'Orthodoxy' is here used very broadly to include both 'classical marxism' (usually specified
as the position initiated by Marx and re-worked by Lenin), and 'vulgar marxism · (the reduc
tionist hardening of classical marxism into a positivistic or scientific doctrine, associated with the
writings of the Second and Third International). 'Nee-orthodoxy' is used to encompass those
contemporary theorists who, in the words of Tom Nairn ( The Break-up of Brilain: Crisis and
Neo-Na1ionalism, 1981, p. 330), believe that if we 'lend a retrospective helping hand' an adequate
theory will surely emerge from 'between the lines of the classics'. There are not many blithely
unreconstructed Marxist-Leninists still writing on the nation question: one example is M.
Kulichenko, Nations and Social Progress, 1984.
8. The literature on this first area is more extensive and goes back further. The seminal early
contribution is Peter Worsley's The Third World. ( 1964) 1978. From the mainstream see John
Kautsky, ed., Polilical Change in Underde,·eloped Coun1ries, 1967. The revival of left mtercst m
the nation question was marked by the 1962 Pas! and Presen1 conference. See Alan Adamson's
notes, 'Colonialism and Nationalism in Africa and Europe', 1963.
106 Nation Formation
forth from partly forgotten, but apparently 'primordial', ethnic fissures. 9
The recent explosion of neo-nationalism in Eastern Europe, exacerbated by
the break-up of the Soviet bloc, had not yet burst upon the scene, but there
were enough examples in Weskrn Europe alone to warrant considerable
rethinking.
We can also point to a third source of nationalism. Though in retrospect it
is now starting to appear obvious, a new kind of nationalism was emerging
out of the globalizing pressures of late modernity which was then overlooked
by marxist and liberal alike. Evidenced partly in the celebrations of bicenten
aries in the USA, Australia and France, 10 the new nationalism did not fit in
with any familiar analyses including the new theoretical language associated
with understanding social movements. In the heartlands of the highly urban
ized, Westernized nation-states, there stirred a general and 'renewing' sense of
national awareness. Without generating any social movements as such, it
involved the sharpening of a sensibility dulled in the cosmopolitan optimism
and 'mobile privatization' of the post-war boom. I I People sought to reconnect
with older established forms and sensibilities, including a sense of national
engagement, but they did so from a standpoint that was no longer comfort
able with the classical modern form of nationalism. The national past was
more likely to be treated as a pastiche to be selectively criticized and lauded
than as a binding essential history. National culture was more likely to be
understood (in postmodern terms) as an heterogeneous patchwork of frag
ments than as a homogeneous seamless whole.
Orthodox theory was met by a closely associated theoretical challenge. It
centred on the problem of understanding the 'realm of the cultural'. This will
be discussed !JlOfe generally in the next chapter, but specifically in relation to
marxism, economistic and reflectionist theories of the base-superstructure
kind began to look as if they might be built upon corroding scaffolding.
Ironically this occurred just as commentators across the political spectrum
reopened the question of the force of the economic by pointing to a trans
formation in the mode of production from monopoly to late capitalism, or (in
the language of Daniel Bell and others) from industrialism to technetronic
post-industrialism. Machinofacture was acknowledged to have lost its com
petitive edge to robotic, computerized and information-dominated
9. The literature on this second area, though recent, is growing all the time. For example the
Canadian Review of Studies in Nationalism was a early leader in publishing articles including:
John Agnew, 'Political Regionalism and Scottish Nationalism in Gaelic Scotland', 1981; Joseph
Rudolph, 'Ethnoregionalism in Contemporary Western Europe', 1981; and Phillip Rawkins,
'Nationalist Movements Within the Advanced Industrial State', 1983.
I 0. See John Hutchinson, Modern Nationalisms, 1994, ch. 6 'Pioneers of Post-Nationalism or
Insecure Parvenus?'
11. The phrase 'mobile privatization' is Raymond Williams'. His work provides a telling illus
tration of the turnaround in marxist sensitivity toward the nation question: Towards 2000 (1985),
his reflections on the 1980s and beyond, includes a chapter on 'The Culture of Nations', whereas
his creed for the 1960s, The Long Revolution ( I 961 ), does not once raise the nation as an explicit
issue.
Nation Formation and the Janus Faces of History 107
production. Seen narrowly and only in these terms some marxists remained
convinced that there was still reason, albeit with a modicum of sprucing up,
to retain the base-superstructure framework essentially unchanged. For oth
ers the challenge went deeper. The issues raised by feminism, the
counter-culture, May '68 and the student movement, by the critiques of a
one-dimensional culture, and by events such as the invasions of
Czechoslovakia and Vietnam, required more than reasserting a new ortho
doxy.
The debate between the structuralists and the cultural materialists - includ
ing the various lines of demarcation between Louis Althusser, Nicos
Poulantzas, Terry Eagleton, Fredric Jameson, Raymond Williams, Edward
Thompson and Lucien Goldmann - was a response to this 'rise of the cul
tural'. While very critical of what became known as vulgar marxism, none of
these theorists intended to dismantle completely the old edifice.12
Nevertheless, the debates shook orthodox marxism to its foundations. The
'crisis in marxism' was still a few years away from formally being announced,
but with this debate, the issues around which the crisis would later erupt
were coming to the fore. 13 On the one hand, the 'discovery' and translation of
Antonio Gramsci's Quaderni de/ Carcere, and on the other, the consolidation
of Althusser's structuralism, simply confirmed the new emphasis which marx
ism, and social theory more generally, was beginning to place on culture,
ideology and Ianguage. 14 From the same already-present concerns there arose
a 'small clamour' for an English translation of the Grundrisse: this series of
Marx's workbooks had been available in the original German for at least
two decades.
Tom Nairn: a partial break with orthodoxy
It was in this context of a change in the social form of nationalism and a the
oretical upheaval giving rise to the New Left, that an article entitled 'The
Three Dreams of Scottish Nationalism' appeared in New Left Review (1968).
The article substantially, and by intonation, diverged from some received
12. See Richard Johnson, 'Histories of Culturerrheories of Ideology: Notes on an Impasse·.
1979.
13. See the chronicling of this in Alex Callinicos, Is there a Future/or Marxism?, 1982. Here
again there was a further sleeping challenge to orthodox marxism. At that time it went substan
tially, or at least publicly, unacknowledged. Represented by the writings of Michel Foucault,
Giles Deleuze and F elix Guattari, Jacques Derrida and others, this challenge was initially brack
eted as being of t he same order as that coming from Althusser, Claude Levi-Strauss and the early
Roland Barthes. In the 1970s all these French theorists were run together as 'structuralists'. In the
1990s the once callow challenger, post-structuralism, is now the front-runner.
14. Gramsci's phrase the 'national popular' was given a renewed lease of life in the 1980s as
a catch-cry around which to politically connect a plurality of social movements and groupings
including working-class alliances. See the articles by David Forgacs ('National-Popular·
Genealogy of a Concept'); and Iain Chambers and Lidia Curti ('A Volatile Alliance') in
Formations: Of Nation and People, 1984.
108 Nation Formation
tenets of orthodoxy: it introduced, at least metaphorically, the language of
psychoanalysis; it questioned, at least in the case of Scottish history, the
nexus between capitalism and protestantism; and while conventional in its cri
tique of the 'garrulous, narci�istic windbaggery' and parochialism of
bourgeois nationalism, it posited the only sane alternative as being Socialist
Nationalism.Its Scottish author, Tom Nairn, was at the same time part of the
editorial committee of New Left Review, and supported the journal's
expressed intention of opening the national drawbridge and importing
Western Marxism from across the English Channel. Gramsci, Sartre,
Althusser and Colletti were ordained to give direction to the English marxist
tradition. For his part, Nairn translated Giuseppe Fiori's biography of
Gramsci for New Left Books.
Few critics could make sense of a marxist who, on the one hand, felt
'inwardly wounded by the anti-Europeanism' of the Left argument against
the European Community, 15 and on the other hand continues to be a vehe
ment advocate of the break-up of Britain; who sympathizes with the
bourgeois Scottish National Party (SNP), and steadfastly argues that the
'Ulster-Protestant nationality' is not a passing ethnic relic.As Nairn says in
his candid, retrospective postscript to The Break-up of Britain, his position
reflects the 'dilemma of an insecure national identity - common among
Scottish intellectuals - that had reacted by over-identification with European
cultures ...hence militant Great-English parochialism was a monster threat
ening everything' (p. 397). If we are interested in more than a recital of the
'muscular' logic, or otherwise, of his theory then this conditioning is also
important to understanding the tensions out of which his approach was
developed.
'Three Dreams' was the first of a series of iconoclastic articles, which
together now comprises the most frequently debated, contemporary marxist
theory of the nation. The responses from the non-marxist mainstream to
Naim's approach have been contradictory. Ernest Gellner believes Naim's
'concrete theory of nationalism ... to be substantially correct' , but is puzzled
as to how Nairn could think his theory was at all compatible with marxism.16
John Breuilly, to the contrary, says that 'Abstractly it is a plausible and
impressive argument. But it does not fit the facts. 17 Whichever is the case,
Nairn has become a figure of almost compulsory citation.Anthony Giddens,
in his second volume of A Contemporary Critique of Historical Materialism,
a study specifically aimed at exploring in dialogue with marxism the 'contours
15. Nairn, Break-up of Britain, 1981, quote from p. 397. All page numbers in the body of the
text will henceforth refer to this book. See also his 'British Nationalism and the EEC', 1971; The
Left Against Europe?, 1973; and The Enchanted Glass, 1988.
16. Ernest Gellner, 'Nationalism, or the New Confessions of a Justified Edinburgh Sinner',
1979, p. 270. Similarly Edward Tiryakian with Neil Nevitte calls Nairn's Break-up of Britain a
'brilliant analysis of the nationalisms of Britain'. See their 'Nationalism and Modernity', 1985,
p. 59.
17. John Breuilly, Nationalism and the State, 1982, p. 26.
Nation Formation und the Janus Faces of History 109
of a post-Marxist' interpretation of the nation-state, refers only to Nairn's
work when discussing the contemporary group of approaches written within
the framework of historical materialism. Giddens makes a couple of brisk
criticisms but then comments that Nairn's is 'The most illuminating account
of nationalism produced in recent times by an author affiliated with
Marxism.' 18 It is intended as a back-handed compliment.
The very mixed responses to Nairn's approach are in part a consequence of
the limitation that despite the voluminous writings which touch on the nation
question, none amounts to more than 'the scantiest outline' of a theory. 19 For
example, all that Horace Davis achieves in his book, ambitiously entitled
Toward a Marxist Theory of Nationalism, 20 is to show that marxism needs to
come to terms politically with minority and ex-colonial national cultures. A
second reason for Nairn's notoriety stems from the way in which he bridges
orthodoxy and the writings of those who have started to argue for its radical
reconstruction. Eric Hobsbawm's critique of Nairn is an instructive instance
of the neo-orthodox over-reaction to this. While Hobsbawm ostensibly pro
fesses the need for a continual rethinking of received marxist theory - 'above
all because the very development of world history changes the context, the
nature and the implications of "nations" and "nationalism'" - he flatly con
cludes that Nairn has made neither a useful nor a convincing contribution to
this development.21 Leaving aside for the moment the question as to whether
this is a sustainable criticism, it is made having only discussed Nairn's overall
theory in two footnotes.22 Hobsbawm's concern, however laudable, to defend
the practical politics of orthodoxy as hardly requiring serious modification,
thus leaves Nairn's theoretical approach largely unexamined.23
It is to such an examination that I would now like to turn. After briefly out
lining Nairn's theoretical position, the chapter broadens out to assess the
general implications of his and other contemporary marxist contributions for
the development of a workable theory of the nation.
At the centre of Nairn's theory is the concept of uneven development; the
'shambling, fighting, lop-sided, illogical, head-over-heels fact' of the uneven
development of capitalism. 24 This is tied to the premise that an adequate
18. Anthony Giddens, The Nation-State and Violence, 1985. p. 213. Compare Homi Bhabha "s
much more sympathetic use of Nairn in 'Anxious Nations, Nervous States', 1994.
19. Nairn, Break-up of Britain, 1981, p. 356, in modestly describing his own work.
20. Horace Davis, Toward a Marxist Theory of Nationalism, 1978. Peter Worsley did this m a
more interesting way over a decade earlier (The Third World, 1964).
21. Eric Hobsbawm, 'Some Reflections on "The Break-up of Britain'.. , 1977. p. 21.
22. Ibid., fn. 12 and 13.
23. Ibid., p. 21. See the similar comment by Pierre Vilar, 'On Nations and Nationalism·.
1979. p. 28. Ironically, despite his tone, Nairn is closer in particular but significant ways to the
orthodox base-superstructure argument than either Vilar or Hobsbawm. Cf. Eric Hobsba" m
'Some Reflections on Nationalism', 1972.
24. From 'The Modern Janus' first published in Ne,.· uft Review m 1975. reprinted ID !',;aim.
Break-up of Britain, 1981, p. 337. On uneven de\'elopment see also pp. 71 72, 961T.• 1().lff, 113.
134, 178, I 841T., 2021T., 2201T. 227. 229. 3181T.
110 Natfon Formation
theory of nationalism can only be initiated with world history as its frame
work of reference. Country-by-country analyses, he says, have already
succumbed to the ideology that human society essentially consists of discrete
nations. For a similar reason, NaM"n, like Poulantzas, rejects as mythology the
view that nationalism is internally determined, necessitated by either the
national market-economy and its leading class, as orthodox marxism would
have it, or by the will of the Volk, as idealist conceptions including even
Weber's have effectively assumed. 25
Nairn's theory unfolds as follows: in the beginning, before the conditions of
nineteenth-century uneven development, there were the 'historic'
nation-states of Western Europe: England, France, Spain and Portugal,
Sweden, Holland. The new forces of production and the military powers of
the new form of state swept the world (in Ernest Gellner's phrase) with the
devastating force of a tidal wave. They generated an imperialism of the met
ropolitan centres of Western Europe over the periphery: first Central and
Eastern Europe, then Latin America, and on to other continents. In the
peripheral regions, the elites were faced with overcoming their ambivalence to
this uneven process. They wanted the means of progress - factories, parlia
ments, schools - but they quickly found that it was only possible for a
minority to enter the kingdom of 'cosmopolitan technocracy' . Nairn thus
places intellectuals and the intellectually trained in the centre of the picture.
Out of the 'regions of intermediate social change' (Hroch), from the small
towns and rural areas of disrupted but still pre-industrial Europe, came the
new intelligentsia: modern, romantic, mobile, and from the petit-bourgeoisie
(p. 119). Rather than be left behind, the members of this newly awakened
intelligentsia c.9nsciously mobilized others against foreign domination in the
formation of a self-aware, cross-class community. They did this using the
particularities of their locale, their 'nationality' (for Nairn in inverted com
mas), and their inherited ethnos. 'The new middle-class intelligentsia of
nationalism', as his now-famous phrase has it, 'had to invite the masses into
history; and the invitation had to be written in a language they understood'
(p. 340). Thus:
Capitalism, even as it spread remorselessly over the world to unify human society
into one more or less connected story for the first time, also engendered a perilous
and convulsive new fragmentation of that society. The socio-historical cost of this
rapid implantation of capitalism into world society was 'nationalism'. There was no
other conceivable fashion in which the process could have occurred. (p. 341)
25. Ibid., pp. 332-333. These folklores of nationalism are, Nairn adds, 'not entirely wrong'.
They are as such an important set of 'clues towards whatever these forms are really about' (p.
334). Poulantzas criticizes the national market explanation as one-sided; as not explaining why
unification occurs at the level of the nation, and as expressing a 'profoundly empiricist and pos
itivistic conception of all the elements that are supposed to constitute the nation' (State. Power,
Socialism, I 980, pp. 96---97). See also Juan Gomez-Quinones, 'Critique on the National Question,
Self-Determination and Nationalism', 1982, p. 78. Alternatively, for Weber's position see 'The
Nation' in From Max Weber (essays from 1904-20) 1968, pp. 171-179, cf. p. 65.
Nation Formation and the Janus Faces of Hisrory Ill
At this intermission in the argument, Naim's critics reach for their knives.
The proponents of neo-orthodoxy conclude that Nairn has put 'Marxism at
the mercy of nationalism' and moved to 'change the ideology and undermine
the "science'". 26 However, they fail to take in Naim's underlying circumspec
tion that nationalisms do resist, but only to be transformed themselves in the
terms of the dominant industrialized countries. They miss the force of his
metaphor (used in a different sense than I have been employing it) that
nationalism is the modern Janus, with one face looking forward along the
passage to modernity but forced to endure violent upheaval, and the other
face desperately glancing backwards to the reassuring remnants of past tra
ditions. In Nairn's argument, nationalism is always ethically and politically
ambiguous. Ironically, this is the dialectic by which his nee-orthodox critics
also work: it calls to mind Marx's double-sided phrase that progress resembles
'that hideous pagan idol, who would not drink the nectar but from the skulls
of the slain'. 27
A further irony is that, like classical and nee-orthodox marxism, Nairn
tends to treat the original formation of the 'historic' nation and nation-state
as an unproblematic historical given. This is a slightly different point from
Benedict Anderson's aside that there is in Nairn the 'good nationalist ten
dency to treat his "Scotland" as an unproblematic, primordial given'. 28 But
together these points suggest that while Nairn has become relatively careful
not to repeat Marx's mistake of assuming the always-imminent death of the
nation-state in general, he still has not moved to emend the limitations of
Marx's approach to the birth of the nation.
Contrary to the accusations of his neo-orthodox critics, Nairn is very crit
ical of nationalism (that is, as distinct from nationality or nationhood). He is
in fact critical to the point that his analysis is overly wrapped up in the
metaphoric manner of diagnosing nationalism as a pathology involving irra
tionality, sublimation, neurosis, split personality, and cultural schizophrenia. 29
The use of psychologisms is not a major problem in itself; 30 as we shall see, his
friendly bete noire, Ernest Gellner, similarly engages in what can be over
looked largely as excesses of style effected for literary or political impact.
26. Hobsbawm, 'Reflections on "The Break-up of Britain'", 1977, p. 22. Also J.M. Blaut,
'Nationalism as an Autonomous Force', 1982.
27. Karl Marx, On Colonialism, (1850--88) 1976, p. 87.
28. Benedict Anderson, Imagined Communities, 1983. p. 85.
29. For example see Nairn, Break-up of Britain, 1981, pp. IOI, 129, 153. 154- 167. 169. 172,
177, 242, 288; and Nairn, Enchanted Glass, 1988, pp. 11, 87, 113, 128-129. 175 and so on.
Michael Lowy, among others, also slips into the language of nationalism as pathology. Sec his
'Marxists and the National Question', 1976, p. 99.
30. Although cf. Sarni Zubaida, 'Theories of Nationalism', 1978. p. 69. He says. I think over
critically, that Nairn shares with others like Perry Anderson and Immanuel Wallerstern a general
historicist teleology: '"Nations" seem to be historical super-subjects with the attributes ofa�ency
and action: they "mobilise", "aspire", "propel themselves fornard", "react", and they even ha,e
atavistic, irrational "ids" seething with traumas which explode periodically.' See also. Ronaldo
Munck, The Difficult Dialogue, 1986, pp. 145-146.
112 Ndtion Formation
However, in Nairn's case it is a problem in that by giving the impression of a
thorough-going psychoanalytic theory of the subjective it glosses over signif
icant gaps in his argument. In particular we find a lack of attention to the
original formation of nations ood nationality; a very narrowly conceived dis
cussion of social or ideological integration; evidence of the limitations of the
orthodox base-superstructure framework in theorizing the subjective and
explaining the centrality of the intelligentsia; and the absence of other than a
practical argument for assuming that 'ethically demarcated territorial state
hood continues to be inescapable, as the political structure of all foreseeable
development' and implicitly of all alternative politics (p. 371). Discussion of
these issues will be opened up in the next section by considering the first
Janus face that assumes rather than theorizes the primordiality of the ground
ing forms of human political association. Nairn is not alone in assuming the
category of historic nations. We should recall from earlier discussion that
Marx and Engels used the word nation to apply to polities, from the
Phoenician tribes to the still-to-be-unified land of imperially connected prin
cipalities, landgraviates and bishoprics called Germany. This will lead into the
issues of essentialism and primordialism. The following section takes up the
second face of historiography and the issues of modernity and cultural inven
tion. A further section, 'Past and Present', discusses the importance of a
synthesis of the two faces, and the chapter concludes with an interlude on
Nairn's use of the concrete-abstract distinction.
The original formation of nationality and nation
The search for Nairn's theory of nationality and nation has to begin between
the lines of his discussion of the 'original' nation-states. As was earlier out
lined, in the beginning before the conditions of uneven development there
were the historic nation-states in Western Europe. To use the language he
sometimes prefers, they were State-nations, in which nationality had played a
role quite distinct from what it would assume in 'nationalism proper'. What
I think he means is that pre-nineteenth century nationality was submerged
below the general possibility of being politically divisive or self-consciously
held. 31 Nairn says: 'Put at its most simple: they were in fact multi-ethnic
assemblages in which, through lengthy processes of conquest and absorp
tion , one or other nationality had established ascendancy (normally in
late-feudal times, through the machinery of absolute monarchy)' (p. 178).
While nationality is not here the primary subject of his concern, it is evi
dent that Nairn believes that although dominant polities prior to the
nineteenth century were states over and above being nations, at the same
time nationality was then already present as a primordial form of social
31. With qualifications this interpretation is borne out by Anthony D. Smith in his The Ethnic
Revival, 1981, ch. 4. However, Smith's definition of ethnic communities as a social group with a
sense of common origins and destiny appears to cut against it. Either way the notion of sub
merged identity is dubious.
Nation Formation and the Janus Faces of History 113
relation. 3 2 So that, for example, in his words, England was 'a country of
ancient and settled nationality' (p. 262) and the United Kingdom 'was the
first state-form of an industrialized nation' (p. 14). If we add to this, and read
backwards from another instructive comment - namely: 'Nationalism,
unlike nationality or ethnic variety, cannot be considered a "natural" phe
nomenon' (p. 99) - it becomes clear that he considers nationality to be
'natural' in inverted commas. It is 'natural' in the sense that the 'deeply
given' presents itself as natural with such force that only the inverted com
mas serve to remind us that it is nevertheless historical.
Does this mean, just as Althusser once accused most of his marxist con
freres, and post-marxism now accuses everybody including Althusser, that
lurking in Nairn's theory of the nation is that most insidious of methodolog
ical flaws - essentialism?33 The problem of essentialism is important to our
theme of the primordialist-modernist divide, and needs to be raised here
directly, if only because the emerging academic dominance of post-struc
turalist methodology threatens to rule out any discussion of the deep
historical roots of all social forms including those which ground the modern
nation. Armed with an overly exuberant, post-structuralist suspicion of any
form of Grand Theory it is all too easy to find the problem of essentialism in
Nairn. For instance, from the questionable premise that all who seek a com
mon socio-historical process to explain such a highly variable phenomenon
effectively surrender 'to the conceptual terms of the nationalist problematic of
the national "essence "' , 34 Sarni Zubaida throws a blanket of criticism over all
theorists from Nairn to Gellner. Zubaida's position is open to easy
counter-critique. 35 Nevertheless, in the midst of his uneven comments on
Grand Theory, he manages to throw up a telling question which continues to
confront both marxism and conventional theory: how without assuming the
presence of essential nations could nationality be said to constitute the fault
lines crossing the ancient social formations?36 Nicos Poulantzas poses the
question the other way round: 'What makes it possible for these seemingly
transhistorical elements to be articulated at the focal point of the modern
nation?' 3 7 Ernest Gellner wisely (and evasively) prefers to talk of
entropy-resistant cultural markers rather then pre-existent national or even
ethnic traits. 38 Tom Nairn's move to say that the nation is 'natural', that is,
natural in inverted commas, is a similar but less effective evasion.
32. See also Nairn, Enchanted Glass, 1988,pp. 170---171, 177, 182,213. 236, 307.
33. For a new tum of the screw see Norman Geras·s discussion, 'Post-Marxism', 1987. pp.
40---82: which turns the essentialist critique back against 'left" post-structuralists.
34. Zubaida, 'Theories of Nationalism·, 1978,p. 69.
35. In weakly acknowledging that the ideologies of nationalism 'share a common 1deolog1cal
field',the stridency of his disavowal of the possibility or necessity of broad theoretical work thus
rebounds upon itself. Nairn could ask what explains the commonality of this ·,Jeological field "'
36. Zubaida, 'Theories of Nationalism'. 1978,p. 69.
37. Poulantzas,Srate, Power. Socialism, 1980. p. 97. On this question see also John Ehrenreich.
'Socialism, Nationalism and Capitalist Development". 1983; and Smith. Th,• Erhnlf Rnii-ul,
1981,pp. 39-40.
38. See Nations and Nationalism, 1983, ch. 6.
114 ivrJtion Formation
While Nairn has no developed answer to the post-structuralist inquisition,
but rather than indicating an inevitable essentialism it attests to the fact that
he has yet to emphasize the political relevance of developing a theory of
those social formations of ea.rly modern history such as the monarchical
patria or the divisions of natio in the medieval universities and monasteries,
formations based on forms of association from which the nation later
emerged. 39 As Konstantin Symmons-Symonolewicz notes, there are only a
few brief disquisitions into this shadowy area.4-0 The levels argument is an
attempt to express in a non-essentialist way the dialectic of continuity and dis
continuity of prior social forms into the modern period. All that we need to
say at this stage in relation to Nairn is that his approach is limited to a (par
tial) theory of nationalism and to a standpoint from which to assess the
institutional politics of the modern nation-state. 41 But the broader problem
remains. And, while firstly the marxist emphasis on material conditions and
social being continues to be salutary, and secondly concepts such as mode of
production continue to be centrally useful, the orthodox base-superstructure
framework can offer us little help.
From the historic nation to nationalism as culturally invented?
Part of the problem is that although the national form is historically deter
mined it not only appears to be natural, basic and primordial, but in an
unexplained way crosses changing modes of production, specifically feudal
ism to capitalism. Within mainstream sociology this has given rise to a
primordialist tradition where nationality and ethnicity are treated as cultur
ally natural�or even biologically grounded associations. Within the marxist
tradition it has been considered sufficient to say that the nation is located in
history. (It is important to remember here that we are still talking about
nationality and nation rather than nation-state.) Stalin initially bypassed the
problem by distinguishing the nation as a historically constituted category
from the tribe as an ethnographic category (though why this should be the
case is itself not explained). But he then slips into treating nationality as a pre
national phenomenon and the problem asserts itself. 42 Otto Bauer attempted
a more synthetic approach. However, his definition of the nation as a cultural
community bound in common fate was derided as heresy, partly because in
trying to go a step further to specify how the nation was grounded historically
39. We need to take seriously the research of writers such as G.G. Coulton, 'Nationalism in the
Middle Ages', 1935; and Hans Kohn, The idea of Nationalism, 1944. Despite their tendency to
see ideas as the motor of history, the best contemporary writings on this are John Armstrong,
Nations Before Nationalism, 1982; and Anthony D. Smith, The Ethnic Origins of Nations, 1986.
40. 'National Consciousness in Medieval Europe: Some Theoretical Problems', 1981.
41. This is close to the conclusions of Andrew Orridge, while leaving out his belief that Ernest
Gellner adequately provides the other half of the story. See Orridge, 'Uneven Development and
Nationalism: 2', 1982, pp. 181-190.
42. See Joseph Stalin, Marxism and the National and Colonial Question, (1913-34) 1947, p. 13.
Nation Formation and the Janus Faces of History 115
he failed among other things to emphasize the by-then sloganized dictum that
the proletariat have no country. 43
More recently culture has become central to the debates. In the next chap
ter this will be given considerable attention; for the moment it is confined to
the notion of cultural invention. Despite the rise of considerable interest in
cultural questions, and for quite new reasons, culture continues to be treated
by many marxists as effectively epiphenomena!. This includes theorists who
decry the earlier stages of economic reductionism. In the new sense of the
word, culture is lifted onto a pedestal of recognition and yet in the same ele
vation it is reduced to the arbitrary construction of instrumentally managed
processes. 44 A number of contemporary marxists have with misplaced alacrity
embraced the argument that ideologies which project a national historical
antiquity are simply fabrications invented in the present. 45 This parallels the
ascendancy of the language of cultural invention underwritten by post-struc
turalism46 and also, in an odd congruence, by the line of conservative
sociology from Acton to Kedourie and Geitner.
It is in fact possible and, in the terms of the present text, crucial to hold
together both the historically grounded and culturally invented conceptions
of the nation. An example drawn from Hobsbawm and Ranger's book, The
Invention of Tradition, should make the issue clearer. There is little doubt that
the tartan kilt was first designed by an English Quaker industrialist well after
the Union of 1707, and that it was devised not to embellish the Highland tra
dition but to facilitate the transformation into industrial work. Furthermore
there is substantial evidence that clan differentiation by tartan pattern began
with the formation by the British government in the mid-eighteenth century
of Highland regiments enlisted to fight in the imperial wars. 47 However, all
this does not indicate that clan culture was an English or Lowland aristocratic
invention. It suggests that the forms of association around which it was mean
ingful to 'invent' a new means of symbolizing Highland and clan
differentiation were already existent. 48 Certainly intellectuals from clerics to
poets contributed to giving clan culture a new level of meaning; however, even
43. Marx and Engels' phrase from the Communist Manifesto; on Bauer see Ronaldo Munck.
·0110 Bauer: Towards a Marxist Theory of Nationalism', 1985.
44. This applies even to Philip Corrigan and Derek Sayer's impressive study. The Great Arch.
1985. While they argue that a revolution in cultural forms grounds the reformation of the state.
they also assert that the nation 'epitomizes the fictive community' (pp. 41T., 118. 195).
45. See for example Eric Hobsbawm and Terence Ranger, eds, The lm·ention of Tradirion.
1983. The language permeates Naim's latest book, The Enchanted Glass (1988. pp. 108, 111, 126,
168, 172, 173, 184, 187 and so on).
46. See for example Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari, Nomadology: The u-i1r Machine, 1986;
and going back to Friedrich Nietzsche, see pp. 49, 61-62, 160-163 in The Portable Nier:scl,e,
1985.
47. Hugh Trevor-Roper, 'The Invention of Tradition: The Highland Tradition of Scotland',
1983. On pre-1707 nationalism see Keith Webb, The Growth of Nationalism in Scotland, 1978,
ch. 2.
48. On the reconstitution of clan and kinship in the eighteenth century see Eric Cregeen. 'The
Changing Role of the House of Argyll in the Scottish Highlands". 1970.
116 N111tion Formation
here the 'invention of culture' argument is qualified by the long-run histori
cal consciousness of Scottish identity. In 1320 'Scottish' royal officials wrote
to the Pope arguing that baronial loyalty was owed not primarily to the King
of Scotland, but to the patriji itself. As Susan Reynolds comments, the
Declaration of Arbroath has been received by contemporary scholars with
curious historical cynicism - almost a sort of inverted nai'vete - which is determined
not to take any statement of feeling or principle at face value. But a work of pro
paganda, as this was, must have been intended to appeal to values and emotions
current at the time: the Scottish royal officil:tls who drafted the letter presumably
thought that ideas of collective political independence based on a single collective
identity would seem convincing both to the barons in whose name it was drafted,
and to the pope to whom it was addressed.49
Similarly in the late eighteenth century the Macphersons may have rewritten
'Scottish' history by treating 'Irish' ballads as if they were indigenous to
Scotland, but the question remains why the 'fabrication' was perpetrated. If
the primordialist face of Janus can hardly admit such fabrications, the second
face rarely bothers to ask that kind of question, and has no adequate way of
providing an answer.
Past and present
It is possible to synthesize the historically grounded and culturally invented
faces of history, but not as Nairn does by retaining both at the same time
without rewriting the terms of their synthesis. 50 When made explicit, a posi
tion such as Nairn's faces the danger of succumbing to the dichotomy of
essentializing rhe distant past and fictionalizing the present (and modern
past). The pre-modern past becomes that different country where people did
real things, had concrete relations and made unself-conscious history. The
present becomes a shallow layer of constructed artifice where all social action
is directed to accruing cultural capital. (There is also, as will be further dis
cussed in Chapter 7, the opposite danger that in synthesizing the historically
grounded and culturally invented faces of history, quite different forms of
human association are treated as a narrative, discontinuous or otherwise,
unfolding on a single plane with a relatively unchanging ontology.)
Like all half-truths the dichotomy of the faces of Janus has the ideological
force to take down even the most subtle theorist. The late Raymond Williams,
the Welsh-born writer who has been in the forefront of rethinking questions
of the determination of culture and the problems of the base-superstructure
49. Susan Reynolds,'Medieval Origines Gentium and the Community of the Realm',1983,pp.
385-386.
50. So that Nairn can say that 'Many new "nations" had to think away millennia of oblivion,
and invent almost entirely fictitious pasts' (p. 105). He can write, 'Europe invented nationalism',
and a paragraph later say that, 'This original formation of nationalism took many centuries. It
is a process deeply rooted in Europe's history' (Break-up of Britain, 1981, p. 310). For Nairn on
nationalism as invention see also pp. 121,141,166,168,174,215,228,301,304,310,323.
Nation Formation and the Janus Faces of History 117
framework, is a surprising victim. He argues that face-to-face relauons and
those relationships formed in local or even regionally placeable bonding are
real (he does not simply forget to put in the mandatory inverted commas all
through this discussion). They are 'of quite fundamental human and natural
importance' whereas 'the modern nation-state is entirely artificial'. an
imposed form initiated as a 'ruling-class operation', 'a willed and selected
superstructure':
It is capitalism, especially in its most developed stages, which is the main source of
all the contemporary confusions about peoples and nations and their necessary loy
alties and bonds. Moreover it is, in the modern epoch, capitalism which has
disrupted and overridden natural communities, and imposed artificial orders. It is
then a savage irony that capitalist states have again and again succeeded in mobil
ising patriotic feelings in their own forms and interests.51 (emphasis added)
Apart from being imbued with essentialist nostalgia for older modes of
community the real/artifice distinction (like the 'natural'/invented distinc
tion) repeats the problem of the unresolved faces of Janus. At the very least
it does not explain how an artificial imposition has so much power. As
Patrick Wright says, 'If the culture of the nation is only so much wool, then
the eyes over which it is pulled must belong to sheep.'52 There are sound rea
sons for agreeing with Raymond Williams that an alternative politics should
reject the ideologies of race and nation as they are projected currently.
Furthermore - and this is the key issue - we should reject them, as Williams
suggests, 'in favour of lived and formed identities either of a settled kind, if
available, or of a possible kind where dislocation and relocation require new
formation'.53 However, valorizing face-to-face relations as in themselves
more real than other forms of abstract community will not achieve this
desirable politics.
A theory of social forms which posited levels of social integration - from
face-to-face embodied associations connected through kinship and recipro
cal exchange, through to the more abstract extensions of community made
possible by such means of integration as administrative apparatuses or the
mass media - could with Williams criticize the subordination of locale and
place to the more abstract politics of the nation-state. But it would do so
without essentializing the past, or fictionalizing the present; without sacral
izing the local, or demonizing the global. The claim that the form of the
contemporary nation is grounded in long-run historical forms does not
imply that Indonesia, India or even France or England can be said to have
consolidated until quite recently as nation-states. By the same reasoning it is
understandable why the early nineteenth-century Javanese prince
Diponegoro could have no conception of the Indonesians or Dutch as a
51. Williams, Towards 2()()(), 1985. p. 184 with earlier quotes from pp. 180 181. 191 Cf his
novel Loyalties where in one brief passage he cuts through the intellectual nostalgia for the 're.ti
hfe' of the Welsh valley ( 1985, p. 247). See also Francis Mulhem's s)·mpathet1c but forceful cri
tique of Williams in 'Towards 2000, or News from You-Know-Where', 198-1
52. Patrick Wright , On Living in an Old Country, 1985, p. 5.
53. Williams, Toll'ards 2000. 1985, p. 196.
118 N!Jtion Formation
collectivity. It is also explicable why this prince who intended to conquer
Java, not liberate it, from the Dutch, is now elevated as a national hero.54
Nairn, despite his attachment to Scotland, has little to say about such
questions of ontological groullding.Perhaps it is indicative that other than
the preface to The Break-up of Britain the body ofthe text was written in cho
sen 'exile' from the land of his birth. Eric Hobsbawm similarly has until
recently tended to direct his attention elsewhere.55 He readily admits of him
self: 'I ...belong to a people of refugees [born in Egypt to an Austrian
mother] whose experience has been such as to make me still vaguely uneasy if
I don't possess a valid passport and enough cash to transport me to the near
est suitable country at short notice.' 56 On the other hand, Regis Debray has at
least broached the question ofthe ontological history out ofwhich the mode
ofassociation we call the 'nation' emerged.But he has taken this as a reason
for asserting the priority ofthe national as ifthe nation embodies the levels of
association from which, by its form, it is already abstracted.It has worrying
consequences for Debray's political logic.He says, 'I can conceive ofno hope
for Europe save under the hegemony of a revolutionary France', 57 and later,
heads off as President Mitterand's envoy to explain to the 'loyal French' sub
jects of the Pacific why they should accept nuclear detonations on their
islands. Ethical questions aside, it suggests that the Imperial Nation dies
hard. Between 1975 and 1991, 124 tests were conducted in the Pacific; in
1995 and against world opinion the new conservative president, Jacques
Chirac, presided over the resumption ofnuclear testing. In the context ofthe
possibilities for joint research and computer-simulated testing it was very
clear that what was at stake was old-fashioned national pride rather than mil
itary security. ·
What seems like just a theoretical question can thus very quickly be shown
to have important political implications.A theory and politics ofthe question
of human association has to confront centrally this issue of how the two
faces ofJanus can be integrated. Otherwise the one-sided accentuation ofthe
grounding historical forms ofthe nation can lead to a sophisticated version of
'my country, right or wrong' ...'my nation, good or bad'. Alternatively
emphasizing the modernity of the nation-state and the self-consciousness of
its invented traditions can lead to a politics cast only at the level of asking
what are the institutional requirements ofan alternative political practice and
how are the oppressive, homogenizing directions of the contemporary
54. Cited in Anderson, Imagined Communities, 1983, p. 19. Here he rightly says the very con
cept 'Indonesia' is a twentieth-century 'invention'. See also his other uses of the concept of
invention and the (somewhat unresolved) qualifications of the term, pp. 15, 122, 129, 142, 143.
Le Bras and Todd's work (L'Invention de Ia France written in I98 I) is an example of taking the
inventionist thesis past the point of usefulness: 'by rights,' they say, 'France should not exist'. It
was 'invented'. Discussed in Fernand Braudel, The Identity of France, 1988, pp. l03ff., cited on
p. 109.
55. Cf. his latest book Nations and Nationalism since 1780, 1990.
56. Eric Hobsbawm, 'The Limits of Nationalism', 1969.
57. Regis Debray, 'Marxism and the National Question', 1977, p. 41.
Nation Formation and the Janus Faces of History 119
bureaucratic state to be mitigated. It is this second emphasis which as I said
has become the front runner in theories of the nation and nation-state. Unless
we take this theorizing a stage further, the next generation, if it is still around,
will look back in frustration and repeat Nairn's words, that the theory of
nationalism represents our great historical failure. They will attend com
puter-mediated conferences on this issue, plug into the extended means of
communication offered to the well-to-do of the meta-national global village,
and muse nostalgically about the relative richness and concrete solidity of the
past while bemoaning the continuing neo-national violence as atavism that
will soon fade away.
An interlude on Nairn's concrete-abstract distinction
Before concluding this chapter, I would like briefly to comment on Tom
Nairn's use of the terms abstract and concrete. They are obviously central
concepts in the present work, but I have not included a fuller discussion of
Nairn's use of them because, at least in his writings directly on the national
question, they are only touched upon in a couple of passing references.
Drawing upon Marx's notion of the abstract individuals of capitalism and
J.H. Shennan's phrase, the abstract state, Nairn writes of 'the truly modern
doctrine of the abstract or "impersonal" state which, because of its abstract
nature, could be imitated in subsequent history' (p. 17). It is too brief a ref
erence to draw out anything conclusive, though it does seem somewhat
problematic. It appears to be imbued with an implicit diffusionism (that is,
that ideas can be more readily diffused merely by virtue of their abstraction as
ideas), and it is followed a couple of pages later by an overly functionalist
view of class practice in the suggestion that the 'abstract political order' was
a mechanism invented by the bourgeoisie to overcome the chaos of competi
tive anarchy, just as it 'generated the cohesive power of nationalism to hold
itself together' (pp. 24--25). I would have left these fragments to lie unnoticed
except that in his more recent book, The Enchanted Glass, the abstract
concrete distinction becomes a recurrent motif. Again, the theoretical status
or import of the terms is not made explicit, but this time they pervade his
argument. 58
In The Enchanted Glass Nairn sets out to explain how the contemporary
British monarchy has maintained the 'neo-tribal loyalty' of the people of
Ukania (his name for the 'spirit-essence' of the United Kingdom). 'A per
sonalized and totemic symbolism,' he says, 'was needed to maintain the
a-national nationalism of a multinational (and for long imperial) entity: and
"the Crown" could effectively translate identity onto that "higher plane". 'l9
58. See Nairn, Enchanted Glass, 1988,pp. 30,48,58, 63,69,90,94,97,106. 117,138,139, 140,
141,144,160,188,205,209,212,216,229,233,273,275,278.287,288,298,314,316,355,357.
360; all references to this sense of the abstract.
59. Ibid.,p. 11.
120 Nation Formarion
What Nairn faces in attempting an explanation is an entity which accrues its
power as much through the disembodied realm of the mass media (recall the
cry of the Scottish crofter cited earlier) as out of the longer-run institutions of
agency-extension; an entity which moreover relies upon recurrent traces of
face-to-face contact: the Touch; the Intimate Wander through adoring
crowds; the elusive ordinariness of the Royal Family; the face-to-camera
to-face addresses of the Queen broadcasting from her own home; in short,
'the human presence of Royalty with its concrete familial guarantee of all
being well in the longer run'. 60 In the language of the present text, royalty thus
gains its power through the same historical processes as does the nation - that
is, constituted in a contradictory intersection of levels of abstraction - except
that the cultural power of royalty manifestly focuses upon particular per
sons as the concrete embodiment of abstracted power. That is its strength and
its weakness.
Nairn too connects royalty and nation, but he reduces the Ukanian obses
sion with royalty to an aspect of a unique Anglo-British national identity. He
writes:
What the theatre of Royal obsession sustains is not (real) personality, therefore, in
the ordinary sense of individuality or idiosyncrasy. It projects perfectly abstract
ideas of 'personality', which are received and revered as some kind of emblem. In
other words it is an abstract cult of the concrete - an ideology of the (supposedly)
nonideological ... deeply and recognizably English ...a quite decipherable and
quite important aspect of national identity. 61
Phrases such as the 'abstract cult ofthe concrete' reverberate in exciting ways
back into the constitutive abstraction thesis, but there are important differ
ences between our respective positions which, if clarified, might also serve to
clarify what the present text is not doing. A few more illustrations of Nairn's
use of the concept of abstraction will make this task easier. The following pas
sages are taken from The Enchanted Glass:
For Top People, clearly, the Monarch is an 'institution' - close indeed to being the
institution when questions of soul and national essence arise. Under threat, it is not
just the individuals but what they mean that counts: the abstract, sacred thing
somewhere in the background.
2
Though quite true to say [that the British state] centres on a sense of 'State'
grandeur and continuity, this has never been the abstract or impersonal apparatus
which post-Absolutist Republicanism fostered in Europe ... Its awesomeness and
'near hypnotic impact' depend upon this ostensible identification of State with
society: what one could also call ...the metaphoric family unity of a Shakespearian
(or pre-modern) nationalism.
60. Ibid., p. 215.
61. Ibid., p. 48. See also p. 10: the underlying structures of 'the Royal passion-play ... are (in
my view) merely the structures of nationalism'.
Nation Formation and the Janus Faces of History 121
3
The whole development of nationalism since the 18th century has tended towards
the fusion of two generally recognized levels of nationality: the personal (concrete?)
or 'ethnic' identification on the one hand and formal (abstract) or passport citi
zenship on the other. But in the British Isles (itself a piece of phoney geography)
such coalescence is impossible.
4
An anti-abstract ideology (or non-theoretical theory) is compelled to focus upon
the ultra-concrete: visible things (or persons) radioactive with an otherwise ineffable
significance. This poetry of national existence - intuitive decency; 'our way of
doing things' - contrasts automatically and quite naturally with the foreign, the
modern, the extreme, the impersonal and the noxiously abstract.
5
Analysis of pathologically concretized or anti-abstract customs and ideology has
taken off from what that order itself has consecrated as 'reality': fetishized ·experi
ence' as the incarnation of the human. 62
The differences between the present text and Nairn's Enchanted Glass are
methodological rather than political. They can be summarized as follows.
In using the levels of abstraction metaphor, Nation Formation attempts to
overcome the problem of dichotomizing the concrete and the abstract.
2 It seeks to avoid treating the concrete as that which is palpable, material
or real, over and against the abstract as that which is artificial and imper
sonal, is structured as ideas or is a phantom somewhere in the back
ground.
3 Similarly, though the present text distinguishes between historical forms
of nationality, it does not set up that comparison as a distinction between
pre-modern, 'real nationality' 63 and modern nationalism with the British
case posited as fitting somewhere in between as either 'pseudo-rational
ism'64 or a metaphoric unity which draws upon the (ethnic) pre-modern
and yet, via the persons of Royalty, fosters community from above.
4 Without denying the possibility of self-conscious artifice, the present text
avoids the dichotomous distinction between the real and the phoney, the
invented, the pseudo and so on.
5 Rather than accede to Nairn's version of the novelty of the British situa
tion (except in the sense that all nation-states have unique histories)
Nation Formation attempts to show how nation-states in general depend
for their naturalized, concrete awesomeness upon intersecting levels of
integration, framed by the most abstract level but never in a way that can
resolve the contradictions of that intersection.
62. Quotes from ibid., p. 58, 90, 174, 94. 216.
63. Ibid., p. 176.
64. Ibid., p. 183.
122 N•tion Formation
With Nairn as the focus, the present chapter has examined some of the prob
lems inherent in contemporary marxist approaches to theorizing, firstly, the
original development of nationality and national formation, and, secondly,
the emergence of nationalism.and the nation-state. The confusions which
surround the theorizing of the emergence of national formations stem in part
from the lack of a non-essentialist theory of trans-epochal or trans
mode-of-production levels of social integration. Such a theory would, it is
hoped, allow us to say that while nations do not come into being until they
are lived as such (or at least abstractly recognized as such, usually in the first
instance by intellectuals or persons lifted out of the face-to-face) the social
forms which ground national formation are already lived prior to the gener
alization of this new sense of historicity.
In these terms, England is in no way 'a country of ancient and settled
nationality'. It is rather a land which particularly after the Norman conquest
had a remarkably continuous history of (relatively) settled institutional unity.
The possibility of looking back over this 'unity' and framing it as a national
unity entails, according to this argument, an abstraction of time and space, of
history and territory, and thus a constitutively different subjectivity.
Unfortunately, in theorizing this relation between the objective and subjective,
marxist theories of the nation continue to be plagued by the limitations of the
base-superstructure framework. Furthermore, the other side of the argu
ment can be reasserted: the processes of abstraction do not simply involve
inventing the past; culture is not an epiphenomenon of processes of social
construction. Certainly people give the past meaning in terms of contempo
rary sensibilities. But to talk of this projection as fabrication or invention is to
miss that it too.is bound by (or rather constituted by) the conditions and sub
jectivities otJts time - as is the ideology of cultural invention. It is not just by
chance that there are lines within conservative and liberal sociology, orthodox
and neo-marxism, structuralism and post-structuralism, all drawing upon
similar conceptions of the invention of culture. The next chapter will attempt
to take this argument a step further: it begins by introducing the concept of
the 'rise of the cultural' and ends by criticizing the way that some contempo
rary theorists from Ernest Gellner to Fredric Jameson have asserted the
emergent dominance of the cultural.
6
Nation Formation and the
'Rise of the Cultural':
A Critique of Liberal Sociology
At the very same time that men [and presumably women] become fully
and nervously aware of their culture and its vital relevance to their vital
interests they also lose much of the capacity to revere their society
through the mystical symbolism of a religion. So there is both a push and
a pull towards revering a shared culture directly, unmediated in its own
terms: culture is now clearly visible, and access to it has become man's
most precious asset. Yet the religious symbols through which, if
Durkheim is to be believed, it was worshipped, ceased to be serviceable.
So - let culture be worshipped directly in its own name. That is national
ism.
Ernest Gellner, Culture, Identity and Politics, I 987
It did not however fail to produce those social conditions which lead to
nationalism, i.e. to the identification of men with a High Culture which
defines a large, mobile, anonymous mass of people, who however visual
ize that abstract society in the imagery of a concrete community.
Ernest Gellner, Encounters with Nationalism, 1994
While the nation continues to be an ontological formation of central, though
changing, importance, it is currently beset by a two-fold development in the
poverty of theory. On the one hand, a growing number of theorists are talk
ing as if the nation-state is now an anachronistic carry-over from the modern
past, fast becoming irrelevant in their version of the postmodern, post
sovereign, borderless world. On the other hand, for many people the nation
is taken for granted, disappearing into its commonsense obviousness: outside
the cognoscenti, the concepts of the nation, this society, and this community
are often used as coterminous. Note how the definite article works in all
those cases. When I tell acquaintances and colleagues. including academic
colleagues, that I am doing some work on the nation it is invariably assumed
that I am referring to some aspect or other of 'this country of ours'. Both ten
dencies militate against adequately explaining the consolidation and
transformations of the national formation. Studying the nation has engen
dered the submergence of theory under empirical or ideological verities,
124 Nb.rion Formarion
rather than the coherent integration of historical particulars and political
arguments into an approach which links social form and social subjectivity.'
In one important way, as the previous chapter began to document, this is
changing. The 1980s and 1990s have seen a new wave of attention being
given to the national question. 2 It coincides with the heralding by some the
orists of what will be called here the rise of the cultural. The phrase will be
used with a trilateral reference: firstly, in connection with theoretical prac
tice, it refers to the way in which questions of human subjectivity and human
existence - from the new emphasis on the.body and sexual difference to the
recent taking apart of the constitutive notion of reality - are being pushed by
social commentators into the glare of unremitting examination. It suggests
the emergence of a social form which 'insists' upon its grounding condi
tions being theorized. It is expressive of this emergence that one feels
compelled to place 'reality' in inverted commas.3 Secondly, in relation to
political practice, the phrase refers to the increasing grounding of politics in
the affirmation of subjectivity: 4 hence the maxim, 'the personal is political'.
Thirdly, it concerns the way in which, within late capitalism, social life is
more and more experienced by people as being relatively fluid and 'cultural'.
If Weber's phrase, the 'age of subjectivist culture', or Marx's, 'all that is solid
melts into air' , discussed earlier, were once the prognoses of abstracted intel
lectuals, they now have hit 'the person in the street' with a vengeance. The
contemporary sensitivity to material and social constraints on lifestyle is the
obverse side of this same process, and quite distinct from the way in which
cultural boundaries were once historically lived as God-given or socially
natural.
As a sign gfthe changing times recent studies commonly acknowledge the
difficulty and unresolved nature of the national question. However, Tom
Nairn's oft-quoted statement that, 'the theory of nationalism represents
Marxism's great historical failure' , 5 or Ralph Miliband's that, 'in no other
I. See Anthony D. Smith, 'Nationalism and Classical Social Theory', 1983; and "'Ideas" and
"Structure" in the Formation oflndependence Ideals', 1973.
2. Significant contributions include those of Benedict Anderson, Homi Bhabha, John Breuilly,
Partha Chatterjee, Walker Connor, Ernest Gellner, Anthony Giddens, Liah Greenfeld, Eric
Hobsbawm, John Hutchinson, Jim Maclaughlin, Ronaldo Munck, Tom Nairn, Cornelia
Navari, Ephraim Nimni, Hugh Seton-Watson, Anthony Smith and Leonard Tivey amongst
many others.
3. On 'reality' see Jean Baudrillard, 'The Precession of Simulacra', 1983, pp. 3-47; and Gerry
Gill's critique of that position in 'Post-Structuralism as Ideology', 1984. The 'rise of the cultural'
can also actually have the opposite effect from that of generating new ways of theorizing what
remain substantive questions: in being pushed into relief, categories like the nation can appear to
dissolve into relief, categories like the nation can appear to dissolve into pure invention. However
insightful the post-structuralists may be, setting up the nation as a phantom meta-narrative
will not take us very far. To take an example close to 'home', Andrew Lohrey's 'Australian
Nationalism as Myth', 1984, provides one of the earliest examples in Australia of the limitations
of this approach.
4. Russell Jacoby, Social Amnesia, 1975, ch. v, 'The Politics of Subjectivity'; Anthony Giddens,
Modernity and Self-Identity, 1991; Seyla Benhabib, Situating the Self, 1992.
5. Tom Nairn, The Break-up of Britain: Crisis and Neo-Nationalism, 1981, p. 329.
Nation Formation and the • Rise of the Cultural' 125
area of the human sciences has the neglect been so marked', 6 cannot be taken
at face value. They are now more indicative of the fundamental inadequacies
of approaches to a theory of the nation than of a simple neglect. We should
perhaps recall Poulantzas' comment, cited in Chapter 3, about our under
estimation of the difficulty of theorizing the nation. Eric Hobsbawm's
decades-old comment is still relevant: 'Nationalism is probably the most pow
erful political phenomena of our century .. .but analysis has found it
remarkably hard to come to grips with.' 7
While the rise of the cultural starkly confronts many writers with the
importance of understanding the nation-state and nationalism, it certainly
has not forced the abandonment of narrow empiricism. To the contrary, the
unimaginable complexity of the question, among other considerations, has
paradoxically sent the majority of studies in the direction of sequestering the
possibilities of a general social theory. The mainstream journal Canadian
Review of Studies in Nationalism, 8 first published in 1974, carries a plethora
of reviews of recently written, narrowly focused books.One of the Canadian
Review's frequent contributors and himself author of several books on
nationalism, Boyd Shafer, entitled one such article, 'If only we knew more
about Nationalism' . 9 It begins by extending upon the tradition of Rupert
Emerson's comment that, 'what we do not know or have taken for granted
without adequate evidence adds up to an impressive body of ignorance and
uncertainty which is all the more dismaying because of the frequent failure to
face up to the limitations of our knowledge' .10 Shafer says that despite his
own 'incomplete' bibliography of thousands of writings he remains quite
ignorant. While laudably modest his is still predominantly a statement of
empirical gaps and an empiricist call for verifying research.
The other tendency in responding to the complexity of the national ques
tion is to fall back on a kind of volitional subjectivism without explaining the
constitution of that subjectivity. To take an example from the mainstream.
one writer who has achieved almost compulsory citation in the bibliograph
ical procession, Hugh Seton-Watson, is 'driven to the [Weberian] conclusion
that no "scientific definition" of a nation can be devised; yet the phenomenon
has existed and exists'.He is reduced to the tautology: 'All that I can find to
6. Ralph Miliband cited in Horace B. Davis, Toward a Marxist Theory of Nationalism, 1978.
p. I. A non-marxist who has made a similar claim is Ernest Gellner: 'Nationalism is notoriously
one of the most powerful forces of the modem world, but oddly enough one which has received
relatively little systematic treatment by sociologists.' See also his 'Nationalism', 1981. p. 753.
7. Eric Hobsbawm, 'Some ReOections on Nationalism', 1972.
8. Other journals specifically in the area include Nationalities Papers, published semi
annually by the Association for the Study of the Nationalities (USSR and East Europe); Europa
Ethica: Problems of Nationalities (Vienna); and the recently established Nationalism a11d Ethnic
Politics (vol. I, no. I was published in 1995). Compare these to the Ne11· Na11on, first published
in January 1891 in the United States, edited by Edward Bellamy. It 'aimed to bnng about the eco
nomic equality of citizens, which is known as nationalism'() I January, 1891).
9. Boyd Shafer, 'If Only We Knew More about Nationalism', 1980.
10. Rupert Emerson, From Empire to Nation, 1960. pp. 89 90. and cited m Shafer. 1b1d ..
p. 197.
126 Nalion Formation
say is that a nation exists when a significant number of people in a community
consider themselves to form a nation, or behave as if they formed one.' 11 It is
an inadequate subjectivist definition with a long heritage.12
The fact that Seton-Watson joins a long parade of others emphasizing the
willed character of national identity is however, significant. In 1882 Ernest
Renan gave his noted lecture at the Sorbonne, 'Qu'est-ce qu'une Nation?', in
which he said: 'A nation is a great solidarity, created by the sentiments of the
sacrifices which have been made and of those which one is disposed to make
in the future. It presupposes a past; but it resumes itself in the present by a
tangible fact: the consent, the clearly expressed desire to continue life in com
mon.' 13 Despite clear transformations in thinking through the nineteenth to
the twentieth centuries, Renan's conception reflects a common view held by a
tradition of nationalists and theorists alike.14 Certainly some went further.
Johann Bluntschli's massive A/lgemeine Statslehre (1852) defined the nation
state as a morally organized, masculine personality: 'History ascribes to the
State a personality which, having spirit and body, possesses and manifests a
will of its own.'15 In contemporary writings it seems to be more a fall-back
position than an assertion.16 The limitations of the line from Renan to Seton
Watson, embodied emphatically, practically, in nationalist writings from, say,
Jules Michelet or Giuseppe Mazzini to late twentieth-century figures as
diverse as Mishima Yukio or Fidel Castro, underscores the necessity for a
materialist, social relational account, but one which instates the centrality of
the subjective. In short, we need to keep to the fore the theme of the sub
ject-object relation. To put it more graphically, we need to take seriously the
fact that people are prepared to die for their nation, and not simply because
of a willed natioJ1al spirit or a deluding ideology.
In partially recognizing the limitations of one-sided subjectivism, most
11. Hugh Seton-Watson, Nations and States, 1977, p. 5.
12. In the thirteenth century, long before nation-states were even envisaged, Marsilius of
Padua argues that states were united by common will, rather than, as most of his contemporaries
suggested, by a naturally occurring unitary form (per formam aliquam unicam naturalem).
Discussed in Susan Reynolds, 'Medieval Origines Gentium and the Community of the Realm',
1983.
13. Ernest Renan, 'What is a Nation?', 1882, reproduced in Hans Kohn, Nationalism: Its
Meaning and History, 1965, p. 139; also in Homi Bhabha, Nation and Narration, 1990.
14. Hans Kohn writes: 'The most essential element [in the formation of nations] is a living and
active corporate will. Nationality is formed by the decision to form a nationality'. See his The
Idea of Nationalism, (1944) 1956, p. 15.
15. Johann K. Bluntschli, The Theory of State, (1852) 1895, p. 22. The notion of the state as
having a 'personality' is more abstract than the feudal view of the regnum or patria as having an
abstract 'body'. Otto von Gierke (Political Theories of the Middle Age, 1900, pp. 67-73) shows
how the idea of personality is missing from medieval political theories of the body politic.
Moreover in doing so the preconceptions of the late nineteenth century speak from between the
lines of von Gierke's analysis: his implicit point is that the medieval theorists should have been
able to give to an abstract 'Fictitious Person' a distinct personality and will.
16. The phrase 'a fall-back position' is deployed with ironical allusion to its use by Elie
Kedourie (Nationalism, (1960) 1993, p. 75). In the context of criticizing the way nationalists fall
back on the concept of 'individual will' he goes on to affirm Renan's definition cited above.
Nation Formation and the 'Rise of the Cultural' 127
contemporary writers retire like Seton-Watson into working their way
through problems of definition, into devising classificatory schemes of dif
ferent types of nations or national movements, or into documenting
particular nationalist uprisings and national histories. Seton-Watson's grand
survey is one of the more encyclopedic. While those types of studies remain
important, we might want to say, reworking Emerson's comment, that our
body of ignorance is passing from impressive to overwhelming. It has been
consequently the assumption of this book that a theory of the nation requires
as integral to its starting point an adequate theory of social formations and
associated subjectivities. Social formation, as previously discussed, is taken
here to have various possible levels of definition. At one level of theoretical
abstraction it has been defined as the broad, structured conjuncture of social
relations of a particular society conditioned and integrated through the
means and relations of communication, production, organization and
exchange, practised in and across its boundaries. However, the emphasis of
the present discussion has been on a more abstractly conceived definition:
social formation as an intersection-in-dominance of levels of integration. As
a way of going further into the problem I propose to spend some time look
ing at the work of someone within the Weberian-Durkheimian lineage who as
part of the new wave of attention has attempted a comprehensive and direct
contribution to a theory of the nation. First, let me summarize a couple of the
assumptions of this sociological tradition.
Out of the traditions of Weber and Durkheim
Contemporary theorists who work out of the lineage of Max Weber and
Emile Durkheim start from the basic distinction between Traditional and
Modern societies. It has been called the Great Divide and is relevant to one
of the continuing themes of the book, the primordiality-modernity ques
tion. While the present discussion calls into question all dichotomous or
ideal-type theorizing, it is important to acknowledge that the Weberian
Durkheimian lineage has thrown up a number of irreducible issues concern
ing the difference between social formations.
To briefly recapitulate: Durkheim distinguished between mechanical and
organic forms of solidarity, while Weber's ideal-type methodology distin
guished three relationships of political organization - traditional, charismatic
(always a transitional phase) and rational-legal (the modern side of the Great
Divide). Expressions of this same broad tradition can in turn be located in a
series of typological contrasts written by those living through what Polanyi
has called the Great Transformation: 17 Otto von Gierke's contrast between
Genossenschaft and Herrschaft; Henry Maine's status/contract distinction;
and Ferdinand Tcinnies' writings on Gemeinschaft um! Gcsellsclwft ( 1887)
17. Karl Polanyi, The Great Transformation: The Pnlirical and Economic Ortxins of Our Time,
(1944) 1957.
128 Nmion Formation
are amongst the most prominent discussions of the Great Divide. As Robert
Nisbet points out, Marx was the only writer of this period who dissented sig
nificantly from the value implications of the contrast. 18
Drawing on these classical tru.:orists, mainstream sociology posits the exis
tence of three stages of the modernization process: tradition, transition,
modernity. (Notice that this model still assumes a basic dichotomy. 19)
Nationalism and the nation as a way of organizing the relations between
people is seen as an outcome of the 'transitional phase'. Similarly, national
ists, like Daniel Lerner's archetypal character 'the grocer of Balgat' are
transitionals, persons in mental and physical motion. As Anthony Smith
concludes of one line out of this complex lineage of theorists:
The functionalist perspective on modernisation starts ... from the suggestions in
Rousseau, draws heavily on Durkheim's analysis of complex society, and ends by
echoing Weber. The key to the argument is the idea of the 'imperatives' of a com
munity of tradition ... To survive painful dislocation, societies must institutionalize
new modes of fulfilling the principles and performing the functions with which ear
lier structures can no longer cope. To merit the title a new 'society' must reconstitute
itself in the image of the o/d.20 (emphasis added)
Reconstitution in this 'image of the old' and the harking back to traditional
myths refers in the functionalist argument to an adaptive process under
gone by new societies because of legitimation crisis. 21 It is not as evocative a
phrase as it first promises. Accordingly, the ideology of nationalism is theo
rized as that ideology which is best suited to bridging the tradition by
adapting primordial ties to modern complexities, to use Edward Shils' influ
ential phrase. In the language of Talcott Parsons, it unites particularistic with
universal orientations. Clifford Geertz gives a similar but less functionalist
account of wfiat he calls the integrative revolution. 22 However, to go into any
more detail at this stage would not add significantly to ground already cov-
18. Robert A. Nisbet, The Sociological Tradition, (1966) 1970, p. 48. See his discussion of the
various conceptions of community versus society in ch. 3; also in his The Quest for Community,
(1953) 1971.
19. The three stage model still maintains the dichotomy of traditional/modern: simple/com·
plex, despite the broad implications of the later work of Durkheim and his pupil and colleague,
Marcel Mauss, particularly Mauss' The Gif1.· Forms and Functions of Exchange in Archaic
Societies, (1925) 1974. This dichotomy still pertains to approaches which expanded upon the
concept of transition; take for example Walt Rostow who, in Stages ofEconomic Growth: A Non
Communist Manifesto, 1960, suggested an ideologically value-laden, five-stage evolutionary
scheme: (I) traditional; (2) preconditioning; (3) take-off; (4) the drive to maturity; (5) the age of
mass-consumption.
20. Anthony D. Smith, Theories of Nationalism, 1983, pp. 49-50.
21. This limited perspective on the reconstitution of the old is common to the so-called con
ventional development theorists. One of the more interesting embellishers of the
structural-functional framework is Daniel Lerner, The Passing of Traditional Society, 1958. See
also Lucien Pye, Politics, Personality and Nation Building, 1962. The big contemporary name in
the 'theory of adaptation' is James Rosenau. See his The Study of Political Adaptation, 1981.
22. Talcott Parsons, The Social System, 1951; Edward Shils, 'Primordial, Personal, Sacred and
Civil Ties', 1957; Clifford Geertz, The Interpretation of Cultures, 1973, chs 9 and 10.
Nation Formation and the · Rise of the Cultural' 129
ered by Smith's excellent critical discussion of structural functionalism, the
'mass society' model and related approaches to modernization theory in his
Theories of Nationalism (I 983). Moreover, a theory of the nation is hardly
the central preoccupation of such approaches. Smith's commendable capac
ity to wring relevant theoretical substance out of them gives a misleading
impression as to the level of formulation and direct application to a theory
of the nation they had reached. It reflects more his original aim in the first
edition of 1971 to 'demonstrate the close links between nationalism and
"modernisation"' . 23
Until recently, with some notable exceptions, the question of the basis for
the constitution of the nation was not in itself taken up within this tradition
as a pressing problem. In many ways it could quite legitimately be argued that
it would be solved when the problems of social integration and social change
were dispensed with. On the other hand, I would suggest, merely echoing
many other critics, that the functionalists' way of dealing with social integra
tion and social change is part of the problem, thoroughly impairing any
subsequent attempts to develop a theory of the nation.
There is one writer out of the Weberian-Durkheimian lineage who has
done more than any other to rethink the categories of the theory of nation. It
is probably of no coincidence that he is of Jewish-Czech background an<l has
spent most of his life lifted out of his natus into cultural 'exile'. I am referring
to the well-known European philosopher, social anthropologist, social theo
rist, historian of ideas and doyen terrible, Ernest Gellner. 24 Gale Stokes
maintains that, 'of all the writers on nationalism, Gellner is the only one
who has produced a full-scale theory' . 25 She may be right, but this chapter will
argue less fulsomely that although his writings are insightful they remain
paradigmatic of the limitations of liberal orthodoxy. It will argue that his
approach is predicated upon an ultimately unsustainable theory of the history
of societal forms. 26
Ernest Gellner: a partial break with orthodoxy
For the most part Gellner's work has been well received even when criticized.
The radical Weberian, Anthony Smith, calls it 'one of the most complex and
original attempts to come to grips with the ubiquitous phenomenon of
nationalism', while Gavin Kitching's review in the marxistjournal Capital and
Class sympathetically describes Nations and Nationalism as a fine book of
23. Smith, Theories of Nationalism, 'Preface to the Second Edition', 1983, p. ,x.
24. For a general discussion of Gcllner see John A. Hall, 'Ernest Gellner', ch. 6 of h,s
Diagnoses of Our Time, 1981; and Perry Anderson, A Zone of E11gug,•m,•nt. 1992, ch 9. (With the
publication of The Ethnic Origi11s of Nations, 1986, the work of Anthony Smith must be consid
ered to be of comparable importance to that ofGellncr.)
25. Gale Stokes, 'The Underdeveloped Theory of National"m', 1978. p. 154
26. Gellner is more interested in societal forms tribal society, agrarian ,ocicl). mdusmal
society - than in particular social formations.
130 NaritJn Formation
trenchant clarity.27 Tom Nairn, who is himself probably the most influential
contemporary marxist theorist of the nation (Benedict Anderson and
Anthony Giddens are qualified in their relation to any marxist lineage) calls
Gellner's 1964 chapter 'Nationalism', 'the most important and influential
recent study in English' . Except for the undeveloped and only passingly rele
vant criticism of Gellner for engaging in 'a sort of compromise between
historical materialism and commonsense' - and thus not asserting the moral
ambiguity of nationalism - Nairn, like Michael Hechter, John Hall, Andrew
Orridge and T. V. Sathyamurthy, uncritically incorporates some of the central
tenets of Gellner's thesis into his own position. 28 Ironically both the
Durkheimian-Weberian and the New Left marxist (discussed in the previous
chapter) fail to deal adequately with a related dilemma: both fail, for differ
ent reasons, to put together the nation as an objectively constituted social
form/social subjectivity.
From 'savage' to 'cultivated' cultures? 29
The suggestive strength of Ernest Gellner's position arises out of its broad
theoretical sweep. In other words, in having a social theoretical attitude he
has more to say than the safer, perhaps more accurate, empirical studies, and
as such his position is thoroughly taken apart. Before turning to a detailed
critique I will try to summarize his argument. History for Gellner has three
fundamental stages or ideal types of social formation: the hunting-gathering,
the agrarian and the industrial.3° Because it is a necessary condition for the
development of� nation that the state has a taken-for-granted existence it is
27. Smith, Theories of Nationalism, 1983, p. 109; Gavin Kitching, 'Nationalism: The
Instrumental Passion' , 1985. By way of comparison see also Boyd Shafer's 1984 'Review of
Gellner's Nations and Nationalism, where he comments that 'This one might be a beginning of an
overall [theory of nationalism], though I am never quite certain of what Gellner's explanation
explains' (pp. 141-142). For a series of criticisms aimed as shots in the dark see Partha Chatterjee,
Nationalist Thought and the Colonial World, 1986.
28. Nairn, Break-up of Britain, 1981, pp. 96 and 342. Also pp. 99, 133, 317, 338, 358.Gellner
is only backhandedly kind to Nairn. Gellner's 'Nationalism, or the New Confessions of a
Justified Edinburgh Sinner', 1979, see Nairn's work as admirable in so far as it farewells marx
ism. For the uncritical use ofGellner see Michael Hechter, Internal Colonialism, 1975, pp. 36-43;
John A. Hall, Powers and Liberties, 1986; A. W. Orridge, 'Uneven Development and Nationalism:
2' , 1982. TV. Sathyamurthy, Nationalism in the Contemporary World, 1983.
29. These terms are taken from Ernest Gellner's extended botanical metaphor: culture as
savage, wild, low, spontaneous; distinguished from culture as cultivated, garden, high, nourished
and national. See his Nations and Nationalism, 1983, p. 50.
30. These are his 'three great stages of man' (ibid., p. 114). Gellner assiduously manages to
avoid the use of terms like 'feudalism' and 'capitalism' . At one point in critique of the marxist
position he refers to 'capitalism' as 'an overrated category' (ibid., p. 90). In Thought and Change,
1964,Gellner, for example, prefers to use Walt Rostow's normatively deployed phrase, the stage
of high mass-consumption (p. 166). While the subtitle of that writer's book proclaims its anti
marxist stance, Gellner's writings, at least up until the past few years, have been a series of
non-marxist manifestos. With Encounters with Nationalism, 1994, his stance softened.
Nation Formation and the 'Rise of the Cultural' 131
by definition not possible to talk of the emergence of the nation in pre
agrarian or tribal, hunting-gathering societies. By the middle or agrarian age
the state is optional.3 1 Coevally with this possibility for political centraliza
tion, a new class of specialized, literate clerics effect a cultural-cognitive
centralization. Thus according to Gellner, restricted literacy causes a split
between the 'great' and the 'little' traditions. At the level of the 'little' or
vernacular-based tradition, the 'petty communities of the lay members of the
society' are laterally differentiated and culturally drifting. 32 It follows that in
the agrarian age the determinants of political boundaries are distinct from
those of cultural boundaries. Given Gellner's argument that the nation
comes into being with fusion of the taken-for-granted state apparatus with a
relatively homogeneous culture, then, even if nationalism had 'been invented
in such a period its prospects of general acceptance would have been slender
indeed' 33 (emphasis added). With industrialization comes a new division of
labour. This is related to a number of developments, but most crucially to the
mobility of persons across the old, context-bound 'little' communities
through, firstly, the 'functional requirement' of a mobile work-force, and sec
ondly, the (abstracting) tendency towards universalized literacy in a
generalizable language. A homogeneous 'high culture' comes to pervade and
dominate social life, sustained primarily through a national education and
communication system. It can only be held together, he says, by the nation
state.
Even when described at such a high level of generality the strengths and
weaknesses of Gellner's position start to become apparent. For present pur
poses, discussion will centre predominantly on problems and shortcomings.
Discussion of Gellner's first fundamental stage of human history, the pre
agrarian, need only be brief for his own treatment of it, particularly in Nations
and Na1ionalism, is perfunctory. However, it is integral to his argument that
the development of nations would be impossible during the pre-agrarian
epoch. So that while the notion of the pre-agrarian appears only analytically
relevant in its use as a starting point for comparison to later 'enriched' cul
tural stages, it actually has to carry a heavy theoretical superstructure. It is
relevant for us because it is indicative right from the very beginning of weak
ness in this type of approach to a theory of social integration. When Gellner
says that:
31. Nations and Nationalism, 1983, p. 5. Gellner has a tendency to use either anthropomorphic
and/or voluntaristic terms in describing cultural-structural connections. As he acknowledges in
attempting to define the 'idea of the nation· his approach has two elements: (I) the 'cultural';
namely the necessity of a shared culture; and (2) the 'voluntaristic'; namely, that 'nation, are the
artefacts of men's convictions and loyalties and solidarities' (p. 7). With regard to the use of
anthropomorphisms, Gellner continues the practice for literary eITect while reluctantly and
gently acknowledging that it should be avoided. See ibid., p. 5 I.
32. Ibid. Gellner is not altogether consistent on this. Compare his comments on participatory
communities: 'they may have their local accent and customs, but these tend to be but vanants of
a wider inter-communicating culture containing many other similar communities· (p. 14).
33. Ibid., p. 11. The notion of 'invention' will be taken up later
132 Ndtion Formation
Cultures, like plants, can be divided into savage and cultivated varieties. The savage
kinds are produced and reproduce themselves spontaneously, as parts of the life of
men [sic) ... wild systems of this kind (in other words, cultures) reproduce them
selves from generation to generation without conscious design, supervision,
surveillance or special nutrition: .. 34
or, when he compares the elaborated communications code of the industrial
age to the restricted 'context-bound grunts and nods'35 of 'backward sav
ages', it could be concluded that he is producing, despite attempts to the
contrary, an ethnocentric, elitist, teleological, functionalist and idealist ver
sion of the Great Divide. Numerous passages could be marshalled in support
of such an assessment, but it is a misplaced conclusion. It misses out on the
ironical style and provocative richness of Gellner's approach.
Leaving aside excesses of style there are still, none the less, substantive rea
sons for concluding that Gellner's work lacks an adequate account of social
integration, both with regard to tribal or reciprocal exchange societies and
'modern' or late-capitalist societies. The pre-agrarian is portrayed in Nations
and Nationalism as a form of social life in its most natural and spontaneous
state: 'wild systems', he says, can be compared with 'a natural species which
can survive in the natural environment'. 36 Although it may appear that
Gellner here is relying upon a Janus faced dualism between the 'natural'
and the 'artificially produced' (his terms), other aspects of his approach
suggest a modernist anti-primordialism. There is a pervading Durkheimian
ghost in the Gellnerian schema which rejects the notion of natural, primor
dial spontaneity. Tribal societies, integrated in mechanical solidarity, are in
these terms seen as highly structured, closed systems. To see whether Gellner
can elude th� tension in his work we have initially to return to his earlier
writing.
Structure, culture and the new subjectivity
In Thought and Change, Gellner makes the conventional, indeed necessary,
analytic distinction between structure and culture. His next move is however
34. Ibid., p. 50. The notion of society-at-large as a wilderness which required cultivation
merged incidentally alongside the use of the verb 'to civilize' in the seventeenth and eighteenth
centuries. In the 1760s Les phi/osophes preached about the human act of civilizing 'as the method
to transform the savage wilderness of society into a designed, orderly formal garden' . See
Zygmunt Bauman, 'On the Origins of Civilization: A Historical Note', 1985. For more detailed
parallels to Gellner's language see Lucien Febvre, A New Kind of History, 1973, pp. 219-257.
35. Gellner, Nations and Nationalism, 1983, p. 51. See also p. 33. Here, in making the distinc
tion between 'elaborate' and 'restricted' codes, Gellner is drawing on a historically specific and
oversimplified version of Basil Bernstein's distinction between linguistic codes. One could imag
ine Gellner approvingly quoting Bernstein when the latter says that, 'the type of social solidarity
realized through a restricted code points towards mechanical solidarity whereas the type of sol
idarity realized through elaborated codes points towards organic solidarity. (Bernstein, Class,
Codes and Control, 1974, p. 147 and passim).
36. Gellner, Nations and Nationalism. 1983, p. 51.
Nation Formation and the 'Rise of the Cultural' 133
quite dubious. 37 It is related to our object-subject theme and has crucial sig
nificance for his theory of the nation. In face-to-face societies, structure,
narrowly conceived by Gellner as the social positions, roles and relation
ships, is theorized as primary. Structure is the 'substance' which is merely
reinforced by culture, the latter being defined as the style of being and expres
sion or the manner in which one communicates. 38 Shared culture, he
maintains, 'is not [in face-to-face societies] a precondition of effective com
munication'. (There is little to be gained from pausing to ponder how culture
can be simultaneously the manner of communication and not necessary for
communication - it is possible because of a sliding definition, but more crit
ically it arises out of problems we will have to come back to later.) In modern
societies, on the other hand, Gellner argues that the relative importance of
structure and culture reverses: 'In modern societies, culture does not so much
underline structure: rather, it replaces it!'39 He is thus heralding the rise of the
cultural and a new emphasis on subjectivity.
Through these analytic moves Gellner is attempting, even if unsuccess
fully, to deal with major issues implicit in classical and contemporary
accounts of social integration: that is, how to theorize various social for
mations as being constitutively different. There is strong reason to argue
that there is a qualitative difference between those societies constituted pri
marily in the face-to-face (where persons are, to use Gellner's phrase, set in
place by a frame of fairly stable relationships), and those societies in which
face-to-face contact can no longer be said to be the dominant constitutive
level of social integration. 40 In the latter setting, social relations at the level
37. Sathyamurthy argues to the contrary that it is a move that 'is absolutely crucial to a suc
cessful analytic examination of the concept of nationalism' ( Contemporary World, 1983. p. 72).
Similarly, John Breuilly, despite his extensive criticisms of Gellner for other failings, treats the
move as Gellner's most significant contribution to theorizing the nation. See Breuilly's
'Reflections on Nationalism', 1985. Phillip Rawkins uncritically uses Gellner's structure/culture
distinction as the 'platform' for his article, 'Nationalist Movements within the Advanced
Industrial State: The Significance of Culture' , 1983.
38. Gellner, Thought and Change, 1964, pp. 154, 155. See also Nations and Nationalism, where
in trying to bypass the problem of his initial definition of culture as 'a system of ideas and signs
and associations and ways of behaving and communicating' by suggesting that we look primar
ily 'at what culture does' (I 983, p. 7), he falls into the trap of reifying culture as an acting
medium in itself Later, after leaving the concept 'deliberately undefined·. he says reductively that
'an at least provisionally acceptable criterion of culture might be language· (p. 43).
39. Thought and Change, 1964, p. 155. In one way Nations and Nationalism replicates this
argument. For example Gellner writes: 'Culture is no longer [in industrial society) merely the
adornment, confirmation and legitimation of a social order which was also sustained by harsher
and coercive constraints; culture is now the necessary shared medium, the life-blood or perhaps
rather the minimal shared atmosphere, within which alone the members of the society can breathe
and survive and produce' (1983, pp. 37-38). But in another way it contradicts it: 'The roots of
nationalism in the distinctive structural requirements of industrial society are very deep indeed'
(p. 35).
40. This statement of a qualitative difference is not the same as setting up a dichotomous vie"
of history. See Anthony Giddens, Poll'er, Property and Srare, 1981. pp. 157 168 on the method
ological distinction. The issue of qualitative difference between different forms of society 1s
relatively uncontroversial, but for a dissenting view see Mary Douglas, Natural f>'.rmhol.,. 1970.
134 Na/ion Formation
of the face-to-face are fragmented and constituted more abstractly. The
subjects of a nation are not held together because they will all at some time
meet each other. But whether or not the more abstract form of integration
underpinning the national formation is less structured is quite a different
question.
While this is not the place to attempt a full-blown discussion of the form of
the new relation, a few comments are needed to contextualize the problem
with which Gellner is dealing and to highljght the extent to which he falls
short of an adequate explanation. An explanation couched in terms oflevels
of integration arguably provides some insights into the national question
which overcome the problems of the culture/structure inversion. To summa
rize the earlier exposition, it was argued that the nation came into being with
the intersection of a number of distinguishable levels of social integration: the
relatively 'concrete' face-to-face, clearly a necessary dimension of any con
ceivable society; the agency-extended - where apparatuses such as religious
'bureaucracies', and later, predominantly state bureaucracies, schools, mili
tary forces etc., and their agents such as postal workers or census collectors,
connect people across increasing extensions of time and space; and the dis
embodied - namely the more abstract extensions ofsocial relations possible
with, for example, the initially agency-bound circulation of commodities and
capital across a mass market, or as Benedict Anderson has emphasized, the
new means of communication beginning with print and reaching unprece
dented heights with the contemporary mass-communication industry. As the
first two levels historically have become reconstituted in relation to the dom
inance of the third, most abstract level, people subjectively have experienced
a relative 'lib�ration' from many of the bounded limitations of face-to-face
association, and apparently a liberation from structure per se. Structure in this
sense has not been replaced by culture; rather the cultural-structural form has
changed.
It is partly understandable that Gellner takes the line he does. With the
emerging dominance of relations of disembodied extension, a universalizing
form of interchange 'presents itself' as post-structural. Nevertheless, writers
such as Benedict Anderson, Geoff Sharp and Anthony Giddens41 have in
more fruitful ways begun to theorize this abstraction of social relations and
its structure of apparent structurelessness. They point to the new means of
abstraction and distantiation such as the mass media as being simultane
ously the structural means of social extension and integration, a structure
which constitutes subjects in a way that forces us to be increasingly self-active
in constructing our identities. Gellner by contrast, even in his most recent
writings, Encounters with Nationalism (1994), hardly alludes to the informa
tion revolution. In a sense, theorists such as Anderson, Sharp and Giddens
41. Giddens, Power, Property and State, 1981 and his The Nation-State and Violence, 1985;
Benedict Anderson, Imagined Communities, 1991; and Geoff Sharp, 'Constitutive Abstraction
and Social Practice', 1985.
Nation Formation and the 'Rise of the Cultural' 135
emphasize with Gellner the breakdown and fragmentation (or rather, and this
is an important restatement of Gellner's terms, the reconstitution of prior
modes) of social integration. But none of them makes the mistake of trying to
theorize the transformation between different forms of social relations by an
analytic inversion. 42
Problems flow through from this methodological standpoint of Gellner's.
If structure is defined as that which determines one's relationship to others -
for example, kinship is structural in societies he calls 'primitive' - then why
are not the new determinants of social relations in contemporary societies
also structural? Moreover, Gellner says at one point in his essay
'Nationalism' in Thought and Change, that: 'Modern societies are not quite
as lacking in structure as they are sometimes depicted. Bureaucracy is the
kinship of modern man.' 43 This is strange given the overall argument of that
essay, but his subsequent qualification of this leads to even more confusion.
Gellner writes that unlike in a kinship network, in modern societies persons
can divest themselves of their ascribed roles 'as of an overcoat: the wider
society lacks either legal or ritual sanctions for enforcing them' 44 (emphasis
added). He will have to yet again qualify this last evocative statement, but
before he does it is worth pointing to its immediate implications. The state
ment implicitly reinstates culture - previously defined by him as 'manner,
conduct, ritual, dress and so forth' , and which you'll remember was earlier
said to be a dispensable appendage to structure within primitive societies -
back into a necessary relationship to the structure of those societies. His next
qualification in the same paragraph contradicts the overcoat metaphor. He
says: 'The rigid ascription of roles takes place within organizations ['the
kinship of modern man'], but men are fairly free to choose and change their
organizations.' 45 And even here Gellner notes economic constraints to
choice.
It takes a while to think through why Gellner would argue for such a prob
lematic device as the structure/culture inversion. But the first step of a
possible explanation is relatively simple: the terms, culture and structure, are
for Gellner descriptive as well as (or even prior to being) theoretical concepts.
Therefore, in Gellner's gender-specific language, when the structured ascrip
tion of roles breaks down to the point where 'a man is a man' then. ipso
facto, the cultural has replaced structure as the basis of social integration.
42. Anton Zijderveld (The Abstract Society, 1974) gets himself into a parallel but opposite
position to Gellner. Theoretically he argues for the replacement of'cu/tura/ imegrativn based on
"mechanical solidarity "' by 'srrucrura/ imevation based upon "organic sohdanty'" (p. 69) but
then a few pages later he contradicts himself. arguing that ·such uniform realities as castle.
estate, or class, which give a society a strict structure, arc con,p1cuously absent in pluralist soci
ety' (p. 72).
43. Gellner, Thought and Change, 1964, p. 154.
44. Ibid., p. 155. Cf. Zijderveld, Abstract Society, 1974. who "rites that \\loving between the
institutional sectors, the modern individual IS compelled to change roles hke the Jaclet, of hi,
wardrobe' (p. 71 ).
45. Gellner, Thought and Change. 1964.
136 N£1tion F'ormwion
Recent theories of the 'subject' have criticized the assertion that the new indi
viduality heralds in the person as person as overly simplifying.46
To pursue that line now would be to lose track of the issue of social inte
gration. Besides, Gellner is do�g his argument a disservice. It is part of his
unnecessary sententiousness. When he says modern society turns everyone
into a cleric of the high culture, it is as misleading as Donald Horne's claim
that we are all intellectuals. 47 Nevertheless, to the extent that both point to the
reconstitution of the form of subjectivity and central importance of intellec
tual training, they cannot just be dismissecf.
For Gellner, when a society appears to be unstructured, it is necessarily
held together by a common culture:
If a man is not firmly set in a social niche, whose relationship as it were endows him
with his identity, he is obliged to carry his identity with him, in his whole style of
conduct and expression: in other words, his 'culture' becomes his identity. And the
classification of men by 'culture' is of course the classification by nationality. 48
Gellner is here only describing the phenomenal, the appearances of the
change. Certainly the seeming paradox of the nation arising in conjunction
with the individuation of person is analytically resolved, but it is also too
neatly bypassed. It does appear on the face that the contemporary modern
individual is not structured into society and from this comes Gellner's (ini
tially) bold analytic inversion.
In his latest writings Gellner has implicitly revised the basis of his position.
He seems to have finally drawn back from positing an inversion when he
says: 'T he national and often nationalist state, is a precise example of ... [the]
replacement of one structure by another; and that it cannot be explained by
invoking historical events alone, but only by highlighting the difference
between the two contrasted structures.'49 On the face of it this is a major
emendation. It appears to dull the force of the foregoing critique. My argu
ment, in positing constitutive structural levels, would now it seems only want
to qualify Gellner's statement by suggesting that while the social form is
qualitatively different the change involves not the replacement of one struc
ture by another, but the reconstitution of 'prior' levels and the emerging
46. Such theories range across the methodological spectrum. Louis Althusser, Lenin and
Philosophy, 1971; Rosalind Coward and John Ellis, Language and Materialism, 1977, chs 5 and
6; Anthony Giddens, Central Problems in Social Theory, 1979, ch. I; Julian Henriques et al.,
Changing the Subject, 1984; Benhabib, Situating the Self, 1992. On the other hand, for an exam
ple of a statement of the same quality as Gellner's, though this time with the added problem of
being ahistorical, see Graham Little, Political Ensembles, 1985, p. 14. He says, 'There is a third
form of social relations, the Ensemble, in which freedom and authority are reconciled because
people interact with other people as people' (original emphasis).
47. Donald Horne, The Public Culture, 1986. A theory of the significance and changed sub
jectivity of intellectual groupings is crucial to a theory of the nation. For a Weberian position see
Anthony D. Smith, The Ethnic Revival, 1981, ch. 6; and for a marxist position see Nonie Sharp,
'Nationalism and Cultural Politics', 1976.
48. Gellner, Thought and Change, 1964, p. 157.
49. From 'Nationalism and the Two Forms of Cohesion in Complex Societies', in his Culture,
Identity and Politics, 1987, pp. 12-13.
Nation Formation and the · Rise of the Cultural' 137
dominance of a new structural level. When examined more closely, however,
Gellner's position has become more theoretically confused. Given that struc
ture is defined by him as the 'relatively stable system of roles and positions' , 50
and, secondly, given that he argues that social position (i.e. structure) in mod
ern society is fluid and mobile, he is either effectively contradicting himself
viz. structure is replaced by 'a structure' where structure is breaking down
or he is employing two quite different definitions of structure, one of which is
never made explicit. Gellner still wants to argue for the rise of culture, and
while this is often described in compelling ways, it is increasingly apparent
that he requires a new theoretical basis for sustaining his description.
When Gellner then attempts to elucidate the positive determinants of the
changed mode of integration further problems emerge: firstly his approach
tends at times to be empirically misleading (I will give an example in a
moment), and overall, at least when he tries to summarize his argument, it
tends to be empirically reductive. Gellner's narrative is laced with insightful
generalizations but it is reductive in so far as it conceives of two basic pre
dominant carriers of change: the transition to industrialism through a
persistently changing division of labour, and the subsequent development of
an all-embracing education system. Although industrialism is adduced to be
fundamental for the change to the national formation, Gellner's recent writ
ing has come to acknowledge the qualifications of the Czech researcher,
Miroslav Hroch. In a study of Eastern and Northern Europe, Hroch found
that the original development of nationalist movements was in areas in which
industrialization was not of direct importance. 51
Gellner is right to conclude that, 'This finding does not destroy the theory
linking nationalism and industrialisation' , 52 however the problem is that he
fails to incorporate this insight into the body of his theory. At times Gellner
acknowledges the relevance of other factors such as the mass media and
commodity circulation, but they are left as additions to the structure of his
argument. This leads to empirically misleading claims such as his suggestion
that the minimum size for a viable unit which can, to use his words, manu
facture its subjects, is determined by the minimum size of an independently
viable education system. For it not to be tautology the concept of viability has
to be theorized.
A rationale for Gellner's contradictory portrayal of pre-agrarian social life
as both spontaneously reproduced, and as highly integrated in a mechanical
solidarity can now be suggested. The former characterization refers to cul
tural life and the latter to structural. But this is hardly satisfactory. And since
the question was first asked as to whether Gellner could elude the contradic
tion the problems have compounded. These criticisms, I think. cast in doubt
the very foundations of Gellner's theory.
50. lbid.
51. Gellner, Encounters, 1994, ch. 14. Sec the discussion of the s1gmficancc of Hroch"s research
m Eric Hobsbawm, 'Reflections on Nationalism', 1972.
52. Gellner, Culture, Identity and Politics, 1987, p. 25.
138 N«tion Formation
The following section delves further into the issue of social integration
and the problem of understanding differentiation within a social whole. It
leads into a discussion of Gellner's argument for a single epistemological
space in industrial societies. � subsequent section, 'Uneven Development
and the Cultural Boundary', discusses boundary demarcation as an aspect of
our theme of the changing ontology of space and time. Each of these sections
is set within the broader theme of the relation between the structure of the
lifeworld (Habermas' phrase) and the subjectivity of national being (namely
the object-subject theme).
Gesellschaft as mass society and culturally bounded
To return initially to old ground, despite Gellner's threefold theory of stages
a basic (neo-Durkheimian) distinction is being made between traditional and
modern societies: both the pre-agrarian (simple) and the agrarian (complex)
come under the heading of traditional societies; the movement then within
this category is from simple to complex. The influence on Gellner's theory of
the Durkheimian understanding of the transformation of mechanical to
organic solidarity or Tonnies' Gemeinschaft to Gesellschaft is apparent here.
As Gellner approving says, the Durkheimian approach posits that society
develops in the general direction of increasing complexity, differentiation
and thus interdependence and functional complementarity. 53
But we have to add a complicating dimension. Gellner is equally drawn to
the 'mass society' thesis, which, he maintains, asserts that contrary to the dif
ferentiation thesis our society tends towards increased 'standardization,
conformity, uniformity, in brief, a mass society' . He thus asks, 'How can two
theories, which assert such diametrically opposed propositions, both appear
so plausible and so illuminating?' 54 It is a question which, at least on the sur
face, affords for his position an easy analytic synthesis.
Most certainly Gellner is here referring to the Weberian routinization of
society argument and the approach running through Ortega y Gasset to
William Kornhauser, 55 rather than, say, to the Frankfurt school contribu
tions to the 'mass society' debate. That is, he is engaged in putting together
the two sides within the Durkheimian-Weberian paradigm. This is said not to
damn it: despite the apparently easy amalgam of Durkheim and Weber in
mainstream sociology (particularly in structural-functionalism), their coming
together still entails tensions. Moreover the tension is not limited to that tra
dition. From a quite different perspective, Jean-Fran�ois Lyotard is grappling
53. Gellner, 'Scale and Nation', I 974, p. 142. See p. 148 for an example of the positing of a clear
dichotomy of traditional and modem. He does however criticize Durkheim for grouping 'advanced
industrial civilizations' and 'industrial' society together under the heading of organic solidarity
without making a distinction within this wider category. See Nations and Nationalism, 1983, p. 27.
54. Gellner, 'Scale and Nation', 1974.
55. See William Kornhauser, The Politics of Mass Society, (1959) 1965, passim; Daniel Bell,
The End of Ideology, (1960) 1965, ch. I; and Smith, Ethnic Re,•ival, 1981, pp. 58--64.
Nation Formation and the 'Rise of the Cultural' 139
with an analogous problem when he is careful to pre-empt objections to his
analysis of the "'atomization" of the social into flexible networks' as seeming
to be 'far removed from the modern reality, which is depicted, on the con
trary, as affiicted with bureaucratic paralysis'. 56 Marxism has dealt with the
problem by conceiving of societies as structured in contradiction. Thus
Raymond Williams' concept of mobile privatization, 57 for example, actively
embraces the contradiction of differentiation or atomization within stan
dardization and conformity. Gellner's argument takes a different route. It
begins by making a series of contrasts.
Gellner maintains that in the contrast between pre-agrarian society (small
and therefore poor (sic]) and modern society (large and therefore likely to be
rich), the most apparent and salient difference is that the former is constituted
in the similarity of its parts, vertically as well as horizontally, and the latter is
constituted in differentiation. However, he says, we can set up a differently
contrasting dichotomy; that is, between agrarian and modern. In this com
parison Gellner suggests that modern society indisputably comes out as
standardized and 'drearily homogenous' . We are witnessing the end of 'char
acter, individuality, uniqueness'. 58 Leaving aside both the way in which it
contradicts other statements of his about a new (subjectivity of) individuality,
and the dubious manner in which the contrast is made, it allows him another
flourish before coming to the core of his position.
Gellner dismisses, with good reason, one possible synthesis of the 'incom
patible' descriptions. It posits that the path from 'simple tribal societies to
complex civilizations' includes an initial movement towards greater differen
tiation which then at a particular conjuncture reverses that direction. He says
rather that diversification has increased all along this evolutionary pathway,
and, crucially, that it has become different in kind. Society has become diver
sified over both space and time. This proposition is illuminating but
unfortunately more limited than it sounds. It does not allude to the multiple
levels of the reconstitution of time and space such as discussed by Anderson,
Giddens, Lyotard, Sharp, or Alfred Sohn-Rethel, nor to the insights for his
tory or geography method offered by, for example, Wolfram Eberhard,
Norbert Elias or Fernand Braudel, Robert Sack or R.J. Johnston. 59 Gellner is
56. Jean-Francois Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition, 1984, p. 17.
57. He has used the terms in various places including: Raymond Williams, Tele,·ision.
Technology and Cultural Form, 1974, pp. 19-31; and 'Problems of the Coming Period', 1983.
58. Gellner, 'Scale and Nation', 1974, p. 142. Compare this position with approaches which
emphasize a new level of individuality and a relative Ouidity of identity such as Lasch's The
Minimal Self, 1985. However, again Gellner's is more pertinently a rhetorical statement to accen
tuate the contrast, for ironically he could agree with much of Lasch's argument.
59. To the works of writers already cited can be added the bibliographical details of others:
Alfred Sohn-Rethel, Intellectual and Manual Labour: A Critique of Epistemolog y , 1978; Femand
Braudel, 'Divisions ofTime and Space in Europe', section I of The Perspecti1·eoft/1e ll'or/d, 1984,
Robert Sack, Conceptions of Space in Social Thought, 1980; R.J. Johnston. Geography and tire
State, 1982; John Urry and Derek Gregory. eds, Soda/ Relations and Spatial Srructurt•.,, 1985;
and David Landes, Re>'olution in Time, 1983; David Hooson, ed., Geography and Satwnal
ldeniity, 1994.
140 Nmion Formation
saying that the new division of labour entails not only a spreading out of dif
ferent skills and specializations (over space), but also that it requires that
people flexibly adjust to changing employment needs (a mobility of persons
over space and time). One is retllinded of the evidence put forward in Vance
Packard's descriptive work A Nation of Strangers, and of the subverting of
International Business Machines' acronym, IBM, to mean 'I've Been Moved'.
Gellner is making an important point in linking these changes to the forma
tion of national subjectivity but at this stage in his writing it is still a limited
theoretical proposition.
A homogenized cultural space?
In Nations and Nationalism, Gellner takes the analysis further to refer to an
epistemological reformation of social space in industrial societies: 'By the
common or single conceptual currency I mean that all facts are located within
a single continuous space.' 60 At one level this might be accurate; in a more
comprehensive sense it is misleading. That is, while it may be correct that a
dominant culture of meaning reaches across a national space, to imply that
knowledge becomes located on one continuous coherent plane leads to
insurmountable problems of accounting for what this book has described in
terms of the various levels of social life. 61 Elsewhere Gellner contradicts his
argument for a single continuous space when he talks of an epistemological
split between the ironic cultures of the lifeworld and the world of scientific
and philosophical enquiry. 62 But even this does not seem sufficient to allow
for the full complexity of knowledges either across particular national cul
tures or held--in-the practical and reflexive consciousness of any particular
individual. Rather than following Gellner's notion of an epistemological split
the present text has used the language of levels in (contradictory) intersection
to evoke this complexity. As was argued earlier, face-to-face relations are a
relatively irreducible level of social existence contributing to a complexity of
social meaning which cannot be explained simply by reference to the domi
nant culture: this is so, even as face-to-face interaction is overlaid and
reconstituted in the context of more abstract levels of integration.
60. Geitner, Nations and Nationalism, 1983, p. 21. Compare this with Lyotard's discussion of
the transition from customary knowledge as condensed, timeless, narrative through scientific
knowledge to a third phase, the plurality of 'language games' in postmodernity (Postmodern
Condition, 1984). Gellner's position is closer to Claude Levi-Strauss' two phase contrast between
'bricolage' and 'science' (The Savage Mind, (1962) trans. 1966), yet Gellner's view of scientific
knowledge and practice at times approaches Lyotard's description of the third phase: science is
the 'mode of cognition of industrial society'; 'It offers no guarantee of stability, it is morally
meaningless and respects no hierarchies' (Thought and Change, 1964, p. 179).
61. This point alludes to a similar discussion in Sharp, 'Constitutive Abstraction', I 985, pp.
59-61. On the question of the dominant culture see for example Raymond Williams, Marxism
and Literature, 1977, particularly section II, chs I, 6-9.
62. Ernest Gellner, Legitimation of Belief, 1974, pp. 191-200.
Nation Formation and the 'Rise of the Cultural' 141
Gellner's approach also flattens social structure conceived of in classing
rather than epistemological or integrationist terms: for example, he writes
class out of the history of late capitalism. Keeping class in the picture is
important but does not solve the first problem. Some world systems theo
rists, who from a different perspective (marxist and aware of class
contradictions) similarly emphasize a generalized division of labour, unfor
tunately also tend to collapse ontological-structural levels. In world systems
theory it is capitalism rather than Gellner's modernization that sweeps all
behind it. 63
Gellner is characteristically half-aware that there is more to it than positing
a single cultural space. 64 The metaphor does not suggest the complexity of life
within that space, but he handles the issue by making an additional remark
(discussed in a moment) which is in an unexplained tension with the first.
None the less, it is crucial that the original proposition is carried, for he ulti
mately wants to say that 'the unification of [peoples'] ideas in continuous and
unitary systems is connected with their re-grouping in internally fluid, cul
turally continuous communities', 65 namely, nations (emphasis added). It is
crucial to Gellner being able to handle the notion of the boundary as the
locus of identification for the new subjectivity. It is critical to initiating an
explanation of how it is possible to conceive of the mobile division of labour
as being partially bound within the edges of the nation-state (that is, one
aspect of what the present text has referred to as an extension or, more gen
erally, an abstraction in time and space).
His theory cannot, however, adequately handle the problems that flow
from his very perceptive insights. It is starkly shown up in relation to tradi
tional societies. On concurrent pages we find the following assertions:
In a traditional social order, the languages of the hunt, of harvesting, of various
rituals, of the council room, of the kitchen or harem, all form autonomous sys
tems: to conjoin statements drawn from these various fields. to probe for
inconsistencies between them, to try to unify them all, this would be social sole
cism or worse, probably blasphemy or impiety, and the very endeavour would be
unintelligible.
63. To anticipate their rejoinder, it is not sufficient to rely on the concept of'uneven develop
ment' to explain complexity as do both world systems theory and Gcllncr's form of
modernization theory. See Roger Dale, 'Nation Stale and International System: The World
System Perspective', 1984. For an interesting yet still inadequately voluntaristic allempl to
'account for the trajectories of globalization in a multi-dimensional fashion' see Roland
Robertson and Frank Lechner, 'Modernization. Globalization, and the Problem of Culture in
World-Systems Theory', 1985. They approvingly refer to Gellner's work as pointing lo the mod
ern state as 'heavily involved in the production of a "high" culture', and thus as implying the
necessity of theorizing a world system which 'requires' cultural divisions (p. 110).
64. For a Gellnerian attempt to handle this problem an anempl which also cclcct1cally
draws on 'cultural' marxists such as E.P. Thompson and Raymond Williams sec Phillip
Rawkins. 'Minority Nationalism and its Limits: A Wcbcnan Pcrspect,vc on Cultural Change',
1984.
65. Gellner, Nation.< and Nationalism, J98J, p. 22; also Encounters, 199-1, ch. 3
142 Nation Formation
2
It is precisely by binding things together that traditional visions perpetuate them
selves and the prejudgments contained within them.<1o
As it is these statements are contradictory. Gellner is quite right to reject the
widely held view that a common culture united feudal society. 67 But even if
they respectively refer to the two parts of the split in traditional agrarian soci
eties we passed over earlier - between (1) the 'little' traditions, and (2) the
'great' or 'high cultural' traditions - it still leaves Gellner unable to theorize
the reach and legitimation across the ruling classes of traditional 'visions'
(or cultures) of structure such as the Great Chain of Being. 68 Moreover he
cannot acknowledge the examples (admittedly isolated examples) of what
Anthony Smith calls vertical ethnie, where a dominant ethnic culture does
permeate in varying degrees beyond the clerical and scribal strata. 69
Given the culture/structure-in-dominance argument the problem is just
turned on its head in relation to modern societies. A second proposition is
added to that of the single cultural space. He says that the homogenization of
cultural facts is accompanied by a 'refusal to countenance conceptual pack
age deals': people analyse and dissect the components of their
held-in-common High Culture. 70 In effect he is saying that a homogeneous
cultural space entails a rejection of cultural homogeneity. It is a leaning in the
direction of asking, as we asked earlier, why are people more conscious, or
conscious in a different way, of cultural questions. It means that with Gellner
we can reject Elie Kedourie's claim that nationalism imposes homogeneity.
But whether on the other hand we would want to straightforwardly accept the
functionalist overtones in Gellner's reversal, that 'it is the objective need for
homogeneity which is reflected in nationalism' , is doubtful. 71
Furthermore, even if there is something to Gellner's argument, the rela
tionship between the homogeneous cultural space and the rejection of
conceptual package deals remains unexplained. The notion of a homoge
nized cultural space relies on a spatial metaphor which will be used to assert
the closed, boundedness of the nation. On the other hand the shift to an open
ness to interminable exploration (particularly affected by the 'programme' of
66. Nations and Nationalism, 1983, p. 21 and p. 22.
67. For a striking critique of the 'common culture thesis' see Nicholas Abercrombie, Stephen
Hill and Bryan S. Turner, The Dominant Ideology Thesis, 1984, ch. 2, and on feudalism, ch. 3.
However, for academic effect they tend to overstate the divide between elite and popular culture.
Michael Mullett (Popular Culture and Popular Protest in Late Medieval and Early Modern
Europe, 1987) provides a more balanced account.
68. Arthur Lovejoy, The Great Chain of Being, (1936) 1964. Further, compare quote I in the
present text to Gellner's statement of p. 31 of Narions and Nationalism (1983) that intellectuals
or clerks in agrarian society 'are both part of a society, and claim to be a voice of the whole of
it'.
69. Anthony D. Smith, The Ethnic Origins of Nations, 1986.
70. Gellner, Nations and Nationalism, 1983, p. 22. Also Gellner's Legitimation of Belief, 1974
and defined in Gellner, Encounters, 1994, p. 26.
71. Gellner, Nations and Nationalism, 1983, p. 46.
Nation Formation and the 'Rise of the Cultural' 143
the intellectually trained) which Gellner will develop in terms of an uneven,
interdependent 'cognitive and economic growth' is not subsumable within the
single-level spatial metaphor. Another way of making the connection has to
be conceived, and Gellner has no way of doing it.
There are two questions that still need to be asked: what gives rise to the
single cultural space; and how does this relate to the new division of labour?
They can be half answered in the context of a discussion of the issue of deter
mination. The determinants of industrial society are most often cast by
Gellner in functional relationships. He is explicit in referring to its 'func
tional prerequisites': industrial society 'wills itself to be mobile'! The division
of labour over time and space 'requires' (Gellner uses the term hazily and
ambiguously, but most strongly in terms of requiring as a prior condition,
and only secondarily as requiring as a consequence) a new kind of person, a
clerk, located in the spirit of rationality. His next proposition that this 'in turn
implies' (emphasis added) a basic shift from folk-familial imbued, low cul
tures to a universalized high-culture transmitted by a homogeneous education
system,72 again vaguely expresses a logical if not determinant relationship.
Thus in an implicit rewriting of Weber, Gellner says that at the 'base of the
modern social order stands not the executioner but the professor' . 73
Here, with important differences, Gellner unintentionally strikes some par
allels with Althusser's famous notes on the overdetermination of subjectivity
through the ideological state apparatuses (]SAs) with the educational ISA as
primary in training citizens. 74 However, in using the marxist language of
base/superstructure it is turned upside-down. The 'base' is the educational
system with its substantially common generic training. Any fashionable sug
gestions of openness, of criticizing common curriculum, which have become
forcefully voiced in contemporary education debates would according to
Gellner be merely a 'manifest function' masking its real basis. On this is
forged the new superstructural division of labour. If we can ignore the oppo
site direction of determination contained in the concepts 'requires' and
'implies' discussed just a moment ago, this conception of the base suggests
that the generic intellectual training through the educational sphere is the
basis of the homogeneous cultural space. But the single cultural space is also
part of the base because it 'underlies' the rational spirit (regularity and effi
ciency) carried by the division of labour.
Perhaps we are expecting too much of Gellner to be consistent on questions
of determination: after all he makes no claims to be able to establish what he
calls the 'aetiology of industrialism'. All the same, problems of methodolog
ical inconsistency suggest Gellner has managed to develop not so much an
adequate theory of the nation as to emphasize some important processes in
national formation. The following passage from Gellner at least summarizes
his descriptive position:
72. Gcllncr, 'Scale and Nation', 1974, pp. 146-149.
73. Gellner, Nations and Nationalism. 1983, p. 34.
74. Althusser, Lenin and Philosophy, 1971.
144 Ndtion Formation
Thus, in brief, the complex nature of modern technology and the high-powered
training it presupposes, in conjunction with rapid mobility and the requirement of
job-switches within one lifetime and between generations, ensure that modern soci
ety is both more homogeneous and more diversified that those which preceded it.
It is more homogeneous in that'"it presupposes a shared universal basic training of
a very serious nature, and at the same time, on the basis of this shared foundation,
a rapidly changing superstructure is erected, which contains far more and more pro
foundly diversified elements than were found even in the more complex traditional
societies ... It is possible, on a basis of those very simple but pregnant premises, to
construct a theory of nationalism. 75
Uneven development and the cultural boundary
Some of the dimensions pointed to by Gellner's analysis as so far discussed,
such as the erosion of differentiated agrarian communities and of local all
embracing structures, and the development of a generic system of intellectual
training linked to the state, enable him to go some distance toward describing
factors in the formation of the boundary of the nation. However, it cannot yet
explain why boundaries become so important, or take the form that they do.
Why can not they be overlapping? Why are boundaries so precisely demar
cated; so passionately contested? Along what lines are these boundaries
drawn: why this boundary rather than that? Why did not the internationaliz
ing logic of industrialization immediately chase what Gellner calls the
'curiously abstracted loyalties' of nationalism to a further level of abstraction,
that is, towards cosmopolitanism, world communalism or 'emanationalism'. 76
Or to put the same question with a historical emphasis, why are national
boundaries 01ore precisely demarcated than those of the universalizing sodal
ities of Christendom, Islamic society, or the Middle Kingdom? It cannot
explain how the cultural boundaries of nations are maintained while being
interpenetrated by inter-national allegiances and identities: 'the West' ,
Europe, the pan-Islamic community, and so on.
It is at this point that Gellner draws upon the concept of uneven develop
ment, the uneven timing of the arrival of industrialism and the new division
of labour. It is a concept he wrests out of the arms of the marxist tradition. 77
As we saw in the previous chapter the concept was reclaimed for marxism
but in doing so Nairn had to acknowledge the significance of Gellner's con
tribution.
75. Gellner, 'Scale and Nation' 1974, p. 149. Similarly stated in Encoumers, 1994, p. 46.
76. See variously: William Irwin Thompson's mystical book From Nation to Emanation, 1982;
the chapters by Peter Butler, 'The Individual and International Relations', Zdenek Kavan,
'Human Rights and International Community', Michael Donelan, 'A Community of Mankind',
Moorehead Wright, 'An Ethic of Responsibility', and Alan Pleydell, 'Language, Culture and the
Concept of International Political Community', in James Mayall, ed., The Community of States,
1982; Tony Honore, 'The Human Community and the Principle of Majority Rule', 1982.
77. It was central to Lenin's theory of imperialism as one of the 'fundamental inevitable con
ditions and constitute premises of[the capitalist) mode of production'. V.I. Lenin, Imperialism,
the Highest Stage of Capitalism, (1917) 1978, p. 60.
Nation Formation and the · Rise of the Cultural' 145
Gellner posits two principles of modern boundary demarcation. The first
paradoxically occurs through the tendency in the early stages of industrial
ization for existing barriers to communication to be re-formed and extended.
In the process 'low' cultural-linguistic groups of the old order are unevenly
drawn into the new dominant culture. Later entrants into the new culture, or
those whose dialect is more distant from the educationally mediated, bureau
cratic and commercialized idiom, are profoundly disadvantaged. This is not
to say that some individuals of the outlying cultural group don't become
intellectually trained in the new order, but the training has its own repercus
sions. In the course of time, either the outlying group becomes incorporated
into the dominant idiom, or some of its new intellectuals come to express the
discontents of that group in terms of a putative version of the old folk
culture/dialect. In other words, the new disenfranchised intellectuals came to
reassert old boundaries, but on the basis of a more abstract conception of
those boundaries. Gellner thus places intellectuals at the centre of the new
movements. A nationalism emerges propelled in the first instance by a disen
franchised intelligentsia, affirming the folk culture as it supplants it. 78
In one way Gellner barely develops this point about the re-forming (and
abstraction) of linguistic/cultural boundaries. In another sense he takes it
too far. While he gives valuable body to the old functionalist dictum that 'a
new "society" must reconstitute itself in the image of the old' (quoted at the
beginning of the chapter), and starts to address the issue of the masking of
this process by the form that the reconstitution takes, this leads him into an
excessively cultural inventionist stance. Ignoring much evidence to the con
trary he claims that 'Dead languages can be revived, traditions invented,
quite fictitious pristine purities restored'. 79 It seems that the force of the
structuralist/post-structuralist emphasis on the 'arbitrariness of the sign' has
insinuated its way into even this stalwart of mainstream theory. The shrink
ing Gaeltacht (Irish-speaking area) in Ireland at a time of national
self-consciousness, the fitful sagas of Manx, Cornish, Welsh and Scots Gaelic
are all examples which qualify any suggestion that cultural invention or
revival is an easily managed process. The European Bureau of Lesser
Languages, set up under the rationale that after I 992, Europe will find unity
by fostering linguistic diversity, has commissioned the first Cornish-English
dictionary since 1955, but whether this in itself will revive Cornish is ques
tionable. Even Hebrew which appears to be one of the few successful revivals
of a language was never a dead language. 80
The second principle of boundary demarcation refers to the 'inhibitors of
78. Gellner. Notions and Na1iona/ism, 1983, pp. 57 62. An e�ample of the centrality of intel
lectuals to cultural nationalism is the inOucnce in Africa of French speaking black mtellectuals
like Leopold Sedar Senghor. See Abiola lrelc, 'Negritude or Black Cultural Nat1onalism', 1965
It is clear however that industrialization is not the key to the process.
79. Gellner, ibid., p. 56.
80. John Edwards, wnguage, Society and ldmtit)', 1985, ch. 3. I use Ed,.ards' discussion
because ironically he sees himself in complete agreement with Gcllner's point that nauonahsm
becomes important precisely when folklore and folk dialect become 'art1fic1ar (p. 94).
146 N11tion Formation
social entropy' , or those classifications of identity which resist over time their
even dispersal through the whole society, be they genetic or deep-cultural.
Gellner avoids this definition being circular or primordialist by saying that
'Physical traits which Dike red Qair], though genetic, have no strong historic or
geographic associations tend to be entropic'. 81 But in doing so he has effec
tively to base his theory of fissure generation upon cultural differences, and
particularly upon differences which are a 'genuine prior barrier' both to
mobility in the new fluid totality and to equality in this society of egalitarian
expectations. This is the stage of the neo-n"ationalisms. But why is it the deep
cultural differences emerging from pre-industrial society which become
important if, as Gellner claims, it was structural differences which were the
key to understanding pre-national society? This takes us back yet again to the
problem of arguing for the rise of the nation through the transition from
society mediated by structure to one set in a fluid, single-level culture.
The rise of the cultural?
I would like to round off by generalizing the discussion to its broadest impli
cations and exploring the assertion that the cultural is now in dominance. It
should be emphasized that it is not the analytic separation of culture and
structure which is being rejected out of hand. 82 What is being questioned is
the way Gellner has handled the separation, and secondly the status of the
suggestion that we are witnessing the rise of the cultural. The contemporary
period, the age of subjectivist culture, has certainly brought the issues of cul
tural processes to the fore, but to say that is of a different status to arguing for
the predominance of culture over structure. As the second version of Gellner's
argument acknowledges, culture/structure are always in relationship. An ade
quate theory of the nation requires an account of the different
structural-cultural (and object-subject) forms, the levels within them, and the
internal relationship of those levels. And it is here that Gellner's position
continues to fall short.
Ernest Gellner is not alone in suggesting the movement of culture into pre
dominance. For some marxist-influenced theorists the limitations of the
base-superstructure metaphor have been variously resolved in terms of the
affirmative character of culture (Herbert Marcuse); the relative autonomy of
the superstructural (Louis Althusser); by conceiving of a duality mediated
(Theodor Adorno); or a duality in homology (Lucien Goldmann); and so on.
With the recognition of a contemporary historical shift - called variously
postmodernity, the third wave (Alvin Toffier, 198 I) the media cycle (Regis
Debray, I981 ), the society of the spectacle (Guy Debord, I967), and the
81. Gellner, Nations and Nationalism, 1983, p. 70.
82. Its opposite, the collapsing of the two, leads to what Zygmunt Bauman criticizes in
structural-functionalism and phenomenology as 'a view of social structure as "typified": and so
a monotonous sediment of normative cultural patterns'. See Zygmunt Bauman, Culture as
Praxis, 1973, p. 84. Relevant to this whole discussion is section 2 'Culture as Structure'.
Nation Formation and the 'Rise of the Cultural' 147
information society - that is the recognition, in Fredric Jameson's words, of
a 'fundamental mutation of the sphere of culture' in late capitalism, the
debate has been reopened. 83 The lengthy passage from Jameson about to be
quoted expresses this. It has surprising parallels with the earlier version of
Gellner's 'culture/structure in predominance' argument, but it also opens up
a number of related problems relevant both to a critique of Gellner's contin
uing position and to any discussion on the transformations of the form of the
nation. Jameson writes:
What we must ask ourselves is whether it is not precisely this 'semi-autonomy' of
the cultural sphere which has been destroyed by the logic of late capitalism. Yet to
argue that culture is today no longer endowed with the relative autonomy it once
enjoyed as one level among others in earlier moments of capitalism (let alone in pre
capitalist societies), is not necessarily to imply its disappearance or extinction. On
the contrary: we must go on to affirm that the dissolution of an autonomous sphere
of culture is rather to be imagined in terms of an explosion: a prodigious expansion
of culture throughout the social realm, to the point at which everything in our
social life - from economic value and state power to practices and to the very
structure of the psyche itself - can be said to have become 'cultural' in some origi
nal and as yet untheorized sense. This perhaps startling proposition is, however,
substantively quite consistent with the previous diagnosis of a society of the image
or the simulacrum, and a transformation of the 'real' into so many pseudo-events. 84
Rather than getting into a lengthy critique of this statement at this point I
want just to raise a couple of problems and some questions, then to specu
late upon a common and underlying basis to the inadequacy of both the
prodigious-expansion-of-culture argument or the structure/culture-in
dominance position. To these positions can be added others which encounter
similar problems. Christopher Lasch comes close to both and fully agrees
with neither when he says:
Identity has become uncertain and problematic not because people no longer
occupy fixed social stations - commonplace explanation that unthinkingly incor
porates the modern equation of identity and social role - but because they no
longer inhabit a world that exists independently of themselves.85
Firstly, in relation to Jameson most particularly, it should be asked, what does
it mean to talk of a 'prodigious expansion of culture' as occurring in the pre
sent? Does it suggest that Jameson's definition of culture is dependent on
implicit phenomenological assumptions, as, indeed, is Gellner's? Is Jameson
implying that in 'earlier' social formations people were not as thoroughly
culturally constituted as in the present? What are the implications of setting
up a Janus-faced distinction between the 'real' and the pseudo-real as both
Jameson and Lasch wish to maintain? This then relates to an aspect of
83. Fredric Jameson, in one of the most often cited articles in the debates on postmodcmity
over the last decade and a half, 'Postmodemism, or the Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism', 1984,
p. 86. The references cited here are Alvin Tomer, The Third Wa1·e, 1981; Regis Debray, Tcacher5.
Writers, Celebrities, 1981; Guy Debord, Sociery of the Spectacle, ( 1967) 1983.
84. Jameson, 'Postmodernism', p. 87.
85. Lasch, The Minimal Self. 1985, p. 32.
t
148 Nati Jn Formation
Gellner's continuing emphasis and to an issue that has been raised through
out this book (particularly Chapter 5): namely, what are the implications of
talking of culture as invention, or culture as simulacrum as it has become
more fashionable to do lately? Nationalism, in Gellner's aphoristic language
'invents nations where they do not exist' , or as Donald Horne would have it
'their "reality" must be "invented'". 86 Further to this, the problem of how to
conceive of a historical shift in the form of social integration within the para
meters of the orthodox marxist metaphor of base-superstructure is apparent
in this passage from Jameson, but it also relates to a Weberian-Durkheimian
like Gellner who would reject any such notion of base-superstructure yet is at
least partly concerned with the question of determination.
To argue that we now (self-actively) form our identity in the cultural sphere,
or that culture has now exploded into every level of social life suggests an
acute awareness of phenomenal changes (in both senses of the word): from the
globalization of commodified culture and the penetration of international
popular culture into hitherto parochial or relatively closed settings; the
increasing fragmentation of those settings which grounded and even bound
the extent to which questions about identity and ontology could be explored;
to the galloping emphasis on personal, autonomous identity construction
and the realm of the unconscious. 87 However, the attempt to theorize these
developments in terms of a prodigious-expansion-of-culture or a
culture/structure inversion effectively hypostatizes the realms which have been
analytically separated and confuses substantive changes in the form of the
culture and social structure for a changed relationship between those theo
retical realms. Geliner's earlier use of the theoretical concepts of structure and
culture as descJiptive terms to be posited as the alternative webbing of social
integration certainly made this mistake. In Jameson's case he seems to be
confusing what has been described here as the processes of the extension and
abstraction in time and space of a practised-in-common level of culture
(occurring particularly throughout Western capitalist societies) with social life
becoming cultural in a more generalized way.
This can be pushed a step further through asking why social theorists are
putting more emphasis on the cultural, and why many people are more con
scious, or conscious in a different way, of cultural questions. A response
would also tie in with an implied connection made in the introduction to this
chapter: namely, the new meta-interest in cultural questions is relevant to
explaining the latest wave of attention given to explaining the formation and
hold of the nation.
86. Gellner, Thought and Change, 1964, p. 168; Donald Home, The Public Culture, 1986,
p. 109. See also Gellner, Nations and Nationalism, 1983, pp. 48-49, 55-56; Anderson, Imagined
Communities, 1983, pp. 15-16, 122; Richard White, Inventing Australia, 1981; Gary Wills,
Inventing America, 1979; E. Hobsbawm and T. Ranger, eds, The Invention of Tradition, 1983;
Edwards, Language, 1985; Edmund S. Morgan, Inventing the People, 1988.
87. Amongst the massive body of literature on this last development see Ernest Gellner's
own The Psychoanalytic Movement, 1985.
Nation Formation and the 'Rise of the Cultural' 149
To expand this outwards, whereas the tendency towards a relative sup
pression of theorizing the cultural by the classical positions, including even
Marx's, almost closed off the possibility through that period of theorizing the
nation, the contemporary interest in the rise of the cultural (Giddens and
Beck use the term 'reflexive modernization'811) is a condition for a new stage
of theorizing. But it has its own pitfalls. The expansion-of-culture position
and both versions of the culture-in-dominance argument replace an analysis
of the rise of the cultural with a description of it. They thus have restricted
insight into the possibilities of their own theorizing. This development sug
gests that we need to be able to theorize the broad sweep of change which
heightens in inter-relation both a new epistemology and a new self-con
sciousness of an ontological shakiness which previously only philosophers
built into castles in the air. It raises questions about the fundamental recon
stitution of the nation in the postmodern, late-capitalist setting and how
nationality (including some of its modern forms) as one 'primordial essence'
of individual identity will continue to have force. With the emerging domi
nance of a new mode of integration in late capitalism and the reconstitution
of the old form of the nation, new ways of thinking about the old are coming
into prominence. In some ways a theorist like Jameson is better equipped to
deal with these questions. 89 Given the boundaries of Gellner's theory we are
restrained to focus on the formations of the 'classical nation' rather than its
subsequent transformations. Gellner's vigorous critique of the philosophy of
postmodernism90 (much of which I agree with) blinds him to the possibility
that postmodernity may already be upon us as a material process, as an onto
logical formation framing without replacing tradition and modernity.
I have tried in this chapter to show how Gellner's theory of the nation rests
upon a deeply flawed theory of societal forms. Gellner leaves us with a series
of evocative and inspired, but unsustained insights. Gavin Kitching gener
ously writes that:
Gellner rather like Max Weber in fact, is a much better comparative historian than
he is a theorist, and indeed his capacity for astute historical generalization tends to
triumph despite the ponderous and static conceptual apparatus in which it is
enthralled. 91
Gellner in fact set himself a more far-reaching task: unobtrusively to loosen
habitual theoretical associations, to set up new principles which are evident
from the context in which they are developed 'until at last the context has
been set up in which an assertion can be made which is simple. and yet not a
88. Ulrich Beck, Anthony Giddens and Scotl Lash, Reflexi>-e ,\loderni:ation Po/11ics.
Tradirion and Aesthetics in the Modern Soc,al Order. 1994
89. Even so, see Dan La1imer's cri11que in 'Jameson and Post-\1odemism·, 1984
90. Ernest Gellner, Postmoderni.rm. Reason and Religion, 1992. For an e,ccllcnl nposle lo
Gcllner see Bryan S. Turner, Orienta/ism, Postmodernimr. and Globalism, 1994
91. Kitching, 'Instrumental Passion', 1985, p. 107.
150 Nauon Formation
trite repeuuon of the old wisdom'.92 So far, despite his considerable
rearrangements of the terms within the Durkheimian-Weberian approach,
parucularly the traditional/modern distinction, Gellner has not managed to
carry the opening forays of clastical social theory into an approach which
escapes the considerable problems associated with the hardening of that tra
dl!ion into an iron cage of orthodoxy. The next chapter examines a social
theorist who, by drawing the Durkheimian-Weberian tradition into an
unusual synthesis with insights from marxism, does escape some of the limi
tations of orthodoxy. However, the chapter will question whether or not this
radical synthesis by Anthony Giddens is any more successful than Ernest
Gellner's reworkings.
92. Gellner, Notions and Nationalism, 1983. p. 136.
7
Nation Formation and the Instituting
State: A Critique of Structuration
What has made the nation-state apparently irresistible as a political form
from the early nineteenth century to the present-day? From the state sys
tem that was once one of the peculiarities of Europe there has developed
a system of nation-states covering the globe in a network of national
communities ...
In outline, it is not difficult to explain the universal scope of the
nation-state in the modern world.There are three main types of factors
involved, only one of which is intrinsically connected with the spread of
industrial capitalism. The first is the combination of industrial and mili
tary power originally developed in the European nation-state. Rather
than promoting peaceful economic advance, industrialism was from the
beginning married to the arts of war. No state that did not possess mili
tary forces able to use the new organizational forms and the new
weaponry could hope to withstand external attack from those that could
muster such forces. The second factor is the vast expansion of the admin
istrative power of the state, which I have argued is one of the main
definitive features of the nation-state.Only with such extension of author
itative resources does it become possible to concentrate the allocative
resources upon which a flourishing modern economy depends. The
heightened administrative power of the state is necessary not only to
consolidate resources internally, but to cope with the vast international
political network of relations in which all modern states are involved
with others. The third influence, or rather, set of influences, concerns a
series of contingent historical developments that cannot be derived from
general traits attributed to nation-states, but which nonetheless decisively
influenced the trajectory of development of the modern world.
Anthony Giddens, The Nation-State and Violence 1985
Anthony Giddens is not alone in thinking that the existing traditions of
Western social and political thought are in need of renewal and rethinking.
Into this setting have stepped a proliferation of new social theories attempt
ing to provide new means of understanding the world. However, of all those
post-classical theories, theories which in a generalized way purport substan
tially to break with or forge a novel synthesis between the traditions of
marxism and those of Weber and Durkheim, Giddens' theory of structuration
is the only one that stands out as paying direct and sustained attention to the
nation-state. This lacuna in avant-garde theory is surprising. It is unexpected,
not the least because the nation-state has consolidated in this century as the
predominant form of abstract community. Despite the escalated crossing of
152 '
Nation Formation
national boundaries by a flow of international capital and extended forms of
cultural interchange. the nation-state continues to bind people in relations of
intense. if increasingly fragile and contradictory, loyalty.
Such issues remain largely outside the preserve of contemporary, particu
larly postmodern, social the�ry. In the pantheon of big names in
contemporary avant-garde, theory only Julia Kristeva has devoted more than
passing paragraphs to the nation-state. Michel Foucault concentrates on
institutions of power, discipline and sequestration within the state boundary.
Jacques Derrida is taken by his own special expression of the cultural inven
tionist standpoint, to the extent that when he writes an isolated essay on the
American Declaration oflndependence his central interest is in deconstruct
ing the 'patriotic' document as a fictional moment which invents its
signatories in their act of signing. Giles Deleuze and Felix Guattari in occa
sional cryptic comments reduce the nation-state to a locus of artificial
territorialization. Cornelius Castoriadis reduces the nation-state to an exem
plification of his thesis that society is instituted as an act of the imaginary.'
The list could go on. The point is that across the range of contemporary
social theory, Giddens is notable in bringing his general theoretical approach
to bear upon the national question. His analysis of the nation-state in the
context of his overall theory is thus the subject of this chapter. Moreover, as
a synthesizer of the theoretical traditions of Marx, Durkheim and Weber, dis
cussed in earlier chapters, Anthony Giddens provides us with a doubly
relevant body of work through which to draw this present work towards a
conclusion.
Continuing the primordiality-modernity theme the following discussion
critically elaborates upon Giddens' theory of the original formation of the
nation-state. Secondly, as a continuation of the subject-object theme, the
chapter examines his contribution to understanding the subjectivity and
social relations of the nation and nation-state: it asks why it is that within a
broader theory that makes significant strides in interpreting the relation
between objective forms of social relations and modes of individual and
social subjectivity, his more specific theory of the nation-state leaves this
objective-subjective relation as an ad hoc connection. Why does Giddens
retain a strict dualism of subject (nationalism) and object (nation-state) when
a central rationale for the theory of structuration is overcoming such
dualisms?
I. Michel Foucault, Discipline and Punish, (1975) 1982; Jacques Derrida, 'Declarations of
Independence', 1986, and see also his The Other Heading, 1992; Felix Guattari, Molecular
Revolution, 1984; Cornelius Castoriadis, The Imaginary Institution of Society, 1987. Julia
Kristeva is an exception with the publication of three of her essays under the title Nations with
out Nationalism, 1993, but the book is written as a political and philosophical argument not as
political theory. The one field in which the nation is given sustained attention is post-colonial the
ory. See for example Partha Chatterjee, The Nation and its Fragmell/s, 1993.
Nation Formation and the Instituting State 153
Giddens' theory of nation-state formation
For Giddens the nation-state is a bordered power-container. It contains
power through storing and extending the possibilities of time-space distanti
ation, for example through storing information relevant to the direct
supervision of its subject population. By virtue of this reflexively monitored
containment, the nation-state is quite distinct from the polities of earlier
agrarian class-divided societies. This is a different point than that made by
Michael Mann when he overstretches his salutary criticism of theories which
conceive of societies as discrete, monolithic or unitary formations. Mann
implies, I think wrongly, that across the transformations of world history,
societies became more bounded and separated out from each other as state
powers were increased.2 Giddens' traditional-modern distinction which he
makes specific to a comparison of state formations is more easily sustained.
He argues that in contrast to the contemporary (more abstract) state, which
through a rationalized network of agencies attempts to cast a relatively homo
geneous shadow over its territory, traditional states did not have the
administrative power to contain, pacify and monitor space in other than an
uneven way. Their power decreased unevenly across the widening circles of
distance from their administrative centres. (See Chapter I on the distinction
between frontiers and borders.) While Giddens may underestimate the con
cern in the traditional states for precisely demarcating their frontiers,3 his
argument that traditional states did not have borders but frontiers accords
with current research. Giddens thus begins, as he says, with a typological and
comparative concern generically to contrast modern and traditional states. 4
Although the absolutist state is taken as marking the transition to the mod
ern state, it is in his terms still a traditional state.5
Giddens highlights three political characteristics of the transition: (I) the
centralization and extension of administrative power; (2) the development of
more abstract practices and codes of law whereby statutes began to be drawn
distinguishing between private property and the public domain, and the legal
sanctions of state agencies began to replace customary sanctions; and (3)
changes to the forms of managing money, in particular, the institution of
large-scale tax systems to underwrite the constant military confrontations
between the emerging European states {pp. 93-103). Further to these changes,
2. Michael Mann, The Sources of Social Pott-er, vol. 1, 1986, passim. Chris Wickham (in
'Historical Materialism, Historical Sociology', I 988) draws the same implication, but he agrees
with Mann's conclusion. By using the levels-in-intersection metaphor it is possible to allow for
the way in which the processes of bounding work in difTerent ways across varying extensions of
space and time. See Chapter I above.
3. See John Armstrong, Nations before Nationo/ism, 1982, ch. 2.
4. Anthony Giddens, The Notion-State and Violence, 1985, p. 83. All ensuing page references
m the body of the text will refer to this book.
5. Ibid., p. 93. At another point (p. 4) the distinction is not made so clearly. He says: 'In the
absolutist state we discover a breakaway from traditional stale forms.' It is only a minor issue, but
it indicates a problem with the concept of the traditional-modern divide.
154 Nqrion Formation
Giddens associates the rise of the absolutist state and the later nation-state
with certain military developments. Firstly, he suggests that technological
developments in armaments, crucially the industrial-military harnessing of
gunpowder in the sixteenth cen1ury, changed the nature of war and separated
defence from the fortification of cities. Secondly, the amplification of admin
i�trative power within the military and the creation of standing armies owing
direct allegiance to prince and patria favoured the predominance of larger
states and principalities over smaller ones, of unified kingdoms over what
Gianfranco Poggi calls stiindestaatum. Thirdly, Giddens singles out the
importance of naval power as contributing to the rise of the English, Dutch
and French states, and to the further interconnecting of the world (pp.
105-116). These factors, I suggest, are all changes in social form discussed
predominantly at the ontological level of agency-extension (the administra
tion of agents and agencies) and at the epistemological level of empirical
generalization. This point will be developed and become central to a critique
of Giddens' theory as being set on one plane. However, there is a lot of
groundwork to be done before this criticism can be directly sustained.
Much of Anthony Giddens' writing on the national question is expressed
in a comparative listing-of-factors manner. The historical description is well
supported by notable contemporary research such as that conducted by
Charles Tilly and his associates. 6 However, the limitations of his overall
framework can begin to be exposed through an examination of some
instances where Giddens moves to draw conclusions from his comparative
generalizations. He says:
The European state system was not simply the 'political environment' in which the
absolutist state.and nation-state developed. It was the condition, and in substantial
degree the \l'ery source, of that development. It was war, and preparations for war,
that provided the most potent energizing stimulus for the concentration of admin
istrative resources and fiscal reorganization that characterized the rise of
absolutism. Technological changes affecting warfare were more important than
changes in techniques of production. (p. 112)
Underpinning this statement and running through his analysis are a num
ber of propositions which are open to qualification. They warrant extensive
comment. To begin with, we can question the status of the repeated assertion
that the absolutist state and nation-state are European in source and origin. 7
That question becomes the subject of the following section. There is no
doubting the importance, indeed overt centrality, of developments occurring
in Europe; however, Giddens can be criticized along with other writers as
diverse as Hans Kohn and V.G. Kiernan for being overly anxious to attest to
this centrality. 8 Giddens' analysis gives the impression of a single-trajectory
6. Charles Tilly, ed., The Formation of National States in Western Europe, 1975.
7. See also Anthony Giddens, 'Nation-States and Violence', in Social Theory and Modern
Sociology, 1987, pp. 170, 177, 179 and his Power, Property and State, 1981, p. 186.
8. Hans Kohn, The Idea of Nationalism, (I 944) l 956; V.G. Kiernan, 'State and Nation in
Western Europe', 1965, pp. 20-38.
Nation Formation and the Instituting State 155
pathway from European absolution to the nation-state. He leaves out the
complication that developments of the form that he isolates in Europe were,
albeit with quite different cultural content, proceeding elsewhere. Seventeenth
century Japan was for example more bureaucratic, more precisely surveyed
and more intensively administered than late-feudal Europe. 9 The subsequent
section takes up the question of the relation between the state and war and
capitalism. The present chapter thus initially allows the structure of Giddens'
own approach to set the structure of a critical response while beginning to
interleave suggestions as to how the constitutive levels method presents dif
ferent ways of understanding.
Europe as the source and origin?
Giddens defines the absolutist state as 'a political order dominated by a sov
ereign ruler, monarch or prince, in whose person are invested ultimate political
authority and sanctions, including control of the means of violence' 10
(emphasis added). In contrast to Giddens' substantive analysis which overem
phasizes the level of the agency-extended, this definition goes in the opposite
direction to overemphasize a still-present but increasingly subordinate aspect
of this form of state, namely the centring of power on the person of the
prince. Given that with absolutism, face-to-face relations were already over
laid by post-patrimonial relations of agency-extension, and in Gianfranco
Poggi's words, power had become 'more unitary and abstract', detaching
'itself conceptually from the physical person of the ruler', the definition is
doubly misleading. 11 Furthermore, whether by this definition or a more fully
considered version, it is not so clearly the case that the emergence of admin
istrations of absolutist control depended directly upon the European setting.
Ironically, it could be argued that the emergence of capitalism in Europe
rather than in the 'Far East' was testimony to the far greater political and eco
nomic control that the Chinese and Japanese polities had over market
relations, the movement of capital, and its private accumulation.
It would seem that Giddens is also on shaky ground when he says that tra
ditional rulers outside of Europe had not 'incorporated the state within their
own person; they sat at the pinnacle of it' (p. 93). This is not to question his
insightful comment that doctrines of divine right were traditional accou
trements to something very new; it is rather to challenge the modernist and
Eurocentric way in which this point is developed. There are unspoken mod
ernist assumptions permeating Giddens' treatment of kingship as an
administrative accretion upon the body politic. As Reinhard Bendix has
9. Joseph R. Strayer, 'The Tokugawa Period and Japanese Feudalism', and other chapters in
John W. Hall and Marius B. Jansen, eds, Studies in the Institutional History of Early Modern
Japan, 1968.
IO. Giddens, Power, Property and State, I98 I, p. 186, repeated in 'Nation-States and Violence',
1987, pp. 170--171.
11. See Gianfranco Poggi, The Development of the Modern Stace, 1978, p. 74 and ch. 4.
156 Na'tion Formation
argued. kingship was an ambiguous institution having its roots in kin-group
associations. 12
There is a Eurocentrism in both the treatment of kingship and absolutism.
Just to raise one example in.relation to absolutism, the succession of
Tokugawa shoguns who maintained a kind of Absolutist control of Japan
from the seventeenth century well into the nineteenth century did so during
a period of conscious insulation from most European contact. Nevertheless,
they were part of a reconstitution of the traditional. Giddens might counter
that the Tokugawa shogunate symbolically deferred to the sacred pre-emi
nence of the emperor, but it must be recognized how they controlled and
isolated his power. Initially through a revival of the neo-Confucian philoso
phy of Chu Hsi and later through a 'proto-national' doctrine known as the
'Way of Japan as the Way of the Gods', they drew upon the emperor's status
(though not as a completely self-conscious instrumental procedure) to assume
political, administrative and military authority. 13 And, if Herman Ooms is
right, beginning in the early Tokugawa period, as the shogun confirmed their
power they 'dissolved the historical, contingent dimension of their persons,
and inserted them into a Shinto scheme of the sacred' . 14
The same question of Europe as the birthplace of the abstraction of the
state can be raised in relation to the rise of the nation-state. Certainly Europe
was central to the emergent system of capitalist exchange relations which
through imperial expansion effected fundamental changes in the societies of
the 'periphery'. But it is not as Giddens puts it that processes decisive to state
formation, such as administrative control 'sustained primarily through the
disciplinary power of surveillance', first consolidated to become an inherent
feature of the European nation-state system, 'then started to become dif
fused across- the world' 15 (emphasis added). It can be expressed quite
12. Reinhard Bendix, Kings or People, 1978, ch. 1.
13. Even when emphasizing the uniqueness of Japanese development, both Bendix (Kings or
People, 1978, ch. 12) and Johann Amason ('The Modern Constellation and the Japanese Enigma:
Part I', 1987) draw out the structural affinities of the Tokugawa shogunate with European abso
lutism. Manchu China might also be drawn into the comparison: see Theda Skocpol, States and
Social Revolutions: A Comparative Analysis of France, Russia and China, 1979. Perry Anderson
appears to be in agreement with Giddens when Anderson says, quite categorically, that 'Far
Eastern feudalism never passed over into Absolutism' (Lineages of the Absolutist State, 1986,
p. 428). However, his basis for that claim is opposed to Giddens' definition: 'one basic character
istic ...divided the Absolute monarchies of Europe from all the myriad other types ... controlled
by a personal sovereign ...[It) was also simultaneously the age in which private property was pro
gressively consolidated' (Nation-State and Violence, 1985, p. 429).
14. Herman Ooms, 'Neo-Confucianism and the Formation of Early Tokugawa Ideology',
1984. I find much ofOoms' description illuminating even though I substantially disagree with his
overly instrumental, overly constructivist view of ideology. On early Japanese and Korean polit
ical unification see also Joji Watanuki, 'Nation-Building at the Edge of an Old Empire: Japan and
Korea', I973.
15.Giddens, 'Nation-States and Violence', 1987, pp. 176 and 177. For a critique of diffu
sionism see James Blaut, The National Question, 1987, pp. 10-1 I, 29-32, 38-39, 76-100, 172-175.
While most of his criticisms are blunted by an unremitting class-reductionism, he still has instruc
tive points to make.
Nation Formation and the Instituting State 157
differently and in ways not necessarily discordant with other emphases of
Giddens' narrative. The gradual and uneven consolidation in Europe and
elsewhere of developments (some discussed earlier) which conditioned the
transition from the imperial or monarchical state to the abstract state con
tributed to a changed world time, a changed constitutive setting in which
across the globe, and bearing back upon Europe, states and peoples began to
assert their political and cultural identity.
Examples which qualify Giddens' focus on European absolutism as the
proximate source of the nation-state are not hard to find. The Thirteen States
in North America had instituted the internal pacification of its indigenous
inhabitants; they had fought a war of independence against a European
power which brandished absolutist doctrines of the indivisibility of sover
eignty (1775-83); they had worked out a system for parcelling, commodifying
and administering the 'empty' frontier territories; and, in the name of the
People of the United States, had ratified a unifying constitution (1789) - all
before the August Days of 1789 saw Louis XVl's ancien regime brought to an
end by his erstwhile royal subjects. 16
If we travel south to the colonies of Spanish America, Benedict Anderson
asks: 'Why was it precisely creole communities that developed so early con
ceptions of their nation-ness - well before most of Europe?' 17 The apparent
anachronism cannot be explained through a straightforward diffusionist
argument. Giddens could respond to Anderson's question in terms of his
separation between the nation-state and nationalism (that is, leaving aside
problems with the way this necessary separation is made). However, this is
complicated by the way Giddens goes on to bind himself in a minor analytic
knot. He gives the title of 'colonial nation-states' or 'state-nations' to those
former colonies who 'achieved their statehood by fighting wars of national
liberation against the metropolitan powers' (p. 271, emphasis added). Given
the force of his definition that the nation-state is a set of governing institu
tions maintaining exclusive power over a precisely demarcated territory, a
definition which supposedly 'holds for all variants' (p. 121), the discussion of
colonial nation-states belies his emphasis on the extensive reach and homog
enizing administrative control of nation-state apparatuses. Implicitly, by his
discussion, the USA (1781), Santa Domingo (1791), Haiti (1804), Venezuela
(1811), Chile (1817), the Republic of Gran Colombia (1821), Mexico (1824),
and the short-lived republic of the United Provinces of Central America
(1838) 18 emerged as nation-states simultaneously with the first of the
nation-states in Europe (and long before most). As an adjacent point, we can
16. Daniel Boorstin concludes that 'The whole American situation led them to expect more
from large organized political units, the states and the federal government, than did their con
temporaries in the Old World' (The Americans, vol. 2, 1969, p. 316). On the ideological and
economic bearing of the American War of Independence back upon the later French Revolution,
see E.N. Williams, The Ancien Regime in Europe, (1972) 1983, pp. 239-240.
17. Benedict Anderson, Imagined Communities, I 991, p. 50. See also Victor Alba, Nationalists
Without Nations, 1968.
18. From Hugh Seton-Watson, Nations and States, 1977, ch. 5.
158 N111ion Formation
also ask why the term state-nation gets introduced to emphasize that in 'most
post-colonial nation-states there is no sense in which a "nation" precedes the
emergence of the state' (p. 272, cf. p. 251), when, by his definition, a nation
cannot exist prior to its unification within state boundaries anyway.
The criticisms around the iswes of Eurocentrism, diffusionism, and an
unsustained linearity of change expressed over the foregoing pages are bruis
ing rather than knock-down blows, but in conjunction with the next issue to
be raised they start to add up to the conclusion that Anthony Giddens' his
torical synthesis of existing research is not a� impressive or sophisticated as it
first promises. These shortcomings cannot be separated from a major analytic
preclusion that will be drawn out more explicitly as we proceed. I will argue
that Giddens reduces the nation-state to an administrative structure of polit
ical and military power, and that in the process he defines away the possibility
of having a theory of the nation.
Means of violence and mode of production
For the moment there is a second proposition in the earlier passage cited from
Giddens, part of a group of issues, which also needs to be critically explored.
He suggests that in the rise of absolutism, and thus prefiguring the transition
to the nation-state, 'technological changes affecting warfare were more
important than changes in techniques of production'. 19 It is indicative of a
recurrent theme throughout the appropriately entitled The Nation-State and
Violence. The task of the present section is not so much to examine the empir
ical evidence for such a statement as to use it to introduce a discussion of the
way in which Giddens relates internal and external violence (aspects of
administrative- power) to the forces and relations of production.
Contemporary scholarship tends to support Giddens' emphasis upon the
relevance of war to the emergence of the state and nation-state. Along with
writers such as Michael Mann, he brings renewed vigour to an area which
has been underplayed in certain theoretical traditions, particularly in
structural-functionalist theories of nation-building which accentuate con
sensual integration . 20 But the above statement cannot be convincingly
sustained even by reference to the historical sources upon which it is reliant.
Giddens' conclusion overlooks evidence indicating for example that military
developments in Western Europe (which had come after 1500 to surpass
even those of China), did not achieve this advance simply because of tech
nical advances in the military sphere as such. As William McNeill
documents, in the centuries immediately after AD 1000, Chinese industry
and armaments manufacture had anticipated European developments by
I 9. Cf. Giddens, The Nation-State and Violence, 1985, p. 255, where in a more tempered
statement he says, 'industrialism was from the beginning married to the arts of war'.
20. For an indication of the renewed interest in the area, see Michael Howard, 'War and the
Nation-State', 1979; Ronald Cohen, 'Warfare and State Formation', 1984; Michael Mann, States,
War and Capitalism, 1988.
Nation Formation and the Instituting State 159
several hundred years. European predominance in the technology of war
emerged hand in hand with, or dependent upon, other developments: the
development of artillery for example drew upon metal-casting techniques
emanating from the prior craft of church-bell making; it depended upon
improved hard-rock mining and ore-refining techniques, and upon the rela
tively unabated extension of merchant capital and market relations
facilitating the assemblage of raw materials. To give determinant priority to
the technology of war - even if it is, as he says, 'substantially separate' from
the main core of feudal production - is to ignore for analytic effect the inter
dependence of means of warfare with the means of exacting feudal surplus,
as well as with an overdetermining, emergent set of commodity production
and exchange relations. 21
Giddens' related claim is that advances in military technology favoured
larger states (p. I 08). Other work suggests that in a very limited and carefully
qualified sense, and with obvious exceptions, this is possibly so. 22 However, a
much stronger case can be made for the importance of the changing logistics
of war, the mass expansion during the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries of
the numbers of men under arms, the development of standing military forces,
and the effect this had upon the means and intensity of tax collection. 23 But
even here we have to be careful. The Roman Empire gave way in the fourth
century to a patchwork of smaller political, religious and tribal associations
and entities, that is despite the imperial maintenance of a more extensive tax
ation system and a much larger proportion of professional soldiers to
population than existed a millennium later.24
Why then does Giddens make such large claims for the determinative influ
ence and autonomy (presumably relative) of the instruments and organization
of war? He is not a technological determinist. Part of the answer lies in the way
he separates authoritative and allocative resources. The problematic implica
tions of Giddens' use of these terms will be discussed in a later section, but for
the moment it will suffice to begin with some definitions and to link these
terms to an issue which came up in the chapters on Ernest Gellner and Tom
Nairn, namely the relation between the nation-state, capitalism and industrial
ism. The concept of allocative resources refers to what marxists would call the
means of material production deriving from dominion over nature; authorita
tive resources refers in an elaboration of the Weberian sense to the means of
21. William McNeill, The Pursuit of Power, 1983, chs 2 and 3.
22. See Richard Bean, 'War and the Birth of the Nation-State', 1973. However, see also the
very critical comments of David Ringrose, 'Comment', 1973 and Richard Roehl, 'Comment',
1973. As Benedict Anderson points out, 'The first "great" powers of Europe-in-the-world were
tiny Portugal, tiny Holland, and not very big England' (personal communication).
23. Samuel Finer, 'State- and Nation-Building in Europe: The Role of the Military', 1975. For
an interesting empirical discussion of the intersection between the financial effects of war and the
rise of entrepreneurial capitalism, see Christopher Friedrichs, Urban Society in an Age of War,
1979.
24. J.B. Campbell, The Emperor and the Roman Army 31 BC-AD 235, 1984; Peter Garnsey and
Richard Saller, The Roman Empire, 1987, particularly ch. 2.
160 Nation Formation
dominion over human beings themselves. 25 Military power, in its capacity to
extend and intensify the possibilities of applying sanctions, is treated along
with the possibilities ofsurveillance, administration, and ideological formation
as one of the four factors which .:reate authoritative resources {pp. 14-17). It
seems that the logic of Giddens' broader argument that prior to the emergence
of capitalism authorization had primacy over allocation, 26 leads him to extrap
olate analytically the undoubtedly important influence of military power upon
pre-capitalist state formation beyond what the evidence can support.
Given, firstly, that the state did emerge prior to the consolidation of capital
ism, secondly, that the nation-state is defined as an administrative power
container, and thirdly, that the nation-state is theorized as arising directly out of
the heightening and centralizing of administrative power, then Giddens' empha
sis on authoritative resources could have been developed as a closed circle of a
priori logic. This is part of the problem. Characteristically. however, Giddens
always recognizes that there is more than a single determinative force. The
·characteristics' of the (European) nation-state-form depend, he says, not only
upon certain administrative apparatuses but also the conjunctions ofcapitalism
and industrialism: together they constitute three, distinct 'organizational clus
ters' (p. 141, emphasis added). The crucial question, apart from why they are
seen in organizational terms, concerns the relationship between these clusters.
Giddens is, I would contend, more successful in discussing the relation
between capitalism and industrialism than that between industrial capitalism
and the nation-state. By arguing for the logical distinction between, and yet
uneven historical conjunction of, industrialism and capitalism, his position is
able to contrast modern and traditional state forms without following Ernest
Gellner in a rewriting of the Great Divide between the agrarian and the
industrial age.-While Gellner is more evocative on the ontological changes
impelled by a complex division oflabour, Giddens' theory of history is in the
end more successful in that he avoids both Gellner's disinclination to discuss
the implications of capitalism and his tendency to give industrialism an inher
ent dynamic over and above being a particular form of productive activity.
Giddens' discussion of the relation between capitalism and the nation-state
is not so successful partly because the ground is less secure. 27 Still, by impli
cation at least, his contribution avoids many of the problems in Torn Nairn's
25. See Giddens, Nation-Stare and Violence, 1985, pp. 7-17; and The Constitution of Society,
1984, pp. 258-262.
26. Anthony Giddens, Central Problems in Social Theory, 1979, p. 162. also pp. 92-94, 100-101,
162-164. This is toned down in his Constitution ofSociety (I 984, pp. 258-262), and qualified sub
stantially in Nation-Stare and Violence (1985, pp. 7-22), but the original argument still lingers on,
at least in his discussion of the state. What are we to make of his suggestion that 'capitalist soci
ety' is 'the first and only form of society in history of which it might be said with some plausibility
that it both "has" and "is" a mode of production' (ibid., pp. 134-135)?
27. See for example Philip Corrigan, ed., Capitalism. State Formation and Marxist Theory, 1980;
Gale Stokes, 'How is Nationalism Related to Capitalism?', 1986; and perhaps the best attempt,
Etienne Balibar <ind Immmanuel Wallerstein, Race, Nation, Class, 1991. For a specific empirical
investigation of the relation see Jim Maclaughlin, 'Industrial Capitalism, Ulster Unionism and
Orangeism', 1980, or the slightly broader work of Michael Hechter, Internal Colonialism, 1975.
Nation Formarion and the /nstiruting State 161
thesis that nationalism first developed in the periphery as the uneven,
exploitative and remorseless nature of capitalist diffusion engendered a new
fragmentation there along the fault-lines (often ethnic lines) of an earlier
stage of history (see Chapter 5). And although it is much less elegant than
Benedict Anderson's examination of the relevance of print capitalism to the
imagined community - mostly because as I will argue below it sequesters
questions of ontology, subjectivity and culture - Giddens' analysis provides
us with another direct if underdeveloped avenue into considering the rele
vance of the changes wrought through the objective structures of capitalism.
Before following this avenue, let me note its limitations.
For the most part, Giddens treats industrialism, capitalism and the forma
tion of state administrative apparatuses as distinct organizational clusters
providing the backdrop to the nation-state, but this becomes confused when
it is remembered that the nation-state is by his narrow definition a state
administrative apparatus. Hence at times it seems that Giddens' contribution
is not to a theory of nation-state formation, but to the way in which an exis
tent nation-state administrative apparatus frames industrial capitalism . Take
the following examples from The Nation-State and Violence:
The maturation of capitalism involves a commodification of land and products, on
the one hand, and of labour-power, on the other. While these do not proceed wholly
independently of each other, the former is intertwined mainly with the development
of the absolutist state. The latter - or so I shall argue - depends for its large-scale
extension upon the formation of the nation-state (p. 148, emphasis added).
2
The centralization of state power was the necessary condition for the formation of
commodity money (p. 154, emphasis added).
3
The early development of capitalism was indeed predicared upon an insulation of
the political and the economic not only internal but external to the territorially
bounded [therefore, nation-]state (p. 170, emphasis added).
4
The existence of such states ['already distinctively different from traditional state
forms'] supplied certain preconditions for the early development of capitalism
(p. 288, emphasis added).
These comments imply that the nation-state was a necessary pre-condition for
the extension of capitalism. Indeed, the third and fourth passages suggest an
anachronistic back-dating of the territorially bound nation-state to the period
of early capitalism, usually designated as around the sixteenth century. It is a
move which goes against all that Giddens has been arguing. He blocks off any
other interpretation of these passages by his single-trajectory pathway from
absolutism, a traditional form of state, to the nation-state, a modern form.
Elsewhere, however, Giddens writes in ways which suggest that the relation
between industrial capitalism and the nation-state was more complicated
162 Xa'10t1 Formation
1han 1he� pas:.age� md1ca1e. The connec1ion. he says. 1s 10 be looked for no!
m the rela1ion berneen the nature of capitalistic emerprise and !he central
izauon of state po\\ er. but in the social transformations wrought by
capitalism.- Here he 1s referrin� to two key processes. The first is the eradi
ca1ion of the mstnution of the city as a distinct social form and as the
dominant power container: it is s�mbolized b} the disappearance of city
v. alls.� Tots is a strange and misleading way ofarguing what Giddens himself
has better expressed as the increasing commodification ofspace including the
transformation of the city-country relation. or what :'\tarx has called
metaphorically the ·urbanization ofthe countryside·. 30
A second 1ransformation v. rought by capitalism is the abstraction of
labour-power. part ofa generalized abstraction and commodification oftime.
In examining its connection to the nation-state Giddens emphasizes one
aspect of this transformation. ·the extrusion of control of the means of ,io
lence· from class relations.; In contrast to pre-capitalist class societies - that
is. societies Giddens terms class-di,ided - capitalist production brings the
classes into close and ongoing interaction around the workplace. The modern
workplace allows for an expansion ofregularized surveillance and thus for the
consohdation of control by 01her means than direct ,·iolence. Ob,iously the
labour contract does not end inter-class violence. Howe,·er. in conjunction
with the ideological commitment of the bourgeoisie to the liberal rights
including ·freedom ofcontract". the monopoly of the means ofviolence was
gradually passed over to public authorities. Giddens. like ;-.;icos Poulantzas-32
rightly sugges1s that this passing over did not mean that the state became a
passiYe instrument of the ruling classes. It was as much an outcome of the
working-class struggle for economic. civil and political rights as it was ofthe
bourgeois strnggle against the feudal aristocracy. A meshing ofthe effects of
the modes of surveillance occurred as the state set up or oversaw the new
institutions of sequestration (here Giddens draws upon Michel Foucault's
notion of disciplinary power). ·Hospitals·. prisons and poorhouses took up
the handling of the large numbers ofdispossessed people cut loose from the
structures offeudal production . Giddens· argument is that the doubling-up of
these forms of power made possible the new means of internal pacification .
They became central to the administrati,·e co-ordination which characterized
the transition from the absolutist to the nation-state.
:!S. Giddens. Pu,,·,,,- Property and Stare. 19SJ. p. IS8.
�9. Ibid .. p. I 4S
30. It IS strange m that Giddens also "ants to argue for the increasing centralization of power.
\lore<l'·er. sure� Jane Jacobs bas a point "'hen she sa) s that m the modem period. cities have
been confirmed as the prtdommant centres of econorruc pov.er. See her Cities and the II ealrh of
\"arwns. 1956.
31 Giddens. ''-.auon-S:.ates and \"iolence·. 1987. pp. 173-1-4: also Sarion-Srare and Violence,
1955. p. 160.
3:! :S.:icos Poulantzas. Stare P0>o·er Socialism. 19S0. It is peculiar, gi,en the sub-utle of
Gidden,; 1981 book. \'olume 1 of .4 Contemporary Critique of Hstorical .Uarerialism, that he
i
does not menuon that Poulantz.as has ,er) similar concerns to his o...n.
Nation Formation and the Instituting Seate 163
The material abstraction of social relations
There are other dimensions of this transformation, issues which Giddens
does not discuss despite his eloquent and broadly conceived statement that
industrial capitalism helped 'finally to dissolve the segmental character of
class-divided societies' (p. 160). In the restricted space available, I will sketch
the outlines of just one issue. It is an issue which bears upon one aspect of the
material abstraction of social relations underpinning the interconnection of a
nation of strangers. In a quite unexpected way it bears upon the theme of the
intersection between the subjectivities of face-to-face relations and those
formed across more abstract levels of integration.
In the early period of industrial capitalism, each labourer entered into
what was (if only considered at the level of the face-to-face) an individualized
contract for the sale of his or her labour. It seemed that in this noisy sphere
of Freedom, Equality, Property and Bentham, the buyers and sellers of
labour-power were constrained only by their own free will and perhaps by
their self-interest. 33 However, as Marx shows so well, this process of the com
modification of labour and its abstraction as labour-value depended upon
definite historical conditions, in particular where products assume the form of
commodities by being sold for exchange-value, and where for the first time
the owners of the means of production and the labourers meet as free agents
through the relations of the commodity market:
The labour of the individual asserts itself as a part of the labour of society, only by
means of the relations which the act of exchange establishes directly between the
products, and indirectly, through them, between the producers. To the latter, there
fore, the relations connecting the labour of one individual with that of the rest
appear not as direct social relations between individuals at work, but as what they
really are, material relations between persons and social relations between things.34
In short, the labour abstraction was formed as a social relation. It was a
materially abstract relation in the sense that the commodification of labour
did not occur only in the realm of ideas. The value of each labourer's work
was mediated at various levels of lived relations. Localized struggles over
wages within various industries continued to be important, but by the late
nineteenth century even the most parochial struggles tended to be mediated
by institutions of agency extension such as (national) unions and employer
federations. 35 More importantly for the purposes of the present argument,
and occurring from a much earlier period, the value of labour was mediated
through the exchange of commodities and money in a context where each
labourer was thus related to a market of other labourers who were largely
unknown and geographically distant, a market of abstracted strangers. Any
33. Karl Marx, Capira/, vol. I, (1867) 1977, p. 172.
34. Ibid., p. 78.
35. For a discussion relevant to the intersections between face-to-face and agency-mediated
labour solidarity, between artisanal and manufacturing industry in late nineteenth-century
France, see Michael Hanagan, The Logic of Solidariry, 1980.
164 N�1,ion Fornwcion
sense that labour was bound by the constraints of the face-to-face and a rec
iprocity of exchange relations was thoroughly subordinated. It was this
process of abstract interconnection through the changing mode of exchange,
the capitalist market and com�dity exchange, that contributed to the con
stitution of the nation-state, itself an abstract community of strangers who
n�eded never actually to meet to feel ties of commonality.
Certainly the relation between the nation-state and the processes of labour
abstraction was not one of co-extension. A nexus of contributions to
labour-value crossed the state boundaries by which nations tended to become
delimited.36 And within the national market, subjectivities of compatriotism
were qualified by cleavages of class consciousness. Nevertheless, along with
other processes of extension and abstraction, the abstraction of labour-value
contributed to national formation by overlaying and reconstituting the iden
tity-forming predominance of networks of kinship and reciprocal exchange.
It did so in a way and on a scale that seignorial feudalism and the absolutist
state could never have effected. So long as the identity of large segments of a
populace remained bound primarily by relations of the face-to-face, as in
different ways European, Asian and South American 'feudal' peasants were,
then the relations of agency-extension such as those instituted by the state
were more likely to be received as outside intrusions than as integral with even
the most extended reaches of the villagers' imagined communities. The labour
and commodity abstractions contributed to both the changed form of these
communities and to their inhabitants' changed subjectivities. This theme is
part of the larger argument that the nation-state is a materially abstract com
munity of a particular kind, constituted in the changing, uneven and
contradictory in,l.ersection of modes of integration and modes of practice.
Such a discussion, while only scratching the surface, is indicative of the
inextricable meshing of social relations and social subjectivity. However, at
least in his writings on the nation-state, Anthony Giddens separates off ques
tions of structured practices and changing forms of ontology and identity. It
is hard to see how a discussion of the subjective implications of the labour
abstraction could be subsumed under his central distinction between author
itative and allocative resources. This is part of a more general problem which
relates to his overall conceptual apparatus: this can now be spelt out more
explicitly.
If the nation-state is a management structure, what is the nation?
As has become obvious from the foregoing discussion of Anthony Giddens'
theory of nation-state formation, his focus (with the brief exception of a
foray into a theory of nationalism, reviewed in the next section) is on the form
of administrative structuring. Giddens writes about the emergence of the
36. See for example Glenn Morgan, 'From West to East and Back Again: Capitalist
Expansion and Class Formation in the Nineteenth Century', 1985.
Nation Formation and the Instituting State 165
nation-state from the absolutist state as a process of territorial bounding and
concentration of allocative and authoritative resources by a particular kind of
state apparatus. He thus qualifies Marx by Weber: as noted earlier, the con
cept of allocative resources refers to the means of production; the term
authoritative resources refers to the means of dominion over human beings
themselves, what I have been calling the means of organization. Giddens'
argument is that the connection made by orthodox historical materialism
between capitalism as a mode of production and the development (and pre
dicted ossification) of the nation-state is one-sided and reductive. Like Weber,
he wants to treat the mode of organization as an independent institutional
clustering equally implicated in the exertion of power and the structuration of
the nation-state.
Actually, in the act of redressing the balance, Giddens leans too heavily in
the direction taken by Max Weber and Otto Hintze. He goes further than he
may have originally intended. With the reclamation of the importance of
authoritative resources, such means of power become not just built into but
e!Tectively encompass the core of his definition of the nation-state. This is at
the heart of an explanation of some of the over-emphases in Giddens' theory
of nation-state formation discussed earlier, such as the overemphasis on the
importance of military technology and on the administrative apparatus of
European absolutism. For Giddens the nation-state is a particular kind of
locale, a setting of interaction circumscribed as an arena generating adminis
trative power. It is, in short, a power container, an administrative power
container. In contrast to his admonitions of the contemporary Nietzschean
tendency to enthrone power as the primary basis of all social practices, as 'a
mysterious phenomenon that hovers everywhere, and underlies everything', 37
at times Giddens heads along the same path. He is careful to go repeatedly
back to his original point that power containers - that is, arenas generating
administrative power - generate power through the concentration of both
allocative and authoritative resources. However, this is confused by lack of
clarity. At one point, administrative power is defined as the marshalling of
authoritative resources (p. 19). Further on, it is suggested that: 'In all soci
eties, traditional and modern, administrative power is the core of domination
generated by authoritative resources, although it is not the only such resource
that exists (there is, in addition, power deriving from control of sanctions and
from ideology)' (p. 46, emphasis added). In these passages it is not clear
whether administrative power is itself an authoritative resource or an out
come generated by authoritative resources, or both, if that is possible.
Much more importantly, the privileging of administrative power limits the
reach of his analysis. Because, firstly, he uses the terms authoritative and
administrative as definitional cohorts, 38 and given, secondly, that he cuts a
sharp division between subjectivity and institutional arrangements, the
37. Profiles and Critiques in Social Theory, 1982, p. 226. Also see his Nation-State and
Violence, 1985, pp. 29-30.
38. See for example Giddens, ibid., pp. 13-14.
166 /1/a1ion Formation
nation-state is logically reduced to a particular form of structure for the
administration of political and military power. He concludes:
Drawing together the implications of the foregoing observations, we can arrive at
the following concept of the natwn-state, which holds for all variants and is not
intrinsically bound to any particular characterization of nationalism ... 'The
nation-state, which exists in a complex of other nation-states, is a set of institutional
forms of governance maintaining monopoly over a territory with demarcated
boundaries (borders), its rule being sanctioned by law and direct control of the
means of internal and external violence.' (p. I_21)
There is nothing in this definition, or in the overall structuring of Giddens'
argument discussed earlier, about the form of subjectivity constituted by (and
constitutive of) this new form of institutionally regulated association. 39
Giddens thus reduces the nation-state to one form of social practice - the
institutional - and to the overriding predominance of one level of social
integration-agency-extension. He clearly recognizes the capacity of the state
to reach beyond agency-extension to draw upon more abstracting means of
organization, means of disembodied extension crossing time and space such
as electronic communication and information storage. And he perceptively
connects this to the formation of nation-state apparatus:
The 'externalized' character of information traces inevitably severs communication
from its intrinsic connection with the body and the face. But electronic communi
cation for the first time in history separates 'immediate' communication from
presence, thereby initiating developments in modern culture that ... are basic to the
emergence and consolidation of the nation-state. (p. 14)
However, just as with his discussion of the labour abstraction, the relevance
of this process _of the abstraction of organization, communication and
exchange for.the development of an ontologically novel subjectivity goes
largely unnoticed, at least in the sense that it is basic to living as a nation of
strangers.
The reduction of the nation-state to a form of administration is related to
a major elision. The question of the nation as a materially abstracted relation
between strangers disappears into the untheorized space between the territo
rialization of the state and the management of the ideology of nationalism.
Despite his detailed, historically illustrated study of the nation-state - and
despite the irony that he asks why is it that from classical to contemporary
social theory, little systematic attention has been given to examining the
nature of the nationally bounded unity that theorists call society- Anthony
Giddens does not have more than a few words to say about the nation as a
form of social relations. The nation is treated as if it were always made in the
image of the state boundary. This screening out of the nation as an objec
tive/subjective community of persons is partly due to the definitional stricture
39. In another context he explicitly says that, 'What makes the "nation" integral to the
nation-state in this definition is not the existence of sentiments of nationalism but the unification
of an administrative apparatus over precisely defined territorial bounds.' See his 'Nation-States
and Violence', 1987, p. 172.
Nation Formation and the Instituting Stare 167
he places on the meaning of the term, nation. A nation, he says, 'only exists
when a state has a unified administrative reach over the territory over which
its sovereignty is claimed' (p. I I 9). The definition has parallels with Eric
Hobsbawm's premise that the nation 'is a social entity only insofar as it
relates to a certain kind of modern territorial state'. 40 In Giddens' case defi
nitional stricture not only reinforces the methodological elision, it flows on
into his theory of nationalism.
Nationalism as political ideology and personal psychology
Anthony Giddens' discussion of nationalism is summarized in the following
paragraph:
Nationalism [he says] is in substantial part a psychological phenomenon, involving
felt needs and dispositions, in contrast to the nation-state which is an institutional
one. I believe that one can formulate an approach to a theory of nationalism against
the backdrop of the time-space transformations by means of which the 'created
environment becomes the habitat of individuals in capitalist societies, and the
nation-state the dominant 'power container'. Nationalism, I have suggested, feeds
upon, or represents an attenuated form of those 'primordial sentiments' ('"pri
mordial sentiments" writ large, and stripped of their association with communities
of high presence-availability'] of which Geertz speaks in tribal societies or village
communities. 41
As represented in this passage there are three dimensions to Giddens'
approach to understanding nationalism: firstly, the phenomenon is said to be
primarily psychological (p. I 16); secondly, it is attendant upon modern struc
tural developments, in particular, co-ordination of the means of organization
within the nation-state (p. 219); thirdly, it is an attenuated form of primordial
sentiment.
Let me work back through these, beginning with the confusing and difficult
issue of reconstituted primordiality (the primordiality-modernity theme).
There is a dilemma here, invoked on occasions in earlier chapters under the
label of continuity-in-discontinuity. 42 Ernest Gellner handles it by emphasiz
ing the way in which nationalism, despite being uniquely modern, draws
upon the content of the past: nationalism invents nations in the reworking or
fabrication of pre-existing historical and cultural inheritances. Tom Nairn
avoids acknowledging the dilemma by separating its terms into Janus faces:
nationalism as the ideological outcome of the uneven spread of capitalism
and, alternatively, nationalism, an untheorized basis of identity which arises
out of an 'old pre-history of nationality'. Giddens is very critical of both
Nairn and Gellner. However, while in the lengthy passage just cited he seems
40. Eric Hobsbawm. Nations and Nationalism sina 1780, 1990, p. 9.
41. Giddens, Power, Property and State, 1981, p. 193.
42. Anthony Smith (Tl,e Ethnic Origins of Nations, 1986) draws a kindred though less abstract
paradox in relation to ethnicity: 'its mutability in persistence, and its persistence through change'
(p. 32).
168 Na,ion Formation
to be pushing hard against the problems of theorizing issues relating to the
continuities and discontinuities of social forms, Giddens' writing does not
achieve as much as it promises. When examined more closely his theory of
nationalism reduces to a couple•of important but undeveloped insights and a
few rhetorical gestures.
The concept of primordial attachments as derived from Clifford Geertz
refers to attachments and sentiments which stem from 'givens' . In Geertz's
words they are "'givens" - or more precisely, as culture is inevitably involved
in such matters, the assumed "givens" - of gocial existence: immediate conti
guity and kin connection .... congruities of blood, speech, custom, and so
on' . 43 Giddens' use of the concept as a sentiment based on contiguity and yet
'writ large' is, in terms of his spatial metaphor, a contradiction in terms -
close and yet far. His theoretical apparatus of time-space distantiation meets
its limits here. If employed (and it is not) it would go some way to elucidating
the processes of extension by which subjectivities grounded in relations of
contiguity still have meaning when abstracted across time and space. However,
it remains limited by being a spatial metaphor cast on one plane. By contrast
the metaphor of levels in intersection developed in the present book from
Geoff Sharp's work enables analysis to proceed at least to a working analytic
description (and a historical specification) of the level at which relations
grounded in contiguity continue to have ontological force, even while being
overlaid, reconstituted and stretched across time and space.44 This entails the
recognition of ontologically changing forms of subjectivity: for example, iden
tifying oneself as being of the Pintupi people is fundamentally different from
identifying as (Aboriginal) Australian, even though at one level there are sim
ilarities of form. It is an issue which, as argued in the next section, cannot
be adequately handled by Giddens' overall analysis. Certainly his first and
second dimensions for explaining nationalism - the fragile psychology of
post-traditional routinization or the co-ordination of administrative power
by the nation-state - cannot explain these processes. Perhaps this is why in
Giddens' later writings the Geertzian terminology is dropped.
In The Nation-State and Violence, Giddens draws a deep divide between
nationalism and pre-existing forms of group identity, this time drawing on
Fredrik Barth's argument about boundary marking and exclusionary senti
ments (pp. l 16fT.). However, he thus appears to open himself to criticisms
made by Anthony Smith of all Barthian-influenced writers for overempha
sizing the role of the boundary at the expense of theorizing social relations
43. Clifford Geertz, The lnterprerarion of Cultures, 1973, p. 259. Geertz may call upon the con
cept of primordialism, but this does not automatically make him an essentialist or idealist. He
treats the two themes of'essentialism' and 'epochalism' (that is, the modernist sense of historic
ity) as being fought out not simply as doctrinal disputes, 'but much more importantly in the
material transformations that the social structures of all the new states are undergoing' (p. 243).
44. Hence I disagree with Giddens' pronouncement that 'In the modern state, existential con
tradiction [an aspect of what I have been calling ontological contradiction] is almost completely
expunged by structural contradiction' (Nation-State and Violence, 1985, p. 196).
Nation Formation and the Instituting State 169
within the boundary. 45 This impression is more a product of Giddens' eclec
tic style than representative of the totality of his view; nevertheless it indicates
the fragmented way in which his argument proceeds.
The second dimension - the co-ordination of the means of organization - has
been discussed in considerable detail already. The basic weakness of tacking on
questions of subjectivity to an analysis which all but ignores these questions
and reduces relations of national identity to a concomitant of state-bounding
should already be obvious from the preceding discussion. What is less obvious
is yet another unexplained tension in Giddens' analysis. How is it possible that
nationalism is the 'concomitant of the co-ordination of administrative power
within the bounded nation-state' (p. 219), that there can be 'no nationalism, in
its modern form at least, without the formation of nations' (p. 116), 46 when as
Giddens acknowledges, 'it was mainly in the non-unified states and principali
ties of central and northern Europe that modem conceptions of nationalism
have their origin'?47 (p. I I 9, emphasis added). On a more positive note it is
worth recording one of his 'important but undeveloped insights':
More deeply layered ideological implications are to be traced to the fact that the con
ditions involved in the reflexive monitoring of the modern state, as a surveillance
apparatus, are the same as those that help generate nationalism. Since the discursive
capabilities involved in monitoring social reproduction become of essential importance
to the state, it is around the intersection between discursive consciousness and 'lived
experience' that the ideological consequences of nationalism will duster. (p. 220)
This brings us to the 'primary' dimension of psychology. Here too, impor-
tant points are made, but by drawing a line between nationalism as a
psychological phenomenon and the nation-state as an administrative institu
tion, Giddens leaves himself unable to account for the overt expressions of
nationality except via the problem-ridden Freud/Le Bon theory of crowd
suggestibility and identification with authority figures. 48 For someone who,
even if eclectic in sourcing their arguments, is usually circumspect about tak
ing on board the unwanted baggage of other theorists, this is a particularly
counterproductive move. His accompanying step of attempting to revive Max
Weber's best-forgotten theory of charismatic leadership has a similar quality.
While Weber and Freud have made significant contributions in other areas,
on this question they are not especially illuminating. 49
45. Anthony Smith, 'History and Liberty', 1986.
46. This of course is the opposite of Gellner's provocative point that nationalists contribute to
bringing nations into being.
47. Further to this, given Giddens' definition of nationalism (Nation-State and Violence,
1985, p. 116) as 'the affiliation of individuals to a set of symbols and beliefs emphasizing com
munality among members of a political order', the sentiment goes back much further than his
suggested post-eighteenth-century beginnings.
48. See Giddens, Power, Property and State, 1981, pp. 13 and 195; Nation-State and Violence,
1985, pp. 219 and 305; 'Nation-States and Violence', 1987, p. 179.
49. See for example, Sigmund Freud, Ci1•i/i=ation and its Discontents, l 975, on the role of Eros
in combining individuals into nations (p. 59). J.G. Merquior, who is in other ways sympathetic to
Weber, criticizes the theory of charisma for its 'endemic lack of sociological depth' (Rousseau and
Weber, 1980, pp. 181IT.). See also Chapter 4 above.
170 Nation Formacion
Having examined Giddens' separation of the objective (nation-state) and
the subjective (nationalism) the following pages broaden out, taking this
theme into a discussion of his general theory of social relations and social
subjectivity.
Subject and object, person and society
In The Constitution of Society, a volume presented as a summation of his the
ory of structuration, Giddens organizes the discussion beginning with the
individual, and then later goes on to accent social structure. The problem with
this is not that he is open to the orthodox charge of methodological individ
ualism, of which, incidentally, he provides as developed a critique as found
anywhere. Rather it is that from whichever side of the dichotomy he begins he
has consequently set up an organizing principle which makes it seem suffi
cient that person and society are put back together on a single ontological
plane. Giddens in effect privileges the constitutional form of modern
individual, the self-active agent making history 'knowledgeably' and
'autonomously'. Despite its title, The Constitution of Society is not about the
way in which different social forms are constitutive of, and through, different
modalities of subjectivity. To put person and society back together, Giddens
depends largely on a theory of contextuality and regionalization. That is,
people are located in overlaying clusters of relations of time and space, thus
avoiding, as he says, the assumption that societies are homogeneous, unified
systems.
People are thus left as active agents (which indeed they are, but in qualita
tively diffe1cn-t ways in different societies). They are understood as
'positioned' in relation to each other rather than theorized as constituted in
the very form of their agency. 50 This is a different category of criticism from
those usually, and I think ineffectually, made of Giddens. Various critics have
made the easily countered point that his view of structure as both enabling
and constraining does not sufficiently emphasize the degree of constraint
upon the actor. 51
Persons in reciprocal tribal groups are for Giddens reflective agents in the
same way as individuals in late-capitalist nations. We are all social theorists,
he says: the difference is to be found in the settings (stages) or locales in
which we move. It is propositions of this sort which need to be carefully
taken apart. Giddens wants to 'disclose features of co-presence [that is, of
50. For an interesting recenl attempt to theorize the relation between person and society by
one of Giddens' critics see Alex Callinicos, Making History, 1989, particularly ch. I.
51. See for example John Thompson, 'The Theory of Structuration: An Assessment of the
Contribution of Anthony Giddens' in his Studies in the Theory ofIdeology, 1984. For general dis
cussions of Giddens' work see Mike Gane, 'Anthony Giddens and the Crisis of Social Theory',
I983; Erik Olin Wright, 'Giddens's Critique of Marxism', 1983; Gregor McLennan, 'Critical or
Positive Theory?', 1984; Alex Callinicos, 'Anthony Giddens: A Contemporary Critique', 1985;
and, the best of these discussions, Richard Bernstein, 'Structuration as Critical Theory', I986.
Nation Formation and the Instituting State 171
people in face-to-face relations] that are found in all societies'. 52 The problem
with this is, as I will argue in more detail in a moment, that he treats co
presence ahistorically.
Face-to-face relations are certainly a primary constitutive level of human
interaction. And as Giddens maintains, the level of the face-to-face continues
to be basic, even when the predominant form of societal integration is
extended beyond 'high presence-availability' and across time and space
through such means as the media of storage and relay of information.
However, his approach significantly underplays the way in which face-to-face
relations, like the form of personhood, is reconstituted at different levels (in
his terminology) of time-space distantiation. It is this which gives rise to the
impression that Giddens' theory treats people as psychologically complex
but otherwise empty shells, interacting on theatrical stages. These stages seem
to be bounded by sets which if removed would only reveal to the actors that
they are located on yet larger stages. The nation-state, at least as Giddens has
defined it, is reduced to one of those stage sets. 53
Discussion of the implications of treating co-presence ahistorically can be
extended through introducing Giddens' notions of routine and actor. They
work to link the objective and subjective but remain two sides of an over-gen
eralized relation. A crucial part of understanding why Giddens treats
co-presence as a world form of social interchange is the centrality he affords
to the practice of routine in day-to-day life:
The term 'day-to-day' encapsulates exactly the routinized character which social life
has as it stretches across time-space. The repetitiveness of activities which are
undertaken in like manner day after day is the material grounding of what I call the
recursive nature of social life. (By its recursive nature I mean that the structured
properties of social activity- via the duality of structure - are constantly recreated
out of the very resources which constitute them.) Routinization is vital to the psy
chological mechanisms whereby a sense of trust or ontological security is sustained
in the daily activities of social life. Carried primarily in practical consciousness, rou
tine drives a wedge between the potentially explosive content of the unconscious
and the reflexive monitoring of action which agents display. 54
Thus the discussion of how we are to understand the constitution of per
sons and the nature of face-to-face integration - what he calls social
integration to distinguish it from societal or system integration which occurs
across time and space beyond the limitations of the face-to-face - is located
in a notion of how we know as practical consciousness the ways to 'go on' in
52. Giddens, Constitution of Society, 1984, p. 69. He passingly acknowledges that in The
Constitution of Society he concentrated upon material relevant to modem society (p. xvii) but this
does not qualify the point.
53. Here I am agreeing (impressionistically) with Jan Craib when he says 'Giddens often talks
about different levels of social organisation as if the social world possessed a depth ... However.
in the course of his bridge-building he loses sight of this depth.' See Craib's 'Back to Utopia:
Anthony Giddens and Modern Social Theory', 1986, p. 17.
54. Giddens, Constiturion of Society, 1984, p. xxiii. The 'duality of structure' as referred to
here is in turn defined as: 'Structure as the medium and outcome of the conduct it recursively
organizes' {p. 374).
172 Na1ion Forma1ion
habitual routine. (As mentioned earlier, it is the modern fragility of routine
which for Giddens gives rise to nationalist identifications.)
There is, however, a tension here in Giddens' approach which will become
apparent if we shift focus for �moment from social integration to look at a
schematic representation of his view of the principal forms of societal inte
gration 55 (see Figure 7.1).
Although routinization of day-to-day life is posited as transhistorical when
Giddens refers to the forms of societal integration, 'routinization' only enters
the schema with class society. This Weberi�n concept is not explained in The
Constitution of Society and only partly addressed in his earlier book, A
Contemporary Critique of Historical Materialism. There he says that in tribal
and class-divided society routinization is normatively embedded in tradition.
The ontological security of tradition, which he is rightly careful to say is not
wholly positive, is radically undercut by a series of related transformations:
the commodification of labour, the breaking of normative connections
between work and private life, and the clear demarcation of nature and cul
ture, particularly as lived in the manufactured environment of the city, the
same processes which underpin the nation-state. 56 Thus: 'The dissolution of
the foundation of society in relations of presence substantially replaces the
grounding of those primordial sentiments in tradition and kinship by a more
routinised, habitual round of "everyday life'" 57 (emphasis added). In this set
ting, as Giddens suggests, the sense of national community provides one
strand contributing to the maintenance of ontological security. However, in
Central Problems in Social Theory he argues that the disavowal of tradition is
'the most profound potential source of deroutinisation'. 58 In short, although
he has never p\lt it this way explicitly, the passing of tradition leads to more
routinizatiori even as it is deroutinizing. Such a position is sustainable, but not
in the contradictory way in which Giddens presents it.
A related example of a terminological difficulty, one this time which
Giddens does in fact recognize, is contained in the term actor. He says: 'It is
precisely because there is a deep, although generalized, affective involvement
in the routines of daily life that actors (agents) do not ordinarily feel them
selves to be actors (players). 59 It is a passing acknowledgement. It is not
adequately taken up as an indication of the different forms of subjectivity. So
far as I understand his approach, he consequently does not have an adequate
way of explaining why the Discovery of the Individual is a relatively recent
phenomenon in world history.60 As Agnes Heller's detailed examination of the
55. Ibid. pp. 181-182 and elaborated in Giddens, Power, Property and State, 1981, p. 159 and
passim.
56. Power. Property and State, 1981, pp. 150-154.
57. Ibid. p. 193.
58. Giddens, Central Problems, 1979, p. 221.
59. Giddens, Constitution of Society, 1984, p. 125.
60. The term is used by Nicholas Abercrombie, Stephen Hill and Bryan S. Turner in The
Dominant Ideology Thesis, 1984, taken from the book by Colin Morris (The Discovery of the
Individual /050-1200), but it is becoming a common enough theme.
Nation Formation and the Instituting State 173
[
TRIBAL SOCIETY Tradition (communal [Fusion of
practices) social and
Kinship system
Group sanctions integration)
Dominant locale Band groups or villages
organization
CLASS-DIVIDED SOCIETY Tradition (communal [Differentiation
practices) of social
Kinship and
[
Politics-military system
STATE power integration)
Economic interdependence
(low lateral and
vertical integration)
Dominant locale Symbiosis of city and countryside
organization
CLASS SOCIETY Routinization [Differentiation
(CAPITALISM) Kinship (family) of social
Surveillance and
[
STATE Economic interdependence system
(high lateral and integration)
vertical integration)
Dominant locale T he 'created environment'
organization
Figure 7.1 Societal Integration
(Source: Anthony Giddens, A Contemporary Critique of Historic
Ma/erialism, second edition, 1995, reproduced with the permission of
Macmillan Press Ltd.)
historical shift of the form of personhood from feudal to renaissance life
indicates, it is an anachronism to generalize the metaphor of self as actor until
at least the sixteenth century: 'In feudal society a [person] did not "play a
role"; a [person] was what [s/he] had been born to be.' 61 And even thereafter
the concept of self-as-actor both changes in time, 62 and can be distinguished
according to intellectual training and class.
In one sense it seems petty to concentrate on the shifting of terms such as
actor or routine. But there is a more important point to make. There are
enormous difficulties in attempting to theorize a discontinuity of social forms
61. Agnes Heller, Renaissance Man, 1981, p. 206.
62. See Richard Sennett, The Fall of Public Mon, 1977, p. 206.
174 Narion Formation
I
while not rethinking the notion of a continuity in the form of agency. It is not
just a matter of saying as Giddens does that there are divergent forms of the
structuration of day-to-day life.
Continuity-in-discontinuity
A description couched in terms of constitutive levels arguably provides a
more fruitful way of conceptualizing this particular instance of
continuity-in-discontinuity. It would be to say that as a particular mode of
integration is supplanted in dominance by a more abstract mode of integration
(as has tended to happen through history) the routine of the day-to-day con
tinues even as it is reconstituted. So as tribal societies constituted
predominantly in the face-to-face are drawn as specific locales into a wider
relationship of a new kind - one which for example in the case of the abso
lutist state separates out institutional spheres in an overarching religious,
legal, and military system - kinship relations and reciprocal exchange con
tinue at one level to be basic, even as they are fundamentally reconstituted.
Kinship relations are still basic to feudal society as they were (and are) to the
tribal person, 63 but in feudal Europe kinship was overlaid by and eventually
re-formed within universalistic juridical categories. These categories were, in
effect, part of the condition of routinizing what was previously taken for
granted (or what could be called the routine of a prior dominant level). This
helps explain the apparent paradox that, as Marc Bloch records, it was from
the twelfth century onwards as kinship groups began to break.down or rather
change in form that family names first appeared: 'Thus in Europe, long after
the demise of f�udal society, the permanent family name, which today is held
in common by [people] often devoid of any feeling of solidarity, was the cre
ation not of the spirit of kinship, but of the institution most fundamentally
opposed to that spirit - the sovereign state.' 64
Here we see the intersection of two forms of social-societal integration.
With changing social relations, including changing modes of production and
exchange, the more abstract level assumes (an uneven) constitutive domi
nance and becomes the setting for reformulating something as basic as how
we name ourselves.
In one way, Giddens does in fact have a conception of levels built into his
analysis. The 'positioning of actors' occurs within a series of intersecting
regions embedded in widening reaches ohime and space. These are levels of
time-space distantiation. But he misleadingly says that in tribal societies
where social integration (co-presence) and system integration are effectively
63. This is to qualify Giddens' statement that 'traditional societies of all types have become
more or less completely dissolved' (Nation-State and Violence, p. 34).
64. Marc Bloch, Feudal Society, vol. 1, [961, p. 14l. See also Giddens on the abstraction of
law (Nation-State and Violence, pp. 98-101) as well as Gianfranco Poggi, Modern State, 1978,
pp. 60-116.
Nation Formation and the Instituting State 175
coextensive, 'positioning is only thinly "layered"' 65 (emphasis added). It would
be better described as the integrative levels being highly condensed. This
would allow for a double point to follow: through such media as writing and
print, practices which facilitate the storage and retrieval of information, rela
tions between people can be extended (and secondly, to make a political
point, they are thus attenuated across time and space). In other words,
through practices of disembodied extension the possibilities of abstract com
munities are enhanced while at the same time relations are thinned out.
Furthermore, as I have been concerned to stress, the notion of extension car
ries only half the picture. Having your breakfast companion read you the lead
story from the morning's nationally distributed newspaper is qualitatively
different to listening to a story which confirms your being as of the Red
Macaw totem.66 There is a difference that makes it only partly relevant that
these interactions are both instances of face-to-face interaction.
Giddens recognizes that writing contributes to a constitutively different
sense of history: in the extending of time-space relations people are afforded
a consciousness of historicity, 'tradition becomes visible as "tradition" ... no
longer a time-honoured basis of custom but a discursive phenomenon open
to interrogation' .67 As Paul Ricoeur puts it, texts 'project new ways of being' .68
But it does not seem to matter how many times Giddens concurs that what
'the "individual" is cannot be taken as obvious'; the full implications of this
as a facet of the way in which the discontinuities between the forms of face-to
face interaction are as important as the continuities do not sink into his
theory of the nation-state. This is ironical given his claim in the discussion of
the nation-state to be writing a discontinuist history. Rectifying the problem
would entail, as I have argued, substantially qualifying the emphasis he places
on the transhistorical reflexivity of social agents. In the terms I was drawing
on earlier to restate Giddens' argument, the heightening of reflexivity and the
generation of a sense of national historicity is only possible as the subject is
lifted into an abstract relationship to tradition-as-lived. Here time itself is
constitutively more abstract as well as distantiated.69
The distinction Giddens draws between social and societal integration is
used as an apparent but ineffective way out of some of these difficulties. It
allows him for instance to recognize that the media of time-space distantiation
65. Giddens, Constitution of Society, 1984, p.85.
66. On story telling see Jean-Francois Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition, 1984, pp.20---23
and Robert Darnton, 'Peasants Tell Tales' in his The Great Car Massacre, 1985. On the news
paper as part of a new mode of apprehending the world see Benedict Anderson, Imagined
Communities, 1991, chs 2 and 3: The very conception of the newspaper implies the refraction of
even "world events" into a specific imagined world of vernacular readers; and [is] also ...
important to that imagined community (as) an idea of steady, solid simultaneity through time'
(p. 63).
67. Giddens, Constitution of Society, 1984, p. 20 I.
68.Ricoeur quoted in Giddens, Nation-State and Violence, 1985, p. 42.
69.The argument about constitutive abstraction also allows for an escape from implicitly leav
ing time and space as privileged categories. This is a tendency because of the use of conventional
self-referring metaphors - time being distantiated turns time upon a spatial metaphor.
176 Nqtion Formation
(which are acknowledged in a cryptic phrase to be simultaneously the means of
societal integration)70 perforce extend time and space by an "'alienation" of
communication in circumstances of co-presence'.71 However, the social
societal integration distinction is part of the problem to the extent that it
bypasses the necessity of thinki';,g of the dominant level of societal integration
;is itself constitutive of and constituted by the form of personal subjectivity. In
his latest series of books, including Modernity and Self-Identity, Giddens has
moved a significant distance in rethinking his previous conclusions about
agency and identity: 'abstract systems', he says 'become centrally involved not
only in the institutional order of modernity but also in the formation and con
tinuity of the self', 72 but in his writings of the 1990s, national identity , the
subjectivity of being part of a nation, gets less rather than more attention than
before. It is ironical that at the very time that his theory is elaborated to the
point that it could provide us with new insights into the abstraction and pas
sion of national identity, his focus turns outward to the processes of globalism
and inward to life-style politics.
In late-capitalist globalizing societies, integrated as abstract communities
through the circulation of information and commodities, with kinship rele
gated to an aspect of an individual's personal history, and with institutionally
bounded role designations such as one's job less secure and no longer as
basic to personal identity, we are increasingly forced to be self-active in con
structing our place in the world. W hen Australian Airlines advertise
themselves as essential when you need to 'say "I love you", face-to-face' it is
not just that the context has changed. Facing one's much-loved, occasionally
visited grandparents to hear nostalgic stories of a disappearing past has a dif
ferent ontologi�al meaning from facing the village story-teller. As various
Arena writers have suggested, it is that the dominant form of subjectivity has
undergone a number of transformations, now in Western late capitalism
heightening the ideological practice that we 'are' autonomous authors of
own identity. The avant-garde and the intellectual must most intensely live the
paradox that we experience multiple difference within a common constitutive
form.
Giddens' theoretical attempt to offset the anti-humanist, structuralist
decentring of the subject through emphasizing the self-reflexive agency of
people is fraught with difficulties. It is just as likely to reinforce the current
ideological practice of autonomous individualism as serve as a critique of it. 73
In other words: the predominant form of individualism in Western, late
capitalist societies (leaving aside the many ways of its expression) is lived
70. Giddens, Power, Property and State, 1981, p. 157.
71. Giddens. Constitution of Society, 1984, p. 203.
72. Giddens, Modernity and Self-Identity, I 991, p. 33.
73. For an elaboration of the concept of the ideology of autonomy see Geoff Sharp,
'Constitutive Abstraction and Social Practice', 1985. Also, from a quite different standpoint but
arguing for changing forms of individualism, see Nicholas Abercrombie, Stephen Hill and Bryan
S. Turner, Sovereign Individuals of Capitalism, 1986; and Seyla Benhabib, Situating the Self,
1992.
Nation Formation and the Instituting State 177
firstly in terms of the assumed, though of course unequally realized, belief in
natural rights espoused in nineteenth-century liberal individualism. Changing
social relations have brought a more recent overlay. This emergent new level
based in the extended relations of the information society is expressed in the
extolling of freedom from constraint. We experience ourselves as agents of
our own destiny, 'inventors' of our identity, 'autonomously' choosing our
lifestyles and privatized personal associations in a manner which takes an
ontological step beyond the era when the 'possessive individual' first claimed
commodity rights. In this setting, theorizing the contradictions of national
formation entails a rigorous examination of the relation between theory and
the constitutive milieu from which theorists take their dearest assumptions.
Giddens writes for example about the way in which Machiavelli's theorems
about state power became 'reflections about phenomena which they have
helped to constitute' . To turn Giddens against himself, we can conclude by
asking the question, is he related to the ideology of autonomy in a manner
parallel io the way in which Machiavelli was implicated in the ideology of the
state?
Ernest Gellner set himself the laudable task of re-working the
Durkheimian-Weberian tradition, to loosen habitual theoretical associations,
to set up new principles 'until at last the context has been set up in which an
assertion can be made which is simple, and yet not a trite repetition of the old
wisdom'. Anthony Giddens' self-imposed task is even more extraordinary.
His is an attempted re-working and syncretism of the traditions of both con
ventional sociology and historical materialism. His work has many strengths.
However, the preceding discussion suggests that Giddens' theoretical and
historical analysis of the social relations and subjectivities of the nation-state
is beset by problems. They arise not only out of the limitations of his histor
ical conclusions, the tensions of definitional and analytic inconsistency, the
overdetermined preclusion of a theory of the nation (that is, except as
couched in terms of state-bounding), but they also arise out of continuing
problems which are at the heart of his overall theory of society and person.
This is not to say that anyone else has done a lot better. But with the rise of
cultural (ontological) questions into the glare of unremitting examination
our demands on what a theory need do have become increasingly compre
hensive.
While acknowledging that social theory has many problems to overcome,
the present work has been based on a rejection of the position that says
because social theory cannot meet our inordinate demands then any attempt
at general theory should be abandoned. Over the course of the book, existing
theories of national formation have been extensively criticized, but there has
been no suggestion that such theories have not made important contributions.
In an illuminating discussion of Anthony Giddens' theory of structuration
Richard Bernstein explains how 'Giddens's approach reflects a point which
has been forcefully made in the post-empiricist philosophy of science. i.e.. we
178 'Nµtion Formation
can judge the adequacy of a theory ... by its ability to explain what is valid
and invalid in rival theories' . 74 Over the preceding chapters the book has
attempted something akin to just that. It has attempted to test the usefulness
of the constitutive levels argument against what are generally regarded as the
most thorough-going theories of the nation and nation-state deriving from
the divergent traditions of Durkheimian, Weberian and marxist social theory.
It has worked back and forth between examining the weaknesses (and
strengths) of existing theory and developing the thesis that the nation is a
materially abstract community of strangers formed in the changing intersec
tion of levels of integration. The argument remains rudimentary in all too
many ways, but at least it allows some sensitivity both to the ontological
complexity of history and to the mysteries of that contradictory association
we call the nation. The next, and concluding, chapter draws together a few of
the themes which have been woven through the discussion.
74. Richard Bernstein, 'Social Theory as Critique', 1989, p. 23.
8
Themes for a Theory of the Nation
To speak of the renewal of community within the terms of co-operation
and sharing is scarcely conceivable within the mould of the national state.
That social form is radically identified with the homogenization of cul
tures and the increasing predominance of instrumental forms of abstract
power.
Geoff Sharp, 'Constitutive Abstraction and Social Practice', 1985
One can deconstruct the constructions of others, or deconstruct the
deconstructions of others, or deconstruct one's own prior deconstruc
tions. But by having no theory (or ethics) of how or when the moment of
deconstructive seeing through should be reintegrated into shared collec
tive practices and meanings, the dictum that 'there is nothing outside the
text', when extended to social interpretation, places one in abstraction
from (and in that sense outside) that society. Texts are amenable to end
less interpretations; but of life - we have only one.
Gerry Gill, 'Post-Structuralism as Ideology', 1984
Richard Bernstein's comment cited at the end of the previous chapter bears
repeating in its full generality: 'We can judge the adequacy of a theory ... by
its ability to explain what is valid and invalid in rival theories.' Although the
present text has not elaborated anything like a comprehensive alternative to
the theories it has examined, it can nevertheless be assessed by how ade
quately it has drawn upon its central thesis of the nation as an abstract
community to work through the limitations of existing theories.
The surface narrative was in this sense intended as a straightforward, his
torically organized and critical exegesis of significant theoretical positions.
However, the material itself quickly suggested that the discussion needed to
be more complicated and layered. It became apparent that from a contem
porary perspective on what a theory is expected to do - or at least from the
perspectives of what various latter-day theorists, for instance Nairn, Gellner
or Giddens, might expect of a theory - the classical social theorists did not
actually achieve theories of the nation. Certainly Marx, Durkheim and Weber
were heedful of the politics of nationality and the conflicts of nation-states
and national minorities. However, while they made significant contributions
to political theory, when it came to elaborating theories of the constitutive
practices through which older forms of community and polity became nations
and nation-states, they left a relatively unmapped nether-region.
Notwithstanding their intellectual urgency to both abstract from particular
180 Nation Formation
events and to rend the veil of social taken-for-grantedness, they failed to
realize (in the sense of failed to address theoretically) the contradictory impli
cations of their insights that social life rather than being naturally evolving or
God-given is constituted in an<! by human practice. However brilliantly their
general theories opened up new possibilities of understanding, the classical
theorists made no direct attempt to explain the conjunctures of material rela
tions and subjectivities which grounded national formation. The nation came
to be conceived of as 'natural' - that is, 'natural in inverted commas' . And the
nation-state came to be seen as an institutional arrangement of space which
either would melt into air (Marx) or was the most developed expression of the
world as it 'is' (Weber).
Two questions were posed: why, in the historical period that the intersec
tion of nation and state was beginning to consolidate as a dominant social
form, did Marx effectively dismiss the nation-state as a transitory form of
association, dead before it could ossify? And how, at the same time, could he
implicitly take the nation for granted as a primordial category of social rela
tions? The first question was about the nation-state, the second about the
nation: it is the second question which continues to be relevant to a discussion
of later theorists including Durkheim and Weber. And it is this second ques
tion which remains the hardest to answer. Indeed the difficulty is intensified
by the way in which now, a century later, both contemporary marxism and
mainstream sociology are divided between those who continue to treat the
nation, in an untheorized way, as a deeply embedded historical formation,
and those who over-emphasize its culturally invented modernity. Nor is the
situation improved by those who attempt to hold these two extremes within
the one approafh. Tom Nairn's position exemplifies how, by sharply dividing
the categories of nation and nation-state, of nationalism and nationalism, the
Janus perspectives of primordialism and modernism can be simultaneously
held in an unsatisfactory dual focus.
Parallel tensions between primordialism and modernism in Marx's position
were masked partly by his political consistency, and partly by the forms of
social relations he was describing. As an acute observer of his times, he rec
ognized the phenomenal surge of late nineteenth-century internationalization,
but without recourse to something like an analytic metaphor of constitutive
levels, he overemphasized its one-dimensional, flattening force. Changes were
occurring that could not be adequately handled within the terms of a
base-superstructure framework. The rapid development of the means and
relations of disembodied extension including the newspaper and telegraph
were, in intersection with expanded commodity circulation and the trans
port revolution, contributing to connecting the globe at a more abstract level
of integration. These changes in the mode of integration also became part of
the transfiguration of hometown society and the uneven consolidation of the
nation-state - hence the overlap or coincidence of apparently antithetical
subjectivities, from romantic longings for the blood and soil attachments of
the village, and commonsense assumptions about the primordiality of the
nation, to cosmopolitan desires for a 'brotherhood of mankind'. Moreover,
Themes for a Theory of the Nation 181
despite the way in which a dominant level of integration was reconstituting
prior forms, it was an uneven process occurring more as the intersection-in
dominance of different forms of integration than the supplanting or complete
dissolution of the old. Resistance to the modernizing tidal wave of capitalism
and nation-state was common in the late nineteenth century, even if para
doxically the act of resistance itself also contributed to the reconstitution of
older ways of life.
Marx was formed by his time, and yet as an intellectual who, qua intellec
tual, worked in the abstracting medium of the written and printed word, he
was doubly sensitive to the dissolution of old certainties and the abstraction
of prior forms of social life. He was driven to 'discover' abstract categories of
social relations such as class which provided a new conception of unity-in-dis
unit y. These analytic categories helped to deconstruct and to put back
together a world which could no longer be explained so comfortably in terms
of natural communities, natural rights and theories of social contract.
However, national formation held an ambiguous place in this new schema.
The nation remained, in Marx's vocabulary, unself-consciously and quies
cently, an effective representation of the real ties of the past (his phrase),
while by contrast the nation-state came to be viewed as an illusory sovereignty
producing persons as 'fictitious phenomena' (his emphasis), and as a repre
sentation of the artificial veils of the present which would eventually drop
away to reveal the real conditions of existence.
Weber and Durkheim also wrote of themselves as working through the
methodology of abstraction, finding generalities from out of the disarray of
particulars, and seeing through the veils of the immediately apparent. But,
writing a generation or so after Marx, they could no longer be so sure that the
nation-state would dissolve into globalism. World War I was a war of dis
solving empires and consolidating nation-states, a war confirming the death
of the old absolutist states. Moreover, the classical theorists faced the uneasy
possibility that nothing lay behind the veils and chimeras of the phenomenal
world. In this age of subjectivist culture (Weber) the early twentieth-century
theorists responded by concluding that politics could only be derived from
what 'is'. For Durkheim, 'the fatherland in abstracto' thus had to be seen as
'the normal and indispensable milieu of human life'. The nation-state was the
highest existent 'embodiment of the idea of humanity'. For Weber, the
nation-state was the most obvious existent source of meaning in the struggle
against the iron cage of rationalization.
Nation Formation provides only partial answers to the question of why
theorists of the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries did not develop
more than implicit theories of the nation and nation-state. And the method
ology of constitutive levels provides only a tentative means of entry into
understanding the classical theorists, not an automatic or a priori grid against
which to map the emphases and aporias of their work. Nevertheless, it enables
the beginnings of an approach which takes seriously the relationship between
theory and the world time in which, and for which, theory is written. The
classical theorists were products of their time and place, but not in the simple
182 Nation Formation
sense that an orthodox base-superstructure position would have it. Their
ideas did not simply derive from the dominant mode of production, nor did
they express the dominant episteme of discourses. Neither can it be said that
their ideas floated free as the ponderings of unique (charismatic) individuals.
By positing an intersection q.f analytically distinguishable, ontologically
inharmonious levels, the abstraction thesis attempts to allow for the com
plexity of the object-subject relation. Secondly, it attempts to allow for the
different conclusions reached by divergent thinkers, while giving some sense
of the commonalities of the avant-gardist thrust. And thirdly, it accents the
contradictory modes of being of the theorists themselves.
Marx, Durkheim and Weber may have been contributors to an incipient
stage of what was discussed as the rise of the cultural. This push to decon
struct taken-for-granted categories of social ontology had precedents, of a
kind, going back to the late-medieval period and the poets of the vernacular
such as Petrarch and Dante - but when taken in comparison with the urgency
of debate in the late twentieth century, the depth of the deconstructive project
even in fin-de-siec/e Europe was relatively contained. Issues of the contin
gency of human nature and sexual difference, the arbitrariness of linguistic
meaning, and the modernity of national formation, to mention only a few,
waited well into the twentieth century before eliciting the direct, sustained
attention of social theorists.
When I first began reading through the work of Nairn, Gellner and
Giddens I assumed that they all had fairly comprehensive theories of the
nation and nation-state. While each expressed his theoretical method in quite
different ways, they all had a broad interest in relating structures and relations
of production, exchange and communication, and linking issues of social
form (object rel_ations) with recurrent patterns of sensibility and subjectivity
(subject relafions). They managed to sustain a rejection of orthodox primor
dialism with analyses which qualified one-dimensional modernism by ranging
across contemporary to early modern history, probing the centuries prior to
the nineteenth century, and thus giving consideration to the long-run trans
formations which frame the relatively recent conjunction of nation and state.
However, in the course of unfolding a critical description of their general the
ories it became clear that their explanatory insight was much more oriented
towards understanding the nation-state rather than towards analysing the
long-run integration of the nation. In so far as they implicitly accept that
nations existed (and exist) which were not bound by the agency-extension of
state apparatuses, their theories left the nation floating in ambiguity, as an
independent social form yet one entirely dependent upon its framing by the
state.
It was Tom Nairn who wrote the words that 'the theory of nationalism rep
resents Marxism's great historical failure'. His own work goes some distance
towards ameliorating that situation; however, as argued, Nairn tends to treat
the original formation of the 'historic' nation as an unproblematic historical
given. His theorizing begins with the effect on the periphery of the nine
teenth-century tidal wave of forces of production and military power
Themes for a Theory of the Nation 183
emanating out of the metropolitan centres of Europe. This generated what he
called nationalism proper (a curious phrase suggesting a kind of teleology).
Against this, Nairn implicitly uses a concept of the 'natural' or 'historic
nation' - always effectively used in inverted commas. It allows him simulta
neously to avoid the critique of essentialism or primordialism, and yet
continue to view the 'historic nation' through the first face of Janus, that of
deep or primordial history. As an evasive tactic it almost works: as an unac
knowledged theoretical assumption it carries the cost of avoiding the issue of
how complex social forms such as the nation generate complex ontological
contradictions. Amongst these we might include the contradictions that
although the nation is an abstract community, a community which extends
far beyond the boundaries of kinship relations or attachment to a perceptible
place, it continually recalls 'concrete' images of blood and soil; that although
it is a paradigmatically modern social formation it is materially grounded in
historically long-run social forms; and that although it is imagined as terri
torially contained and culturally bounded, the persons who most strongly
asserted those 'theories' were, in its early stages, intellectuals who were just as
likely to be cosmopolitan in orientation as nationalists.
On the face of it Anthony Giddens presents us with a more comprehensive
theory and history of the nation and nation-state than that attempted by
Tom Nairn. Giddens' contribution is crucial as a launching point for any dis
cussion of theories for an alternative theory of the nation. However, in the
final analysis, he too bypasses the necessity of theorizing the cultural contra
dictions of national formation. Built into his definition of the nation-state is
the assertion that the nation 'only exists when a state has a unified adminis
trative reach over the territory over which its sovereignty is claimed'. It is, I
suggest, an aspect of his Weberian overemphasis upon the changing forms of
administration which structure political and military power, and his dis
placement of a broader discussion of the forms of social relations and
subjectivities into a narrower focus on nationalism as ideology or psychology.
Hence, despite some exceptional passages of writing Giddens tends to reduce
the nation to one level of social practice - the institutional - and to the over
riding predominance of one level of social integration - the agency-extended.
Questions associated with understanding the nation as a materially extended
(in his term, time-space distantiated) and abstracted relation between
strangers are left unaddressed. They sit alongside other ontological ques
tions about the subjectivity of national formations in the relatively
untheorized space between his analyses of the territorialization of the state,
and the state management of the ideology of nationalism.
Of the three contemporary writers studied in detail, Ernest Gellner has the
strongest interest in systematically analysing the kinds of cultural changes
associated with national formation. He examines such themes as the (abstract
ing) tendency of the move towards universal literacy, the break with parochially
context-dependent communication, and an increasing cultural homogeneity
ushered in as a new level of cultural integration or what he calls a single, con
tinuous conceptual space. However, in positing this 'high cultural', nationally
184 Nation Formation
framed, conceptual space it seems that Gellner, as much as Tom Nairn or
Anthony Giddens, is unable to account for the tensions, contradictions and dif
ferences (and yet interpenetration) between the cosmopolitan, the national
and 'residual' pockets of parochialism, between the dominant culture and sub
ordinate or emergent cultures, �nd between the realms of the public and the
private. The nation appears to be given the appearance of having a homoge
neous constitutive force. Thus, a paradoxical issue such as the febrile fragility
of the postmodern nation cannot be handled adequately within his particular
way of theorizing the rise of the cultural. Tqis is so even though he recognizes
that within the boundaries of the new formations culture has a new fluidity and
persons are increasingly mobile.
How then might a constitutive abstraction argument begin to handle some
of these problems? After a resume of the central thesis, the rest of these con
cluding remarks will be devoted to drawing out some of the problems which
continue to beset even the most ambitious interpretative approaches to
national questions.
The central thesis connecting the book is that the nation is an abstract com
munity which only becomes possible within a social formation constituted
through the emerging dominance of relations of disembodied extension. It is
not a proposition which I have attempted to prove, though there is no doubt
that even on non-empiricist grounds the approach would benefit from a fur
ther volume of historical exploration. Rather, it has been presented here as a
working proposition infused with historical examples and embedded in a
matrix of methodological premises and definitions. Those premises and def
initions can be summarized as follows.
I The concept of abstraction has been stretched beyond its normal usage
to refer to a 11rocess that occurs both in thought and practice. The most obvi
ous examples of abstraction as a material process are the commodity and
labour abstractions and the abstraction of time and space that occurs in the
practices of writing and literacy, in particular in the work of intellectuals. In
each of these, the process depends upon a confluence of modes of thinking
and acting, though not upon any active cognizance of its generalizing impli
cations by the persons who nevertheless actively participate in the structuring
of social life beyond face-to-face interaction.
2 The term community is used in a way which underlines an important
aspect of its richness as a concept, namely as direct relations of mutuality and
commonality: the 'contrasts, increasingly expressed in C19, between, the
more direct, more total and therefore more significant relations of community
and the more formal, more abstract, and more instrumental relationships of
state, or of society in its modern sense ... ' 1 This meaning is counterposed to
its much looser (often more abstract) use in contemporary parlance. In the
present we do not baulk at using the term to describe associations of com
plete strangers or abstract entities such as the global community, or persons
who happen to have an incidental commonality, including the community of
l. Raymond Williams, Keywords, 1976, p. 66.
Themes/or a Theory of the Nation 185
American Express card-users or travellers with Singapore Airlines. While the
nation of strangers is based upon more than an incidental commonality, con
joining the terms abstract and community emphasizes this tension of
meanings. It creates an oxymoron that hints at the issue of what has been
called ontological contradiction.
3 An ontological contradiction reaches into the more concrete grounding
conditions of social practice and social subjectivity, and yet depends upon the
abstraction of those conditions in the context of more abstract levels of social
integration. Numerous examples have been used here throughout, from the
dilemma of the king's two bodies to the way a national cenotaph, quite empty
of particular human remains, calls upon us to remember fallen compatriots as
both actually dead and abstractly representative of a spirit that lives on. In
terms of the abstraction thesis the discussion of contradiction entails no
implicit Hegelian or even orthodox marxist assumptions about the evolu
tion of history, or a teleology of outcomes. An ontological contradiction is
defined as a manifold of opposing modalities formed in the intersection of
levels of social integration.
4 The term social integration is intended to be used without any conno
tations of social life being inherently either a consensual or conflictual
process. It is not the opposite of social fragmentation. For example, it is pos
sible, as in the setting of the postmodern nation, to argue that there has
occurred a privatization and fragmentation of social life at the level of
face-to-face relations, while also suggesting that the nation is constituted and
held together in the dominance of a more abstract level of integration.
5 To speak of constitutive levels is only to invoke an analytic and abstract
word-picture. According to this methodological metaphor the complexities of
a particular social formation can be analysed usefully in terms of levels of
social integration intersecting in dominance. In one way it is no more than a
methodological way of avoiding certain problems such as treating social life
as if it were constituted on one plane, that is, as one dimensional, evenly
changing, consensual, or merely bounded by a grid of time-space pathways
traceable on a social theorist's map. In another way, certain political impli
cations flow from an elaboration of the levels metaphor. These are
implications that have barely been touched upon, but that will be taken up in
a brief coda before we close.
6 The concept of 'treating social life as if it were constituted on one plane'
is used as a shorthand way of criticizing those theories which reduce the
complexity of a social formation or even of all social formations to a single
dominant ontology. There may still be a recognition by those same theorists
that social life is conducted along different time-space extensions, from
face-to-face interactions to more disembodied interactions mediated through
the electronic media, but the actuality of constitutively different human
natures formed across different societies, and the possibility of contradic
tory subjectivities formed within the same society or the same person, are
often either disregarded or relegated to the realm of psychoanalysis.
Three sub-themes amongst others were continually emerging as issues
186 Nmion Formation
around which to elaborate the central theme of the nation as an abstract
community and to develop the methodology of constitutive levels. They can
now be expressed with inflexions towards existing theory.
The subject-object theme: 1he problem of understanding the relation
between subjectivity and (objective) social relations, and between ways of
thinking and the structures of social practice, without setting up a theo
retical chasm between ideologies of nationalism and structures of the
nation-state.
2
The primordiality-modernity theme: the problem of theorizing the moder
nity of the intersection of nation and state, and the recent emergence of
nationality as a generalized form of social relations, without losing sight of
the way in which social forms constitutive of the nation have long-run con
tinuities such as are exemplified in the medieval natio.
3
The theme of intellectual practice: the problem of holding together the con
tradictory being of one of the central groupings in the story of nations, that
is, the role of intellectuals and later the intellectually trained as, on the one
hand, crucial in articulating the connections of the early natio, providing
points of reference and gathering archives for emergent national cultures,
staffing the new bureaucracies of agency-extension, leading oppositional
nationalist movements, or instrumentally managing cultural campaigns to
legitimize the dominant state, and, on the other hand, as 'free personalities'
(Meinecke) most open to the call of cosmopolitanism or post-national dis
dain for the boundaries of place.
As much as it is possible to separate out these themes they will be taken up
one by one.
The subject of nationalism and the object of enquiry
There can be no pretence that the venerable old question of the relation
between subject and object will be brought to a satisfactory resolution over the
next few paragraphs. At its broadest it covers the relation between the person
(as subject) and the social structures of human relations, the recursive practices
lived across various levels of abstraction. More narrowly it concerns the rela
tion between ideas and structures. A full response to the question requires a
theory of the subject far beyond the resources of this book. There are, however,
problems within this theme of more specific relevance to a theory of the nation
around which we can draw some tentative conclusions.
What is the relation between the subjectivities of nationalism and national
identity and the (objective) structures of the nation and nation-state? In what
sense is the nation a cultural invention? And how far do such questions take us?
Themes for a Theory of the Nation 187
One of the apparent strengths of the contemporary theorists whom we dis
cussed is their common quest to theorize the constitutive milieu in which ideas
of nationalism arose, and to relate nationalism to the material conditions of
nationhood and state formation without collapsing nationalist ideas into a
derivative relation to specifically national structures.However, each in his own
way fails to achieve this balance.Anthony Giddens falls to one side with his
claim that nationalism is the 'concomitant of the co-ordination of administrative
power within the bounded nation-state'; 2 and Ernest Gellner falls to the other
side in effectively arguing that nationalisms bring nations into being:
'Nationalism ... sometimes takes pre-existing cultures and turns them into
nations, sometimes invents them, and often obliterates pre-existing cultures.'3
Tom Nairn takes it in both directions at once. On the one hand, he says that
'Many new "nations" had to think away millennia of oblivion, and invent almost
entirely fictitious pasts'. 4 On the other hand, he says (as indeed would Gellner
when pressed and Giddens given certain qualifications) that 'Nationalism in the
real sense is never an historical accident, or a mere invention.It reflects the lat
est fracture-lines of human society under strain.'5 The tension between these two
positions does not amount to an insurmountable contradiction; nevertheless it
requires explanation beyond the rise of the notion of invention.
None of the theorists we discussed would hold the modernist, cultural
inventionist thesis to its reductive and idealist end, but to the extent that
they 'stress the element of artefact, invention and social engineering which
enters into the making of nations',6 they undermine the way in which their
theories purport to be theories-of-the-constitutive.In other words, they need
to develop an argument as to why, and under what conditions, cultural inven
tion arises as an historical practice.Cultural invention might be better
described as an emergent ontological relation to time and space based on a
sense of historicity which turns the past into a source of authenticity. Under
conditions which break the nexus of time with kinship or the sacred, that is,
in empty time, the past becomes a source of artefacts and condensed mean
ings available for displaying in the present, and a series of calendrical
reference points which mark the passage of progress. As the subjectivity of
persons came to be constituted in an overlay of more abstract extensions of
time and space it became meaningful (and possible given developing tech
niques and technologies of information storage and transmittal) to dredge the
past for the roots of the present.In the process, historical practices and
2. Anthony Giddens, The Nation-State and Violence, 1985, p. 219.
3. Ernest Geliner, Nations and Nationalism, 1983, p. 49.
4. Tom Nairn, The Break-up of Britain: Crisis and Neo-Nationalism, 1981, p. 105.
5. Ibid., p. 323.
6. These words of Eric Hobsbawm's express the stress he too wants to place on the element of
cultural invention (Nations and Nationalism since I 780, 1990, p. I 0). Further down the page
Hobsbawm agues that nations are 'constructed essentially from above'. His proviso that at the
same time they should be analysed from below is, I suggest, inadequate to analysing the com
plexity of intersecting constitutive levels. Brilliant historians do not necessarily make brilliant
social theorists.
188 Na1io11 Formation
meanings are thoroughly reworked and relatively new practices and rituals
become historicized. But whether the ascriptions of self-conscious knowl
edgeability implied in the term cultural invention provide an appropriate
description of these contradictory reworkings is doubtful. It is true that cul
tural management was important to development of a generalized national
consciousness. indeed it has become even more important in the age of post
modern image-politics. but cultural management was itself made possible
within larger social changes. In the same way, nationalism did not invent the
nation: and the nation-state was not a necessary setting for the invention of
the doctrine of nationalism. Both emerged, I have argued, with the histori
cally uneven abstraction of community and polity.
A theory of constitutive abstraction developed by such theorists as Geoff
Sharp may not be the best way to proceed to a better understanding of the
subjectivity and objective relations of national formation. but it does help to
overcome some of the problems of existing theory. It is partly that the notion
of abstraction, in its modified meaning adopted here, carries a sense of a
process pertaining both to ideas and material relations, but, more than that,
it is helped by the way the levels metaphor relates forms of subjectivity to par
ticular social formations without reducing the former to the latter. This can
be restated in a brief example.
The emotional evocation by the late-medieval poet Petrarch of an abstract
place called llalia was expressed long before Italy was politically unified. It is
tempting to call this sentiment patriotism, but it was neither an attachment to
the patria in the more concrete sense of an allegiance to the patriarchal
monarch nor in the more abstract sense which developed in the eighteenth
century of an allegiance to the sovereign state. Petrarch's evocation was pos
sible centuries before the various factors identified by Nairn, Gellner and
Giddens as central to the nation. including the development of industrialism
or expansionist capitalism or post-patrimonial administrative apparatus, had
developed any purchase on the subjective being of the populace of the
Apennine peninsula .
Because Nairn, Gellner and Giddens in their different ways locate the idea
and subjectivity of nationality in periodized, and what might be called facto
rial, analyses of national formation,7 they are unable for example to take
hold of the possibility of materially grounded subjectivities which long before
the nation-state came into being could abstract a territorial or cultural con
nection between strangers. Clearly, Italia was not then a nation in the modern
sense of the term, but what Petrarch expressed, along with other individuals
and groupings from out of the strata of intellectuals, merchants and clerics
(particularly those exiled, on legatine missions, or in some way deracinated),
7. I am not rejecting the possibility of any form of periodizing so much as the way in which the
periodizing comes to dominate the possibility of recognizing 'continuous' social forms which
(analytically at least) can be said to run across particular social formations. Similarly I am not
rejecting the documentation of factors central to national formation but rather objecting to the
way in which different levels of analysis are conflated.
Themes for a Theory of the Nation 189
was a sense of attachment to place much more akin to that of classical nation
alism than our contemporary theorists are prepared to allow.
Contemporary theorists respond in two ways. They either preclude the rel
evance of an exploration of the conditions grounding this subjectivity because
of a (well-founded) aversion to the implicit primordialism found in the bevy
of pre- l 960s discussions of 'medieval nationalism', or, like Tom Nairn, they
consign such phenomena to an untheorized black box labelled 'historic
nations' . By using the levels metaphor it becomes possible to argue that
through a manifold of quite material processes - writing and reading, trans
acting inter-regional financial deals based on the abstraction of money, living
in exile from one's natus, and so on - certain individuals and groupings in
late-medieval Italia were lifted, in one capacity of their being, on to a level
that enabled them to abstract a community of strangers, or at least to con
ceive of an 'abstract place' disembodied from the particularizing attachments
which hitherto gave it meaning. They were able to do so even though the
dominant levels of integration on the Apennine peninsula were such that
most of their compatriots could not have thought of, let alone lived by, that
same conception.
The levels metaphor also bears back upon the theory itself. Developing the
theory of national formation further and adequately broadening out the
scope of explanation to include such modes of subjectivity as evinced in
Petrarch's evocation, I have argued, entails working both at a more abstract
level of theorizing and at a more concrete level of detailed research. The pre
sent text has tended in its methodological discussions (as distinct from its
historical discussions) to emphasize the most abstract kind of form analysis,
but a fully fledged approach would have to relate to a meta-theory, sitting in
the background, which indicated how the theory itself could be cast at dif
ferent epistemological levels of abstraction: from a form analysis of different
modes of social integration and subjectivity (hence, the levels of social inte
gration argument); through an analysis of particular social formations which
incorporates comparative discussions of the dominant modes of production,
exchange, communication, organization and enquiry; to more concretely
couched examinations of particular conjunctures and settings, regional dif
ferences and personal including psychological histories.
Rather than being too self-conscious about this point, the present book has
left it largely implicit, allowing the analysis to shift between the various lev
els of theoretical abstraction without signalling those shifts. Indeed, it would
be unnecessarily distracting and awkward to do so. A fully fledged approach
in bringing together various theoretical levels could incorporate, without too
much methodological declaiming, some of the theory and much of the con
tent of explanation engaged in by Tom Nairn in emphasizing the uneven
spread of capitalism; by Ernest Gellner in emphasizing the processes of indus
trialization and the development of a new education-sanctioned subjectivity;
or by Anthony Giddens in emphasizing the binding of subjectivities within
the formation of military-<:apitalist states.
At the centre of that critical reflection, and relevant to the subject-object
190 Narion Formarion
relation, has been a concern to avoid the problem of treating subjectivity
either as split along the Great Divide between traditional and modem soci
eties or conversely as continuing across history in a relatively homogeneous
way. Anthony Giddens, despite occasional passages to the contrary, tends
towards the latter by privileging the constitutional form of the modem indi
vidual, that is, the self-active subject making history knowledgeably. He
attempts to avoid the problem by treating social action as constrained or
enabled within quite different time-space settings, but this still tends to leave
social life as different kinds of practices set-on one transhistorical ontological
plane. 8 Ernest Gellner, by contrast, theorizes a manifest ontological trans
formation in the transition from agrarian to industrial societies, but his
position tends towards setting up a Great Divide in so far as his description
of industrial society separates it entirely from 'prior' subjectivities. Ideas and
identities are framed in Gellner's industrial society by a monolithic, homog
enizing culture-polity. He thus avoids the problem of setting up a
homogeneous subjectivity-in-general which crosses history, only to reduce
the subjectivity of industrial society to a single, historically specific, ontolog
ical plane.9 Tom Nairn appears to get around both of these problems, but only
by leaving the fractured faces of social life unresolved.
Discussion of the Great Divide takes us into the second theme of primor
diality and modernity.
Nation formation as both primordial and modern?
Implicit throughout the last section were questions relevant to the area of pri
mordialism and modernism. T hey either came up as a series of overlapping
tensions - the historically embedded or the culturally invented, the authentic
or the artificial, the historical or the historicized, and the traditional or the
modem - or they were expressed as metaphors of cleavage: the Janus-faced,
and the Great Divide. To avoid being repetitive this section concentrates on
the concept of continuity-in-discontinuity.
T he reasons elaborated by contemporary theorists in so rigorously dis
paraging primordialist arguments have tended to be well founded.
Essentialism, idealism, a tendency to treat social phenomena as if they cut
across history oblivious to the reproductive structures of contemporary social
life, functionalist assertions of basic human needs such as the need to belong,
and the positing of a primal human nature, are all possible pitfalls along the
primordialist path. It is possible to avoid these problems by treating human
history as completely discontinuous and theorizing the nation as pertaining
8. Giddens could avoid this criticism by making the claim for 'self-active subjectivity' as an
expressly abstract methodological point and then, on a less abstract 'theoretical level', distin
guishing different forms of 'self-active subjectivity'.
9. Gellner could avoid this criticism by arguing for a dominant but not exclusive level of sub
jectivity, rather than for a single cultural space of meaning.
Themes for a Theory of the Nation 191
only to the period of modernity (and postmodernity), but this pathway is
beset by another series of pitfalls summarized in the critique of theories as set
on one plane. The concept of continuity-in-discontinuity is part of an attempt
to find a third way.
This alternative rests upon distinctions being made between more concrete
conjunctural description (Level I), comparative analysis of social formations
(Level II), and the more abstract ways of analysing social form (Levels III and
IV). The distinction is only an analytic one. Nevertheless, what the distinction
allows, amongst other things, is a way of distinguishing between levels of
continuity and discontinuity. At the more concrete level of analysis of social
formations and specific conjunctures a discontinuous history of national asso
ciations and political administrations can be quickly sketched: 10
• The late-medieval development of associations called nationes (single,
natio) and the emergence for some of an abstract sense of place. 11
• The early modern abstraction of state apparatuses, though within the
patrimonial political form of the kingdom or empire.
• The post-sixteenth-century politicization of the concept of the nation,
although with the predominant political structure remaining that of king
dom or empire.
• The emergence of explicitly nationalist movements from around the early
nineteenth century.
• The rise of a public sphere in association with ideologies of public sover
eignty and national citizenship.
• The uneasy nineteenth-century conjunction of national citizenry and
abstract state, forming in some cases what has been called the classical
modern nation-state.
• The late twentieth-century postmodern nation, associated both with the
rise of the new and neo-nationalisms and with the overpassing of national
borders by an increasingly globalized flow of culture, capital and per
sons.
The past is a thoroughly unfamiliar place; in ways that contemporary sen
sibilities tend to block out, the extent of this discontinuity with the present is
subjectively confronting. However, from a more abstract vantage point it is
possible to conceive of continuities in the discontinuity of social formations
and practices in a way which does not succumb to the contemporary, nostal
gic tendency to flatten the past into a rustic or undeveloped version of the
present. This abstracted view of continuity is exemplified in a comparison of
two quite different types of association set within two completely disparate
kinds of social formation.
The late-medieval nationes at the University of Bologna were small com
munities of scholars formed within a loosely connected system of city-states
10. This sketch obviously is neither sufficiently comprehensive nor detailed enough to give any
sense or regional differences.
11. My argument here docs not depend upon this being the first such emergence.
192 Nmion Formation
and kingdoms, whereas the contemporary Australian nation is a much more
extended multicultural community, largely built out of pan-continental
migration, bound by state borders, and set within a global system of other
nation-states. Social theorists w Australia are beginning to describe it as a
postmodern nation. In short, at this level of description the nationes of
lfologna and the nation-state of Australia are fundamentally different. Yet
they both are part of a continuity of social forms. Both, I suggest, are abstract
communities where the social practices and subjectivities which integrate
them as communities are formed in an overlay of relations of disembodied
extension (even if that overlay is set within quite different configurations of
less abstract, intersecting levels of integration). Both communities, drawing
upon practices constituted at a disembodied level of abstraction, 'call upon'
less abstract levels to give their association a depth of meaning. Both com
munities connect strangers in terms of affiliations expressed through a
continuing but subordinate level of face-to-face integration.
This argument needs far more historical filling out than is possible here (a
second volume will be necessary to do this), but it should be made clear that
the argument only suggests that there are some continuities of social form,
not that the practices and means of disembodied extension are the same. In
the case of contemporary Australia, it is the mass media which most promi
nently provide a means of disembodied extension between people who at the
level of the face-to-face may or may not have fleeting visual contact, proba
bly will not have any interaction, and except for immediate kin most certainly
will not be bound by very full ties of face-to-face integration. 12 It is by learn
ing of their (national) history and culture through generic intellectual
training in a state-based education system, by reading books and newspapers,
and by watching television broadcasts, replays and re-enactments of signifi
cant 'events' that contemporary Australians will most frequently reinforce
both their sense of simultaneity with their eighteen million living compatri
ots and their connection to those who came before them. In the case of the
late-medieval natio, community is formed, and divisions are generated,
through the held-in-common experience of at one level being lifted out of the
more parochial constraints of place while at another level still subjectively
having one's identity constituted by those constraints. The practices which lift
the medieval cleric out of the parochial, range from simply travelling to
Bologna or Paris or Oxford and facing strangers of a different natus, to the
possibilities of translocating in time and space principally through the activ
ities of reading and writing. In other words, social forms which have a
recognizable continuity can be constituted through practices with markedly
different content and set at a different point in world time. 13 Hence, in terms
12. Throughout, the terms 'contact', 'interaction' and 'integration' have been used to designate
progressively higher degrees of mutuality in face-to-face relations.
13. This is not to disagree with Benedict Anderson's point that 'The world-historical era in
which each nationalism is born probably has a significant impact on its scope.' See Imagined
Communities, 1991, p. 63.
Themes for a Theory of the Nation 193
of the speculative thesis presented here that national association only
becomes possible within social formations constituted in the contradictory
dominance-in-intersection of relations of disembodied extension, the natio is
different from but continuous with the modern nation.
Intellectual practice and the abstraction of community
The relevance of intellectual practice to the national question suggested itself
for a number of reasons. Firstly, it is integral to any reflexive study of the
nation and its theorizers. Theorists of the nation are by definition engaged in
intellectual practice, and even such an apparently politically disengaged prac
tice as writing about national formation bears back upon the lived reality of
nationhood. In a work that attempts to understand some of the underpin
nings of the theorizing process and how those same social forms and practices
which ground the nation rebound upon the practices and assumptions of
theorists, the theme of the practice of intellectuals could not be avoided.
Secondly, it was relevant because intellectuals and the intellectually trained
have been in the forefront of both oppositional nationalist movements and
the official nationalisms of the old and new empires and states. Thirdly, intel
lectual training, via state-education systems, became after the late nineteenth
century one of the central reproducers of a form of culture which was both
inseparable from the practical and imaginative lives of national citizens as
well as indispensable to their administration by the centralized state: this
'dual' process was crucial to the intersection of relations of agency-extension
and disembodied extension.
While Anthony Giddens makes no direct statement on the role of intellec
tuals and the intellectually trained in the development of nations and
nation-states it remains, in effect, an unacknowledged ellipsis connecting his
argument. The growth of a public sphere of textually mediated state admin
istration is at the centre of his theory. Yet the ellipsis marks the question, 'who
are the actors in this sphere?' He leaves aside the issues of how such appara
tuses are dependent upon new kinds of intellectual training, and what
happens to clerics as their relationship to the prince is systematically
abstracted - that is, becomes increasingly post-patrimonial, depersonalized,
desanctified, rationalized, centralized and dependent upon the storage of
information over time and space. Giddens passes over questions about the
subjective practice and contradictory (or liminal) position of the intellectually
trained, a move which, as writers such as Benedict Anderson and Anthony
Smith indicate, is to miss out on an important aspect of national integration.
By contrast, Tom Nairn and Ernest Gellner place these themes of intellec
tuals and intellectual training more explicitly within their theoretical pictures
(at least in the second and third senses as used above). For Tom Nairn, intel
lectuals and the intellectually trained, or what he fuses together as the new
intelligentsia, provide the medium through which nationalism is refracted
into a given society: 'spreading from the top downwards' the intelligentsia is
194 Nation Formation
pivotal to the diffusion of the idea, even if it is compelled to put nationalist
concerns into the language of the 'popular mass still located upon an anterior
level of development ...upon a level of (almost literally) "prehistoric" diver
sity' .14 While this argument his some force, it tends to concentrate upon
nationalism as an idea: one simply diffused by a certain class of persons.The
relation of intellectuals to the subjectivity of nationalism becomes reduced to
the ideologically couched self-interest of that class, albeit a constrained
self-interest, in mobilizing a cross-class alliance against outside intrusions.
Here Ernest Gellner's approach ironic1llly is more thoroughgoing than
Nairn's historical materialism in exploring the material conditions of the
relation between intellectual training and nationhood. Gellner's theory has
parallels with Tom Nairn's in emphasizing 'active cleavages of interest' which
arise in the uneven process of modernization, cleavages which throw intellec
tuals back upon the traditional markings of cultural identity to legitimize
both themselves and a new integrative (national) culture. However, Gellner
puts this process in the context of the breakdown of prior regional cultures
and the subsequent cultural importance of state-sponsored education sys
tems.This, he says, takes us 'some of the way towards a schematic explanation
of nationalisms: these factors explain why in general (abstracting from local
complications) modern loyalties are centred on political units'. 15
There is a nice ambiguity in Gellner's phrase 'abstracting from local com
plications' which unintentionally accords with the theoretical approach taken
by this book. Clearly what Gellner means is that he, Ernest Gellner, is
abstracting from the particular in making the generalizations he does. The
present text goes further again.It has generalized from issues of epistemology
and methodolo_gy to suggest that the process of abstraction is crucial to the
possibility of intellectual work. Those processes which were discussed as
being most relevant to the relation between intellectual practice and the for
mation of nations were the abstractions of time and space carried by the
techniques and technologies of information storage.From these steps in the
argument we are able to reflect upon intellectual practice, attempting to
understand some of the underpinnings of the theorizing process and how
those same social forms and practices which ground the nation rebound upon
the practices and assumptions of the theorists of national formation.
As intellectuals qua intellectuals, Marx, Weber and Durkheim worked in a
medium which materially transcended the dominant modalities of time and
space pertaining during their lifetimes.They interrogated dead authors, made
comparisons to long-disappeared communities, and projected the possibilities
of current political trajectories into future worlds. At the same time, as embod
ied human beings they not only consciously experienced the contradictory
constraints of time and place, but also were formed in ways which slipped
under the intellectual guard of self-conscious reflexivity, and, more deeply,
which constituted their very subjectivity.For example, Weber's dispassionate/
14. Nairn, Break-up of Britain, 1981, pp. 100, IOI.
15. Ernest Gellner, 'Nationalism', 1981, p. 163.
Themes for a Theory of the Nation 195
passionate glorification of the community unto death carried the contradic
tions of the conjunction of intellectual rationalism and subjective 'need'.
Weber was logically and subjectively led to the glorification of war.
Distinguishing the forms of social relations (the rich, condensed intersection of
face-to-face and more abstract bonds forged in war}, from the blind stupidity,
degrading patriotism and senseless carnage of war did not seem to be a press
ing consideration in his schema of things. Whether the classical social theorists
chose a politics of internationalism or of abstract nationalism, the cultural
(and theoretical) means were not yet available for them to take apart the
grounds of that choice. The classical theorists simply took for granted rather
than felt the need to theorize the fact that they lived and worked in the
medium of homogeneous empty time and (national) historicity rather than
Messianic time; in a milieu dominated by territorially bounded (national)
space rather than by the ritually overdetermined condensations of place; and
in a period when the phrase the body politic had become a dead metaphor, no
longer evoking the philosophical conundrums of Hobbes' 'Mortall God' and
the doctrine of the King's Two Bodies.
If, as I have argued, national formation and subjectivity require as a
necessary-though-not-sufficient condition the abstraction of social relations
integrated in the emerging dominance of disembodied extension, then it
comes as no surprise that intellectuals and the intellectually trained are in the
forefront of imagining and enacting the nation. Such persons work in the
medium of disembodied extension. They have in this capacity played a sig
nificant part in the complex of basic changes in world history, changes which
have brought us to the stage when the nation is deeply embedded yet deeply
contradictory.
A political coda
Theoretical arguments, however abstract, can never be divorced from his
tory or be without political implications. The present book, written during a
time of considerable change in the configurations of international and domes
tic politics, is no exception. What does it mean that the political question
commonly posed in this area , namely 'Is national identity a good or a bad
thing?', has not been explicitly raised? In fact the question seems to be
bypassed. Given that Tom Nairn first used the metaphor of the nation as
Janus-faced in relation to the ambiguous ethical quality of nationalism, the
move made earlier to rework the metaphor in terms of the contradictory
ontology of nationality confirms this impression. In the current climate with
the call of nations into the Gulf War, with the crises in Eastern Europe and
the Baltic States, and with continual assertions of neo-nationalisms around
the globe the question remains vexing. However, it is I think the wrong focus
around which to frame a politics.
It is telling that the contemporary academic consensus on the question of
the ethical virtue of nationalism or national identity has tended towards
196 Na-tion Formation
responding ambivalently: 'it is and it is not'. The response, with its account
ing-styled adding up of historical examples on either side of a ledger, indicates
the unhelpful nature of the question. Asking whether nationality is good or
bad moves the focus excessivel�on to the moral content of political practice
rather than allowing for an examination of the constitutive form which
grounds (and is instantiated in) that practice. A focus on form can arguably
allow for a more thoroughgoing political ethics.
In developing a response to the coming period there are decisions which go
beyond asking whether we will support the national framework, or opt for
inter-nationalism, post-nationalism, cosmopolitanism, a return to the vil
lage, or some other alternative. As Michael lgnatieff writes, 'If patriotism,
Samuel Johnson remarked is the refuge of the scoundrel, so post-nationalism
and its accompanying disdain for the nationalist emotions of others, may be
the last refuge of the cosmopolitan.' 16 A deeper choice is faced. Is the onto
logical thinning out of social life through the constitutive dominance of the
most abstract levels of social relations an acceptable development? Or might
it not be preferable to work towards a form of social relations in which the
various constitutive levels are held in a rich, complex and mutually qualifying
manifold? This latter possibility would in practice throw up its own contra
dictions, particularly as the level of the face-to-face came to impose
significant constraints upon the 'openness', ephemerality and speed of post
modern life. It would mean that identification with the nation-state was
reduced to a subordinated aspect of a social relations of reciprocity and social
co-operation between persons living as members of less abstracted commu
nities.
This is not to.advocate a return to the boundaries of the parochial village,
even if it ever existed as the pastoral ideal suggested. It is rather to hope for
a new politics of human cooperation which does not reduce us to homeless
minds. It is to argue for a form of ontological socialism which does not reduce
politics either to wars of position in the public sphere or to struggles for state
control of the mode of production. It is to advocate a new kind of local
regional-global social relations, reaching across the boundaries of place but in
a way which does not reduce others to objects of our romantic or abstract
internationalism.
In all of this the nation will continue to have some relevance. By recogniz
ing that the nation-state will continue for the foreseeable future to be an
influential form of polity-community, albeit one caught between globalism
and localism, we can begin to avoid the potentially dangerous pulls of each.
We can begin to reconstruct the nation-state as a culturally based institution
that qualifies the ravages of globalism while being open to cultural diversity
within its borders; which works across and beyond the limitations of
parochial localism while protecting the rights of minorities. It seems ironical
now, as the modern nation-state falls from grace as the dominant centre of
16. Michael JgnatiefT, Blood and Belonging, 1994, p. 11.
Themes/or a Theory of the Nation 197
social relations, that it should offer the possibility of positively mediating
the local and the global. But then we live in different times. The openings are
there for a new kind of nation-state: a polity-community which, for example,
on the one hand writes into its constitution specific obligations to support
financially and politically the needs of strangers across the globe and, on the
other hand, sets up the legal and social conditions for local regions and face
to-face communities to take over more of the responsibility for managing
their own futures. In this kind of future the intermeshing extensions of local
ity, nationality and globality (and the contradictory intersections of more and
less abstract ways of relating to others) could work to qualify and enhance
each other rather than, as the prophets of globalism would have it, be
subsumed under the latest wave of rationalizing, commodifying, information
charged development.
This, however, is to begin another story, a story which as one nineteenth
century philosopher put it, needs to be worked out in practice rather than just
wrapped up in theory.
Appendix
Levels of Theoretical Abstraction
The overall argument is that a comprehensive theory of social relations and
subjectivities has to work across a manifold of levels of theoretical abstrac
tion. Below is set out one possible way of conceiving such a manifold.
Empirical generalization
(a) In particular
e.g. • Biographies of particular persons.
• Histories of particular polities such as 'post-settlement' Australia.
• Descriptions of particular institutions, fields of activity of discourses.
(b) In general
Drawing on particular accounts and studies, analysis at this level attempts to
be more comparative and to survey the longer term.
e.g. • Histories of the practices of 'personhood', gender relations, class
based lifeworlds.
• Comparative histories of a political form such as 'the nation-state'.
• Descriptions of an institution-in-general such as 'bureaucracy', fields
such as 'the law', or discourses such as 'social democracy'.
At this level, analysis that does not reach for more abstract ways of under
standing, runs the risk - however detailed its description - of superficiality or
empiricism. Nevertheless, empirical generalization remains a basic level of
analysis necessary to any approach in order to avoid abstract theoreticism.
II Analysis of modes of practice
(a) In particular
Analysis at this level of theoretical abstraction proceeds by resolution of par
ticular modes of practice. The present approach complicates 'classical
historical materialism' by analytically distinguishing at least five primary
modes.
1 Production (dominant and subordinate).
2 Exchange (dominant and subordinate).
3 Communication (dominant and subordinate).
Appendix 199
4 Organization (dominant and subordinate).
5 Enquiry (dominant and subordinate).
In practice, no mode of practice exists as a separate, autonomous form. The
rationale for this five-fold classification is that it avoids some of the reduc
tionism of a classical 'mode of production' approach without becoming too
unwieldy.
(b) In general
Drawing on analyses of particular modes of practice, analysis at this level
attempts to describe conjunctures between such modes. Generalizations are
made about the structural connections between dominant modes of practice,
thus allowing for the short-hand designation of formations of practice:
e.g. • (Reciprocal) tribalism
• (Absolutist) feudalism
• (Industrial) capitalism
• (Information) capitalism
• (Command economy) socialism.
These designations, as with all concepts of all classifying schemes, can only be
used as working appellations not reified entities. In practice, social formations
tend to be defined in terms of the dominant formation of practice, but this is
not to rule out subordinate formations.
Ill Analysis of modes of integration
(a) In particular
Analysis proceeds by resolution of levels of social integration (and differenti
ation). While in theory one could distinguish any number of levels of
integration, the present approach sets out three such levels:
l Face-to-face integration
2 Agency-extended integration
3 Disembodied integration.
In practice, no level of integration exists as a separate, autonomous form.
(b) In general
Drawing on analyses of levels of integration, generalizations can be made,
firstly, about the intersections between these (ontological) levels - for example,
charting the emergence of ontological contradictions - and, secondly, about
the complexities of social life as summarized at less and more abstract (epis
temological) levels of theoretical abstraction. Following the second path,
generalizations can be made which further enrich and contextualize our
understanding of particular life histories, fields and discourses (Level I),
200 Nation Formation
modes and formations of practice (II) and the ontological categories and
formations of social life (IV).
e.g. • Modern (industrial) capitalism
• Postmodern (information) capitalism
• Autonomous individualism
• Homogeneous disembodied time.
IV Categorical analysis
At this level, analysis works by reflexively 'deconstructing' categories of social
ontology. It attempts to take nothing for granted, including the epistemolog
ical and ontological assumptions of its own approach (especially the tendency
of some deconstructive projects to give priority to the so-argued 'liberatory'
potentialities of practices of deconstruction).
(a) In particular
Structural archaeologies (as distinct from 'classical' histories or descriptions -
see I(a) above) of particular categories of existence such as:
• Time and space
• Culture and nature
• Gender
• Embodiment
• Knowledge, language, theory.
(b) In general.
Drawing on aiscussions of particular ontological categories, generalizations
can be made about different forms of ontological formation, for example:
• Traditionalism
• Patriarchy
• Modernity
• Postmodernity.
As with all other concepts in the present approach to 'levels of theoretical
abstraction' they remain provisional concepts, provisional as tested against
the criterion 'Are they useful for understanding the complexities of social
life?' At this level, analysis which is not tied back into more concrete political
ethical considerations is in danger of abstracted irrelevance, utopianism with
out a subject, or empty spiritualism.
Bibliography
There are thousands of relevant sources on the national question. To make
this bibliography manageable it was necessary to list only references actually
cited in the footnotes. This has meant leaving out countless important writ
ings from E.H. Carr's Nationalism and After and Karl Deutsch's Tides Among
Nations to Aijaz Ahmad's In Theory: Classes, Nations, Literatures, many of
which were read or consulted. For further reading there are numerous bibli
ographical monographs which can be consulted: the Canadian Review of
Studies in Nationalism has published more than a dozen volumes of its spe
cialized annotated bibliography.
Abercrombie, Nicholas, Hill, Stephen and Turner, Bryan S. The Dominant
Ideology Thesis, London, George Allen and Unwin, 1984.
Abercrombie, Nicholas, Hill, Stephen and Turner, Bryan S. Sovereign
Individuals of Capitalism, London, Allen and Unwin, 1986.
Achebe, Chinua Things Fall Apart, London, Heinemann, {1958) 1974.
Acton, John Dalberg Essays on Freedom and Power, Glencoe, Free Press,
(1862) 1948.
Adamson, Alan 'Colonialism and Nationalism in Africa and Europe' (a
report on the fifth Past and Present conference), Past and Present, 24,
1963, pp. 65-74.
Agassi, J. 'Methodological Individualism', British Journal of Sociology, 11,
1960, pp. 244-270.
Agnew, John A. 'Political Regionalism and Scottish Nationalism in Gaelic
Scotland', Canadian Review of Studies in Nationalism, 8, I, 1981, pp.
I 15-129.
Alba, Victor Nationalists Without Nations: The Oligarchy Versus the People in
Latin America, New York, Frederick A. Praeger, 1968.
Allott, Kenneth Jules Verne, London, Cresset, (n.d.) c.1940.
Alomes, Stephen A Nation at Last? The Changing Nature of Australian
Nationalism 1880-1988, North Ryde, Angus and Robertson, 1988.
Althusser, Louis For Marx, London, Verso, (1965) 1979.
Althusser, Louis Lenin and Philosophy, and other Essays, New York, Monthly
Review Press, 1971.
Anderson, Benedict Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and
Spread of Nationalism, London, Verso, 1983; second edition 1991.
202 Nation
I
Formation
Anderson, Perry Lineages of the Absolutist State, London, Verso, (1974)
1986.
Anderson, Perry A Zone of Engagement, London, Verso, 1992.
Aries, Philippe The Hour of Our Death, Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1981.
Armstrong, John Nations befbre Nationalism, Chapel Hill, University of
North Carolina Press, 1982.
Amason, Johann 'The Modern Constellation and the Japanese Enigma: Part
I', Thesis JI, 11, 1987, pp. 4-39.
Auerbach, Erich Literary Language and its Public in Late Latin Antiquity
and in the Middle Ages, New York, Bollingen, 1965.
Avineri, Shlomo Hegel's Theory of the Modern State, London, Cambridge
University Press, 1972.
Aylmer, G.E. The King's Servants: The Civil Service of Charles I, 1625-1642,
London, Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1961.
Aylmer, G.E. The State's Servants: The Civil Service of the English Republic,
1649-1660, London, Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1973.
Balibar, Etienne and Wallerstein, Immanuel Race, Nation, Class, London,
Verso, 1991.
Barnard, F.M. 'National Culture and Political Legitimacy: Herder and
Rousseau', Journal of the History of Jdeas, 44, 2, 1983, pp. 231-253.
Barrett, William Irrational Man, New York, Doubleday, 1962.
Bartlett, John Familiar Quotations, London, Macmillan, (1882), fourteenth
edition 1977.
Baudrillard, Jean 'The Precession of Simulacra', Art and Text, 11, 1983, pp.
3-47.
Bauman, Zygmunt Culture as Praxis, London, Routledge and Kegan Paul,
1973.
Bauman, Zygmunt 'On the Origins of Civilization: A Historical Note',
Theory, Culture and Society, 2, 3, 1985, pp. 7-14.
Bauman, Zygmunt Modernity and Ambivalence, Cambridge, Polity Press,
1991.
Baumann, Gerd National Integration and Local Integrity: The Miri of the
Nuba Mountains in the Sudan, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1987.
Bean, Richard 'War and the Birth of the Nation-State', Journal of Economic
History, 33, 1, 1973, pp. 203-221.
Beck, Ulrich, Giddens, Anthony and Lash, Scott Reflexive Modernization:
Politics, Tradition and Aesthetics in the Modern Social Order, Cambridge,
Polity Press, 1994.
Bell, Daniel The End of Ideology, New York, Free Press, (1960) 1965.
Bendix, Reinhard Kings or People: Power and the Mandate to Rule, Berkeley,
CA, University of California Press, 1978.
Benhabib, Seyla Situating the Self: Gender, Community and Postmodernism in
Contemporary Ethics, Cambridge, Polity Press, 1992.
Benjamin, Walter Charles Baudelaire: Lyric Poet in the Era of High
Capitalism, London, New Left Books, 1973.
Bennett, Tony, Buckridge, Pat, Carter, David and Mercer, Colin, eds.
Bibliography 203
Celebrating the Nation: A Critical Study of Australia's Bicentenary, Sydney,
Allen and Unwin, 1992.
Berger, Peter Facing up to Modernity, Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1979.
Berman, Marshall All that is Solid Melts into Air: The Experience of
Modernity, London, Verso, 1983.
Bernstein, Basil Class, Codes and Control: Theoretical Studies Towards a Sociol
ogy of Language, New York, Schocken Books, 1971, revised edition 1974.
Bernstein, R ichard J. 'Structuration as Critical Theory', Praxis International,
6, 2, 1986, pp. 235-249.
Bernstein, Richard J. 'Social Theory as Critique' in David Held and John B.
Thompson, eds, Social Theory of Modern Societies: Anthony Giddens and
his Critics, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1989.
Bhabha, Homi, ed. Nation and Narration, London, Routledge, 1990.
Bhabha, Homi, 'Anxious Nations, Nervous States', in Joan Copjec, ed.,
Supposing the Subject, London, Verso, 1994.
Biddiss, Michael The Age of the Masses: Ideas and Society in Europe Since
1870, New York, Harper and Row, 1978.
Binkley, Robert C. Realism and Nationalism: 1852-1871, New York, Harper
and Row, (1935) 1963.
Birch, Anthony H. 'Minority Nationalist Movements and Theories of
Political Integration', World Politics, 30, 3, 1978, pp. 325-344.
Blaut, James, M. 'Nationalism as an Autonomous Force', Science and
Society, 46, 1, 1982, pp. 1-23.
Blaut, James, M. The National Question: Decolonizing the Theory of
Nationalism, London, Zed Books, 1987.
Bloch, Marc Feudal Society, vols I and 2, Chicago, University of Chicago
Press, (1940) translated 1961.
Bloom, Solomon F. The World of Nations: A Study of the National
Implications in the Work of Karl Marx, New York, Columbia University
Press, 1941.
Bluntschli, Johann Kaspar The Theory of the State, Oxford, Clarendon Press,
(1852) 1895.
Boersner, Demetrio The Bolsheviks and the National and Colonial Question,
Westport, CT, Hyperion, (1957), 1981.
Boorstin, Daniel J. The Americans, vol. 2: The National Experience,
Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1969.
Borst, Arno The Ordering of Time, Cambridge, Polity Press, 1993.
Bottomore, Tom 'Sociology', in David Mclellan, ed., Marx: The First
Hundred Years, Oxford, Fontana, 1983.
Bourdieu, Pierre The Logic of Practice, Cambridge, Polity Press, 1990.
Braudel, Fernand The Wheels of Commerce, vol. 2: Civilization and
Capitalism 15th-18th Century, London, Fontana, (1979) 1985.
Braudel, Fernand The Perspective of the World, vol. 3: Civilization and
Capitalism 15th-18th Century, London, Collins, 1984.
Braudel, Fernand The Identity of France, vol. 1: History and Environment,
London, Collins, 1988.
204 Nption Formation
Breuilly. John Nationalism and the State, Chicago, Chicago University Press,
1982; second edition 1994.
Breuilly, John 'Reflections on Nationalism', Philosophy ofthe Social Sciences,
15, 1985, pp. 65-75.
Bukharin, Nikolai Historic'°al Materialism, New York, International
Publishers, (1921) 1925.
Burke, Peter Sociology and History, London, George Allen and Unwin, 1980.
Buthman, William Curt The Rise of Integral Nationalism in France: With
Special Reference to the Ideas and Activities of Charles Maurras, New
York, Octagon, 1970.
Butler, Peter 'The Individual and International Relations' in James Mayall,
ed., The Community of States, London, George Allen and Unwin, 1982.
Bynack, V.P. 'Noah Webster's Linguistic Thought and the Idea of an
American National Culture', Journal of the History of Ideas, 45, I, 1984,
pp. 99-114.
Cahm, Eric and Fisera, Vladimir Claude Socialism and Nationalism, vol. l,
Nottingham, Spokesman, 1978.
Callinicos, Alex ls there a Future for Marxism?, London, Macmillan, 1982.
Callinicos, Alex 'Anthony Giddens: A Contemporary Critique', Theory and
Society, 14, 2, 1985, pp. 133-166.
Callinicos, Alex Making History: Agency, Structure and Change in Social
Theory, Cambridge, Polity Press, 1989.
Campbell, J.B. The Emperor and the Roman Army 3I BC-AD235, Oxford,
Clarendon Press, 1984.
Cannadine, David 'The Context, Performance and Meaning of Ritual: The
British Monarchy and the "Invention of Tradition", c.1820-1977', in Eric
Hobsbawm · and Terence Ranger, eds, The Invention of Tradition,
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1983.
Caraman, Philip University of the Nations: The Story of the Gregorian
University of Rome from I 551 to Vatican II, New York, Paulist Press,
1981.
Cardiff, David and Scannell, Paddy 'Broadcasting and National Unity', in
James Curran, Anthony Smith and Pauline Wingate, eds, Impacts and
Influences: Essays on Media Power in the Twentieth Century, London,
Methuen, 1987.
Castles, Stephen, Cope, Bill, Kalantzis, Mary and Morrissey, Michael
Mistaken Identity: Multiculturalism and the Demise of Nationalism in
Australia, Sydney, Pluto Press, 1988.
Castoriadis, Cornelius The Imaginary Institution of Society, Cambridge,
Polity Press, 1987.
Catto, J.l., ed. The History of the University of Oxford, Oxford, Clarendon
Press, 1984.
Chamberlin, E.R. Preserving the Past, London, J.M. Dent, 1979.
Chambers, Iain and Curti, Lidia 'A Volatile Alliance: Culture, Popular
Culture and the Italian Left', Formations: Of Nation and People, London,
Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1984.
Bibliography 205
Chatterjee, Partha Nationalist Thought and the Colonial World: A Derivative
Discourse, London, Zed Books, 1986.
Chatterjee, Partha The Nation and its Fragments: Colonial and Postcolonial
Histories, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press, 1993.
Chesneaux, Jean The Political and Social Ideas of Jules Verne, London,
Thames and Hudson, 1972.
Chesneaux, Jean 'Information Society as Civic Mutation', Arena, 81, 1987,
pp. 26-34.
Chickering, Roger We Men Who Feel Most German: A Cultural Study ofthe Pan
German League, 1886-1914, Boston, MA, George Allen and Unwin, 1984.
Clanchy, M.T. From Memory to Written Record: England 1066-1307,
London, Edward Arnold, 1979.
Clift, Dominique Quebec Nationalism in Crisis, Kingston and Montreal,
McGill-Queen's University Press, 1982.
Cohen, Ronald 'Warfare and State Formation: Wars Make States and States
Make Wars', in R . Brian Ferguson, ed., Warfare, Culture and Environment,
Orlando, FL, Academic Press, 1984.
Cobler, Anne M. Rousseau and Nationalism, New York, Basic Books, 1970.
Connor, Walker 'The Politics of Ethnonationalism', Journal of International
Affairs, 27, I, 1973, pp. 1-21.
Connor, Walker The National Question in Marxist-Leninist Theory and
Strategy, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press, 1984.
Connor, Walker Ethnonationalism: The Quest for Understanding, Princeton,
NJ, Princeton University Press, 1994.
Corrigan, Philip, ed. Capitalism, State Formation and Marxist Theory,
London, Quartet, 1980.
Corrigan, Philip, and Sayer, Derek The Great Arch: English State Formation
as Cultural Revolution, Oxford, Basil Blackwell, 1985.
Coser, Lewis 'Durkheim's Conservatism and its Implications for his
Sociological Theory', in Kurt Wolff, ed., Emile Durkheim et al.: Essays on
Sociology and Philosophy, New York, Harper and Row, 1964.
Cottle, Basil The Triumph of English 1350-1400, London, Blandford Press,
1969.
Coulton, G.G. 'Nationalism in the Middle Ages', Cambridge Historical
Journal, 5, 1935, pp. 15-40.
Coward, Rosalind and Ellis, John Language and Materialism: Developments
in Semiology and the Theory of the Subject, Boston, MA, Routledge and
Kegan Paul, 1977.
Craib, Ian Modern Social Theory: From Parsons to Habermas, Brighton,
Wheatsheaf, 1984.
Craib, Jan 'Back to Utopia: Anthony Giddens and Modern Social Theory',
Radical Philosophy, 43, 1986, pp. 17-21.
Crankshaw, Edward Bismarck, London, Macmillan, 1981.
Cregeen, Eric 'The Changing Role of the House of Argyll in the Scottish
Highlands', in N.T. Phillipson and Rosalind Mitchison, eds, Scotland in the
Age of Improvement, Edinburgh, Edinburgh University Press, 1970.
206 Nption Formation
Cummins, Ian Marx. Engels and National Movements, London, Croom
Helm, 1980.
Cummins, Ian 'Marx, Engels, and the Springtime of Peoples', in Roland
Sussex and J.C. Eade, eds, Culture and Nationalism in Nineteenth-Century
Eastern Europe, Columbus, Slavica, 1985.
Dale, Roger 'Nation State and International System: The World-System
Perspective', in Gregor McLennan, David Held and Stuart Hall, eds,
The Idea of the Modern State, Milton Keynes, Open University Press,
1984.
Dandeker, Christopher Surveillance, Power and Modernity, Cambridge, Polity
Press, 1994.
Darnton, Robert The Great Cat Massacre, Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1985.
Davis, Horace B. Nationalism and Socialism: Marxist and Labor Theories of
Nationalism to 1917, New York, Monthly Review Press, 1967.
Davis, Horace B. Toward a Marxist Theory of Nationalism, New York,
Monthly Review Press, 1978.
Debord, Guy Society of the Spectacle, Detroit, Black and Red, (1967) 1983.
Debray, Regis 'Marxism and the National Question', New Left Review, 105,
1977, pp. 25-41.
Debray, Regis Teachers, Writers, Celebrities: The Intellectuals of Modern
France, London, Verso, 1981.
Deleuze, Gilles and Guattari, Felix Nomadology: The War Machine, New
York, Semiotext(e), 1986.
Derrida, Jacques 'Declarations of Independence', New Political Science, 15,
1986, pp. 7-15.
Derrida, Jacques The Other Heading, Bloomington, IN, Indiana University
Press, 1992.
Dickens, A.G. The German Nation and Martin Luther, London, Edward
Arnold, 1974.
Dodgshon, Robert A. The European Past: Social Evolution and Spatial Order,
London, Macmillan, 1987.
Donelan, Michael 'A Community of Mankind', in James Mayall, ed., The
Community of States, London, George Allen and Unwin, 1982.
Douglas, Mary Natural Symbols: Explorations in Cosmology,
Harmondsworth, Penguin (1970) 1978.
Draper, Hall The Marx-Engels Chronicle, New York, Schocken, 1985.
Dunn, Michael 'Marxism and the National Question', Arena, 40, 1975, pp.
29-41.
DuPlessis, Robert S. 'The Partial Transition to World Systems Analysis in
Early Modern European History', Radical History Review, 39, 1987, pp.
11-27.
Dupre, Louis Marx's Social Critique of Culture, New Haven, CT, Yale
University Press, 1983.
Durkheim, Emile Professional Ethics and Civil Morals, London, Routledge
and Kegan Paul, (1890--1900) 1957.
Durkheim, Emile Montesquieu and Rousseau: Forerunners of Sociology,
Bibliography 207
Michigan, University of Michigan Press, (1892, published posthumously
1918) 1965.
Durkheim, Emile The Division of Labour in Society (with an introduction by
George Simpson), New York, Macmillan, (1893) translated 1933.
Durkheim, Emile The Rules of Sociological Method, New York, Free Press,
( 1895) 1966.
Durkheim, Emile Socialism and Saint-Simon, London, Routledge and Kegan
Paul, (1896, published posthumously 1928) 1959.
Durkheim, Emile Moral Education: A Study in the Theory and Application of
the Sociology of Education, New York, Free Press, (1902-3, published
posthumously 1925) 1973.
Durkheim, Emile The Evolution of Educational Thought: Lectures on the
Formation and Development of Secondary Education in France, London,
Routledge and Kegan Paul, (1904-5, published posthumously 1938) 1977.
Durkheim, Emile The Elementary Forms of Religious Life, London, George
Allen and Unwin (1912) 1976.
Durkheim, Emile 'Germany Above Al/': German Mentality and the War, Paris,
Armand Colin, 1915.
Durkheim, Emile and Dennis, E. Who Wanted War? The Origin of the War
according to Diplomatic Documents, Paris, Armand Colin, I915.
Dyson, Kenneth The State Tradition in Western Europe, Oxford, Martin
Robertson, 1980.
Eagleton, Terry Criticism and Ideology: A Study in Marxist Literary Theory,
London, Verso, 1978.
Eberhard, Wolfram Conquerors and Rulers: Social Forces in Medieval China,
Leiden, E.J. Brill, revised edition 1965.
Eccleston, Bernard 'The State and Modernisation in Japan', in James
Anderson, ed., The Rise of the Modern State, Sussex, Wheatsheaf, 1986.
Eco, Umberto Travels in Hyper-Reality, London, Pan, 1987.
Edwards, John Language, Society and Identity, Oxford, Basil Blackwell, 1985.
Ehrenreich, John H. 'The Theory of Nationalism: A Case of
Underdevelopment', Monthly Review, 27, I, 1975, pp. 57-61.
Ehrenreich, John H. 'Socialism, Nationalism and Capitalist Development',
Review of Radical Political Economics, 15, I, I983, pp. 1--42.
Eisenstein, Elizabeth The Printing Revolution in Early Modern Europe,
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1983.
Eley, Geoff'Nationalism and Social History', Social History, 6, I, 1981, pp.
83-107.
Eley, Geoff 'State Formation, Nationalism and Political Culture in
Nineteenth-Century Germany', in Raphael Samuel and Gareth Stedman
Jones, eds, Culture, Ideology and Politics, London, Routledge and Kegan
Paul, 1982.
Elias, Norbert The Civilizing Process, vol. 2: State Formation and Civilization,
London, Basil Blackwell, (I 939) translated I982.
Elias, Norbert Time: An Essay, Oxford, Blackwell, 1992.
Emerson, Rupert From Empire to Nation, Boston, MA, Beacon Press, 1960.
208 N,ation Formation
Engels, Friedrich The Origin of the Family, Pril'ate Property and the State,
Harmondsworth, Penguin, (1884) I 985.
d'Entreves, Alexander Passerin The Notion of the State: An Introduction to
Political Theory, London, Oxford University Press, 1969.
Ey erman, Ron, Svensson, Lennart G. and Sederqvist, Thomas, eds,
Intellectuals, Universities and the State in Western Modern Societies,
Berkeley, CA, University of California Press, 1987.
Febvre, Lucien A New Kind of History (edited by Peter Burke), London,
Routledge and Kegan Paul, translated ·1973.
Fernandez-Armesto, Felipe, ed. The Peoples of Europe, London, Times
Books, 1994.
Finer, Samuel 'State- and Nation-Building in Europe: The Role of the
Military', in Charles Tilly, ed., The Formation of National States in Western
Europe, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press, 1975.
Forgacs, David 'National-Popular: Genealogy of a Concept', in Formations
Editorial Collective, eds., Formations: Of Nation and People, London,
Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1984.
Foucault, Michel Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison,
Harmondsworth, Peregrine, (1975) 1982.
Frazer, Elizabeth and Lacey, Nicola, eds, The Politics of Community, London,
Harvester Wheatsheaf, 1993.
Freud, Sigmund 'Thoughts for the Times on War and Death' (1915), in
Collected Papers, vol. 4, London, Hogarth Press, 1934.
Freud, Sigmund Civilization and its Discontents, London, _Hogarth Press,
(1929) 1975.
Friedman, Jon_athan 'Culture, Identity, and World Process', Review, 12, 1,
1989, pp:51-69.
Friedrichs, Christopher R . Urban Society in an Age of War: Nordlinger.
1580-/720, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press, 1979.
Fussell, Paul The Great War and Modern Memory, Oxford, Oxford University
Press, 1977.
Gane, Mike 'Anthony Giddens and the Crisis of Social Theory', Economy and
Society, 12, 1983, pp. 368-398.
Garnsey, Peter and Saller, Richard The Roman Empire, London, Duckworth,
1987.
Geertz, Clifford The Interpretation of Cultures, (particularly ch. 9, 'After the
Revolution: The Fate of Nationalism in the New States' and ch. 10, 'The
Integrative Revolution: Primordial Sentiments and Civil Politics in the
New States'), New York, Basic Books, 1973.
Gellner, Ernest Thought and Change, London, Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1964.
Gellner, Ernest 'Scale and Nation', in his Contemporary Thought and Politics,
London, Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1974.
Gellner, Ernest Legitimation of Belief, London, Cambridge University Press, 1974.
Gellner, Ernest 'Nationalism, or the New Confessions of a Justified
Edinburgh Sinner', in his Spectacles and Predicaments: Essays in Social
Theory, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1979.
Bibliography 209
Gellner, Ernest 'Nationalism', Theory and Society, 10, 6, 1981, pp. 753-776.
Gellner, Ernest Nations and Nationalism, London, Basil Blackwell, 1983.
Gellner, Ernest The Psychoanalytic Movement: Or the Coming of Unreason,
London, Paladin, 1985.
Gellner, Ernest Culture, Identity and Politics, Cambridge, Cambridge
University Press, 1987.
Gellner, Ernest Postmodernism, Reason and Religion, London, Routledge,
1992.
Gellner, Ernest Encounters with Nationalism, Oxford, Blackwell, 1994.
Geras, Norman Marx and Human Nature: Refutation of a Legend, London,
Verso, 1983.
Geras, Norman 'Post-Marxism', New Left Review, 163, 1987, pp. 40-82.
Giddens, Anthony Central Problems in Social Theory: Action, Structure and
Contradiction in Social Analysis, London, Macmillan, 1979.
Giddens, Anthony Power, Property and State, vol. l: A Contemporary Critique
of Historical Materialism, London, Macmillan, 1981.
Giddens, Anthony Profiles and Critiques in Social Theory, London,
Macmillan, 1982.
Giddens, Anthony The Constitution of Society, Cambridge, Polity Press, 1984.
Giddens, Anthony The Nation-State and Violence, vol. 2: A Contemporary
Critique of Historical Materialism, Cambridge, Polity Press, 1985.
Giddens, Anthony 'Nation-States and Violence', in Social Theory and
Modern Sociology, Cambridge, Polity Press, 1987.
Giddens, Anthony Modernity and Self-Identity, Cambridge, Polity Press,
1991.
von Gierke, Otto Political Theories of the Middle Age, Cambridge, Cambridge
University Press, 1900.
Gildea, Robert Barricades and Borders: Europe 1800-1914, Oxford, Oxford
University Press, 1987.
Gill, Gerry 'Post-Structuralism as Ideology', Arena, 69, 1984, pp. 60-96.
Gluck, Carol Japan's Modern Myths: Ideology in the Late Meiji Period,
Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press, 1985.
Gomez-Quinones, Juan 'Critique on the National Question, Self
Determination and Nationalism', Latin American Perspectives, 9, 2, 1982,
pp. 62-83.
Goody, Jack The Domestication of the Savage Mind, Cambridge, Cambridge
University Press, 1977.
Goody, Jack The Logic of Writing and the Organization of Society,
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1986.
Goody, Jack The Interface Between the Written and the Oral, Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press, 1987.
Gosden, Christopher Social Being and Time, Oxford, Blackwell. 1994.
Gould, Carol Marx's Social Ontology: Individuality and Community in
Marx's Theory of Reality, Cambridge, MIT Press, 1972.
Gould, Peter and White, Rodney Mental Maps. Boston, MA, George Allen
and Unwin, second edition 1986.
2IO 'Nation Formation
Gouldner, Alvin W. The Future of Intellectuals and the Rise of the New Class:
A Frame of Reference, Theses. Conjectures, Arguments. and an Historical
Perspective on the Role of Intellectuals and Intelligentsia in the International
Class Contest of the ModerJJ Era, New York, Seabury, 1979.
Gourevitch, Peter Alexis 'The Re-emergence of "Peripheral Nationalisms":
Some Comparative Speculations on the Spatial Distribution of Political
Leadership and Economic Growth', Comparative Studies in Society and
History, 21, 1979, pp. 303-322.
Greenfield, Liah Nationalism: Five Roads to Modernity, Cambridge, MA,
Harvard University Press, 1992.
Gregory, Derek 'Presences and Absences: Time-Space Relations and
Structuration Theory', in David Held and John B. Thompson, eds, Social
Theory of Modern Societies: Anthony Giddens and his Critics, Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press, 1989.
Gregory, Derek and Urry, John, eds Social Relations and Spatial Structures,
London, Macmillan, 1985.
Grew, Raymond 'How Success Spoiled the Risorgimento' in Eugene C.
Black, ed., European Political History 1815-1870, New York, Harper and
Row, 1967.
Gross, David 'Space, Time, and Modern Culture', Telos, 50, 1981-82, pp.
59-78.
Gross, David 'Temporality and the Modern State', Theory and Society, 14, I,
1985, pp. 53-82.
Guattari, Felix Molecular Revolution, Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1984.
Guback, Thomas and Bettig, Ronald 'Translating the Manifesto into English;
Nineteenth_ Century Communication, Twentieth Century Confusion',
Journal of Communication Inquiry, 11, 2, 1987, pp. 3-16.
Guenee, Bernard States and Rulers in Later Medieval Europe, Oxford,
Blackwell (first published in French 1971), 1988.
Habermas, Jurgen Legitimation Crisis, London, Heinemann, 1976.
Habermas, Jurgen Communication and the Evolution of Society, Boston, MA,
Beacon, 1979.
Hall, John A. 'Ernest Gellner' in his Diagnoses of Our Time: Six Views on Our
Social Condition, London, Heinemann, 1981.
Hall, John A. Powers and Liberties: The Causes and Consequences of the Rise
of the West, Harmondsworth, Pelican, 1986.
Hall, John W. and Jansen, Marius B., eds Studies in the Institutional History
of Early Modern Japan, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press, 1968.
Hanagan, Michael P. The Logic ofSolidarity: Artisans and Industrial Workers in
Three French Towns, 1871-1914, Urbana, University of Illinois Press, 1980.
Handman, Max Sylvius 'The Sentiment of Nationalism', Political Science
Quarterly, 36, 1921, pp. 104-121.
Hayes, Carlton 'The War of Nations', Political Science Quarterly, 39, 4, 1914,
pp. 687-707.
Hayes, Carlton Essays on Nationalism, New York, Russell and Russell, (1926)
1966.
Bibliography 211
Hechter, Michael Internal Colonialism: The Celtic Fringe in British National
Development, 1536-1966, London, Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1975.
Heller, Agnes Renaissance Man, New York, Schocken Books, (1967, trans
lated 1978) 1981.
Henriques, Julian, Hollway, Wendy, Urwin, Cathy, Venn, Couze and
Walkerdine, Valerie Changing the Subject: Psychology, Social Regulation
and Subjectivity, London, Methuen, 1984.
Herod, Charles C. The Nation in the History of Marxian Thought: The
Concept of Nations with History and Nations without History, The Hague,
Martinus Nijhoff, 1976.
Hertz, Frederick Nationality in History and Politics, London, Kegan Paul,
1944.
Hinkson, John 'Post-Lyotard: A Critique of the Information Society', Arena,
80, 1987, pp. 123-155.
Hinkson, John 'Postmodern Economy: Value, Self-Formation and
Intellectual Practice', Arena Journal, new series I, 1993, pp. 23-44.
Hirst, Paul and Woolley, Penny Social Relations and Human Attributes,
London, Tavistock, 1982.
Hobbes, Thomas Le1•iathan, London, Dent, (1651) 1976.
Hobsbawm, Eric 'The Limits of Nationalism', New Society, 2 October 1969,
p. 523.
Hobsbawm, Eric 'Some Reflections on Nationalism' in T.J. Nossiter, A.H.
Hanson and Stein Rokkan, eds, Imagination and Precision in the Social
Sciences: Essays in Memory ofPeter Netti, London, Faber and Faber, 1972.
Hobsbawm, Eric 'Some Reflections on "The Break-up of Britain "' , New Left
Review, 105, 1977, pp. 3-23.
Hobsbawm, Eric 'Mass-Producing Traditions: Europe 1870-1914', (1983) in
Eric Hobsbawm and Terence Ranger, eds, The Invention of Tradition,
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1983.
Hobsbawm, Eric Nations and Nationalism since 1780: Programme, Myth and
Reality, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1990.
Hobsbawm, Eric and Ranger, Terence, eds The Invention of Tradition,
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1983.
Hobson, John A. 'Nationalism and Imperialism', the introductory section to
Imperialism: A Study, London, George Allen and Unwin, (1902) 1968.
Holmes, Dave 'Marxism and the National Question' in Jon West, Dave Holmes
and Gordon Adler, Socialism or Nationalism?, Sydney, Pathfinder, 1979.
Holtzman, Steven Digital Mantras: The Languages of Abstract and Virtual
Worlds, Cambridge, MIT Press, 1994.
Honore, Tony 'The Human Community and the Principle of Majority Rule',
in Eugene Kamenka, ed., Community as a Social Ideal, London, Edward
Arnold, 1982.
Hooson, David Geography and National Identity, Oxford, Blackwell, 1994.
Horne, Donald The Public Culture, London, Pluto, 1986.
Howard, Michael 'War and the Nation-State', Daedalus, Fall 1979, pp.
101-110.
212 Nation Formation
Hroch, Miroslav 'From National Movement to Fully Formed Nation', New
Left Review, 198, March 1993, pp. 3-20.
Hubatsch, Walter Studies in Medieval and Modern German History, London,
Macmillan, 1985. •
Hudson, Wayne and Carter, David, eds, The Republicanism Debate, Sydney,
NSW University Press, 1993.
Huizinga, Johan Men and Ideas: History, the Middle Ages, the Renaissance
(particularly the essay 'Patriotism and Nationalism in European History'),
New York, Meridian, 1959.
Hutchinson, John Modern Nationalisms, London, Fontana, 1994.
IgnatiefT, Michael Blood and Belonging, London, Vintage, 1994.
Irele, Abiola 'Negritude or Black Cultural Nationalism', Journal of Modern
African Studies, 3, 3, 1965, pp. 321-347.
lsaacs, Harold R. 'Nationality: "End of the Road? "' , Foreign Affairs, 53, 3,
1975, pp. 432-449.
Jacobs, Jane Cities and the Wealth of Nations, Harmondsworth, Penguin,
1986.
Jacoby, Russell Social Amnesia, Boston, MA, Beacon Press, 1975.
Jameson, Fredric 'Postmodernism, or the Cultural Logic ofLate Capitalism',
New Left Review, 146, July 1984, pp. 53-92.
Jenkins, Brian and Minnerup, Gunter Citizens and Comrades, London, Pluto,
1984.
Johnson, Richard J. 'Histories of Culture/Theories ofldeology: Notes on an
Impasse', in Michelle Barratt, Philip Corrigan, Annette Kuhn, and Janet
Wolff, eds, Ideology and Cultural Production, London, Croom Helm,
1979.
Johnston, R.J. Geography and the State: An Essay in Political Geography,
London, Macmillan, 1982.
Kamenka, Eugene 'Political Nationalism -The Evolution of the Idea' in E.
Kamenka, ed., Nationalism: The Nature and Evolution of an Idea,
Canberra, Australian National University Press, 1973.
Kamenka, Eugene, ed. Community as a Social Ideal, London, Edward
Arnold, 1982.
Kantorowicz, Ernst 'Pro Patria Mori in Medieval Thought', American
Historical Review, 56, 3, 1951, pp. 472-492.
Kantorowicz, Ernst The King's Two Bodies, Princeton, NJ, Princeton
University Press, 1957.
Kautsky, John H., ed. Political Change in Underdeveloped Countries:
Nationalism and Communism, New York, John Wiley, 1967.
Kavan, Zdenek 'Human Rights and International Community', in James
Mayall, ed., The Community of States, London, George Allen and Unwin,
1982.
Kedourie, Elie Nationalism, London, Hutchinson, (1960) 1993.
Keith, Michael, and Pile, Steve, eds, Place and the Politics of Identity,
London, Routledge, 1993.
Kelly, George Armstrong 'Mortal Man, Immortal Society? Political Metaphors
Bibliography 213
in Eighteenth-Century France', Political Theory, 14, I, 1986, pp. 5-29.
Kem, Stephen The Culture of Time and Space, 1880-1918, Cambridge, MA,
Harvard University Press, 1983.
Kiernan, V.G. 'State and Nation in Western Europe', Past and Present, 31,
1965, pp. 20-38.
Kitching, Gavin 'Nationalism: The Instrumental Passion', Capital and Class,
25, 1985, pp. 98-116.
Koestler, Arthur The Act of Creation, London, Pan, (1964) 1977.
Kohn, Hans The Idea of Nationalism: A Study in its Origins and Background,
New York, Macmillan, (1944) 1956.
Kohn, Hans Nationalism: Its Meaning and History, New York, Van Nostrand
Reinhold, revised edition 1965.
Kohn, Hans Prelude to Nation-States: The French and German Experience,
1789-1815, Princeton, NJ, Van Nostrand, 1967.
Koht, Halvdan 'The Dawn of Nationalism in Europe', The American
Historical Review, 52, 2, 1947, pp. 265-280.
Kornhauser, William The Politics of Mass Society, London, Routledge and
Kegan Paul, (1959) 1965.
Krieger, Leonard 'Germany', in Orest Ranum, ed., National Consciousness,
History and Political Culture in Early-Mod ern Europe, Baltimore, MD,
Johns Hopkins University Press, 1975.
Kristeva, Julia Nations without Nationalism, New York, Columbia University
Press, 1993.
Kulichenko, M. Nations and Social Progress, Moscow, Progress Publishers,
1984.
Kurauchi, Kazuta 'Durkheim's Influence on Japanese Sociology', in Kurt
Wolff, ed., Emile Durkheim et al., Essays on Sociology and Philosophy,
New York, Harper and Row, 1964.
Landau, Terry About Faces, New York, Doubleday, 1989.
Landes, David Revolution in Time, Cambridge, MA, Belknap/Harvard
University Press, 1983.
Lasch, Christopher The Minimal Self: Psychic Survival in Troubled Times,
London, Picador, 1985.
Latimer, Dan 'Jameson and Post-Modernism', New Left Review, 148,
November 1984, pp. I 16-128.
Lawson, John and Silver, Harold A Social History of Education in England,
London, Methuen, 1973.
Le Bon, Gustave The Psychology of the Great War, London, Fisher Unwin,
English translation 1916.
Leed, Eric "'Voice" and "Print": Master Symbols in the History of
Communication', in Kathleen Woodward, ed., The Myths of Information:
Technology and Postindustrial Culture, Madison, WI, Coda Press, 1980.
Lenin, V.l. Imperialism. the Highest Stage of Capitalism, Moscow, Progress
Publishers, (1917) 1978.
Lerner, Daniel The Passing of Traditional Society, New York, Free Press,
1958.
214 Nqtion Formation
Levi-Strauss, Claude The Sai•age Mind, London, Weidenfeld and Nicolson,
(1962) translated 1966.
Lewis, I.M., ed. Nationalism and Self-Determination in the Horn of Africa,
London, Ithaca Press, 1983.
Little, Graham Political Ensem6les, Melbourne, Oxford University Press, 1985.
Lockwood, David 'Social Integration and System Integration', in G.K.
Zollschan and W. Hirsch, eds, Explorations in Social Change, London,
Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1964.
Lohrey, Andrew 'Australian Nationalism as Myth', Arena, 68, 1984, pp.
107-123.
Longford, Elizabeth Victoria R. I., London, Pan, 1966.
Lorrain, Jorge The Concept of Ideology, London, Hutchinson, 1979.
Lovejoy, Arthur 0. The Great Chain of Being, Cambridge, MA, Harvard
University Press, (1936) 1964.
Lowy, Michael 'Marxists and the National Question', New Left Review, 96,
1976, pp. 81-100.
Lunde, Erik S. 'The Ambiguity of the National Idea: The Presidential
Campaign of 1872', Canadian Review of Studies in Nationalism, 5, I, 1978,
pp. 1-23.
Lukacs, Georg History and Class Consciousness: Studies in Marxist
Dialectics, Cambridge, MIT Press, (1922, new edition, 1967) 1976.
Lynn, Richard 'The Sociobiology of Nationalism', New Society, I July 1976,
pp. 11-14.
Lyotard, Jean-Frani;ois The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge,
Manchester, Manchester University Press, 1984.
MacDougall, Hugh Racial Myth in English History: Trojans, Teutons and
Anglo-Saxons, Montreal and Hanover, Harvest House and University
Press of New England, 1982.
MacLaughlin, Jim 'Industrial Capitalism, Ulster Unionism and Orangeism:
An Historical Reappraisal', Antipode: A Radical Journal of Geography,
12, I, 1980, pp. 15-28.
MacLaughlin, Jim 'The Political Geography of "Nation-Building" and
Nationalism in Social Sciences: Structural vs. Dialectical Accounts',
Political Geography Quarterly, 5, 4, 1986, pp. 299-329.
MacLaughlin, Jim 'State-Centred Social Science and the Anarchist Critique:
Ideology in Political Geography', Antipode, 18, 1, 1986, pp. 11-38.
MacLaughlin, Jim 'Nationalism as an Autonomous Social Force: A Critique
of Recent Scholarship on Ethnonationalism', Canadian Review of Studies
in Nationalism, 14, 1, 1987, pp.1-18.
MacLaughlin, Jim 'Reflections on Nations as "Imagined Communities "' ,
Journal of Multilingual and Multicultural Development, 9, 5, 1988, pp.
449-457.
McLellan, David Karl Marx: Early Texts, Oxford, Basil Blackwell, 1972.
McLennan, Gregor 'Critical or Positive Theory? A Comment on the Status of
Anthony Giddens' Social Theory', Theory, Culture and Society, 2, 2, 1984,
pp. 123-129.
Bibliography 215
McLuhan, Marshall Understanding Media: The Extensions of Man, London,
Abacus, 1973.
McNeil, William The Pursuit of Power: Technology, Armed Force and Society
since A.D. 1000, Oxford, Basil Blackwell, 1983.
Mann, Michael The Sources of Social Power, vols I and 2, Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press, 1986, 1993.
Mann, Michael States, War and Capitalism: Studies in Political Sociology,
Oxford, Basil Blackwell, 1988.
Marx, Karl On Colonialism, Moscow, Progress Publishers, (1850-1888) 1976.
Marx, Karl Capital, vol. I, Moscow, Progress Publishers, (1867) 1977.
Marx, Karl and Engels, Frederick Collected Works, London, Lawrence and
Wishart, 1976---1985.
Marx, Karl and Engels, Frederick Selected Works, vols 1-3, Moscow,
Progress, 1977.
Mauss, Marcel The Gift: Forms and Functions of Exchange in Archaic
Societies, London, Routledge and Kegan Paul, (1925) 1974.
Mayall, James, ed. The Community of States, London, George Allen and
Unwin, 1982.
Mayer, Arno J. The Persistence of the Old Regime: Europe to the Great War,
London, Croom Helm, 1981.
Mazzini, Giuseppe The Duties of Man and Other Essays, London, Dent,
(1844-70) 1924.
Meinecke, Friedrich Cosmopolitanism and the Nation State, Princeton, NJ,
Princeton University Press, (1907) 1970.
Mercer, Colin 'Regular Imaginings: T he Newspaper and the Nation' in Tony
Bennett, Pat Buckridge, David Carter and Colin Mercer, eds, Celebrating
the Nation, Sydney, Allen and Unwin, 1992.
Merquior, J.G. Rousseau and Weber: Two Studies in the Theory of Legitimacy,
London, Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1980.
Meznaric, Silva 'A Neo-Marxist Approach to the Sociology of Nationalism,
Doomed Nations and Doomed Schemes', Praxis International, 7, I, 1987,
pp. 79-89.
Michels, Robert 'Patriotism', in First Lectures in Political Sociology, New
York, Harper and Row, (1927) 1965.
Minogue, K.R. Nationalism, London, Batsford, I967.
Mitchell, M. Marion 'Emile Durkheim and the Philosophy of Nationalism',
Political Science Quarterly, 46, I, 193 I, pp. 87-106.
Mitzman, Arthur The Iron Cage, New York, Grosset and Dunlop, 1969.
de Montmorency, J.E.G. State Intervention in English Education, Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press, 1902.
Moore, G.E. 'A Defense of Common Sense', Contemporary British
Philosophy, 2, 1925, pp. 193-223.
Morgan, Edmund S. Inventing the People: The Rise of Popular Sm•ereignty in
England and America, New York, W.W. Norton, 1988.
Morgan, Glenn 'From West to East and Back Again: Capitalist Expansion
and Class Formation in the Nineteenth Century', in Howard Newby, Janet
216 Nqtion Formation
Buyra, Paul Littlewood, Gareth Rees and Teresa L. Rees, eds,
Restructuring Capital: Recession and Reorgani;ation in Industrial Society,
Houndmills, Macmillan, 1985.
Morgenthau, Hans J. Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and
Peace, New York, (1948) fifth edition 1976.
Morris, Richard B. Basic Documents in American History, New York, Van
Nostrand, 1965.
Mosca, Gaetano The Ruling Class/Elementi di Scienza Politica, New York,
McGraw Hill, (1896, 1923 edition) 1965, p. 482.
Moses, John A. The Politics of lllusion: The Fischer Controversy in German
Historiography, London, George Prior, 1975.
Muir, Ramsay Nationalism and Internationalism: The Culmination of Modern
History, London, Constable, 1916.
Mulhern, Francis 'Towards 2000, or News from You-Know-Where', New
Left Review, 148, 1984, pp. 5-30.
Mullett, Michael Popular Culture and Popular Protest in Late Medie1•al and
Early Modern Europe, London, Croom Helm, 1987.
Munck, Ronaldo 'Otto Bauer: Towards a Marxist Theory of Nationalism',
Capital and Class, 25, Spring 1985, pp. 84-97.
Munck, RonaldoThe Difficult Dialogue: Marxism and Nationalism, London,
Zed Books, 1986.
Musil, Robert The Confessions of Young Torless, London, Picador (1906)
1955.
Musil, Robert The Man Without Qualities, vol. 1, London, Picador (1930),
1983.
Myers, Fred Pintupi Country, Pintupi Self: Sentiment, Place, and Politics
among Western Desert Aborigines, Washington and Canberra,
Smithsonian Institute Press and Australian Institute of Aboriginal Studies,
1986.
Nairn, Tom 'The Three Dreams of Scottish Nationalism', New Left Review,
49, 1968, pp. 3-18.
Nairn, Tom 'British Nationalism and the EEC', New Left Review, 69, 1971,
pp. 3-28.
Nairn, Tom 'The Left Against Europe?', New Left Review, 75, 1972, pp. 5-20
(later published as The Left Against Europe?), Harmondsworth, Penguin,
1973).
Nairn, Tom The Break-up of Britain: Crisis and Neo-Nationalism, London,
Verso, 1977, second edition 1981.
Nairn, Tom The Enchanted Glass: Britain and its Monarchy, London, Radius,
1988.
Navari, Cornelia 'The Origins of the Nation-State', in Leonard Tivey, ed.,
The Nation-State, Oxford, Martin Robertson, 1981.
Nietzsche, Friedrich Thus Spake Zarathustra (1891-92), and other writings
(1865-1889) in Walter Kaufmann, ed., The Portable Nietzsche,
Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1985.
Nimni, Ephraim 'Great Historical Failure: Marxist Theories of Nationalism',
Bibliography 217
Capital and Class, 25, 1985, pp. 58-83. A longer version appears in Martin
Shaw, ed., Marxist Sociology Revisited: Critical Assessments, London,
Macmillan, 1985.
Nimni, Ephraim 'Marx, Engels and the National Question', Science and
Society, 53, 3, 1989, pp. 297-326.
Nimni, Ephraim Marxism and Nationalism, London, Pluto, 1991.
Nisbet, Robert A. The Quest/or Community, London, Oxford, (1953) 1971.
Nisbet, Robert A. The Sociological Tradition, London, Heinemann, (1966) 1970.
Oakesmith, John Race and Nationality, London, Heinemann, 1919.
Ooms, Herman 'Nee-Confucianism and the Formation of Early Tokugawa
Ideology', in Peter Nasca, ed., Confucianism and Tokugawa Culture,
Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press, 1984.
Orridge, A.W. 'Uneven Development and Nationalism: I', Political Studies,
29, I, 1982, pp. 1-15.
Orridge, A.W. 'Uneven Development and Nationalism: 2', Political Studies,
29, 2, 1982, pp. 181-190.
Ouston, Philip The Imagination of Barres, Toronto, University of Toronto
Press, 1974.
Packard, Vance A Nation of Strangers, New York, David McKay, 1972.
Parker, William N. Europe, America, and the Wider World: Essays on the
Economic History of Western Capitalism, vol. I: Europe and the World
Economy, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1984.
Parsons, Talcott The Social System, London, Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1951.
Petrus, Joseph 'Marx and Engels on the National Question', Journal of
Politics, 33, 1971, pp. 797-824.
Peyre, Henri 'Durkheim: The Man, His Time, and His Intellectual
Background', in Kurt Wolff, ed., Emile Durkheim et al., Essays on
Sociology and Philosophy, New York, Harper and Row, 1964.
Plamenatz, John 'Two Types of Nationalism', in Eugene Kamenka, ed.,
Nationalism: The Nature and Evolution of an Idea, Canberra, Australian
National University Press, 1973.
Pleydell, Alan 'Language, Culture and the Concept of International Political
Community', in James Mayall, ed., The Community of States, London,
George Allen and Unwin, 1982.
Poggi, Gianfranco The Development of the Modern State, London,
Hutchinson, 1978.
Polanyi, Karl The Great Transformation: The Political and Economic Origins
of Our Time, Boston, MA, Beacon Press, (1944) 1957.
Portis, Edward B. Max Weber and Political Commitment: Science. Politics and
Personality, Philadelphia, Temple University Press, 1986.
Poster, Mark Foucault, Marxism and History: Mode of Production versus
Mode of Information, Cambridge, Polity Press, 1984.
Poster, Mark The Mode of Information: Poststructuralism and Social Context,
Cambridge, Polity Press, 1990.
Poulantzas, Nicos Political Power and Social Classes, London, New Left
Books, (1968) 1973.
218 Napon Formation
Poulantzas, Nicos State, Power, Socialism, London, Verso, (1978) 1980.
Pye, Lucien W. Politics, Personality, and Nation Building: Burma's Search/or
Identity, New Haven, CT, Yale University Press, 1962.
Rawkins, Phillip 'Nationalist Movements Within the Advanced Industrial
State: The Significance of Culture', Canadian Review of Studies in
Nationalism, 10, 2, 1983, pp. 221-233.
Rawkins, Phillip 'Minority Nationalism and its Limits: A Weberian
Perspective on Cultural Change', Canadian Review of Studies in
Nationalism, 11, 1, 1984, pp. 87-101.
Rawls, John A Theory of Justice, London, Oxford University Press, 1972.
Renan, Ernest 'What is a Nation?', (1882), reproduced in part in Hans Kohn,
Nationalism: Its Meaning and History, New York, Van Nostrand
Reinhold, 1965.
Reynolds, Susan 'Medieval Origines Gentium and the Community of the
Realm', History, 68, 1983, pp. 375-390.
Ringrose, David R . 'Comment on Papers by Reed, de Vries, and Bean',
Journal of Economic History, 33, 1, 1973, pp. 222-227.
R ipalda, Jose Maria The Divided Nation: The Roots of a Bourgeois Thinker:
G W.F. Hegel, Amsterdam, Van Gorcum, Assen, 1977.
Roberts, Stephen History of Modern Europe, Sydney, Angus and Robertson,
1950.
Robertson, Roland and Lechner, Frank 'Modernization, Globalization, and
the Problem of Culture in World-Systems Theory', Theory, Culture and
Society, 2, 3, 1985, pp. 103-117.
Rodinson, Maxime 'Le Marxisme et la Nation', L'Homme et la Societe, 7,
1968, pp. 131-149.
Roehl, Richard 'Comment on Papers by Reed and Bean', Journal of Economic
History, 33, I, I 973, pp. 228-231.
Rosdolsky, Roman 'Worker and Fatherland: A Note on a Passage in the
Communist Manifesto', Science and Society, 29, 1965, pp. 330-337.
Rosdolsky, Roman Engels and the 'Nonhistoric' Peoples: The National
Question in the Revolution of1848, (1964) translated by John-Paul Himka,
in Critique, 18-19, 1987.
Rose, J. Holland Nationality as a Factor in Modern History, London,
Rivingtons, 1916.
Rosenau, James N. The Study of Political Adaptation: Essays on the Analysis
of World Politics, London and New York, Frances Pinter and Nichols,
1981.
Rostow, Walt W. Stages of Economic Growth: A Non-Communist Manifesto,
Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1960.
Rude, George The Crowd in History: A Study of Popular Disturbances in
France and England, 1730-/848, New York, John Wiley, 1964.
Rudolph, Joseph R. 'Ethnic Sub-States and the Emergent Politics of Tri-Level
Interaction in Western Europe', Western Political Quarterly, 30, 4, 1977,
pp. 536-557.
Rudolph, Joseph R . 'Ethnoregionalism in Contemporary Western Europe:
Bibliography 219
The Potential for Political Accommodation', Canadian Review of Studies in
Nationalism, 8, 2, 1981, pp. 323-341.
Sack, Robert David Conceptions of Space in Social Thought, London,
Macmillan, 1980.
Sathyamurthy, T.V. Nationalism in the Contemporary World, London, Frances
Pinter, 1983.
Sayer, Derek The Violence of Abstraction: The Analytic Foundations of
Historical Materialism, Oxford, Basil Blackwell, I 987.
Scaff, Lawrence 'Fleeing the Iron Cage: Politics and Culture in the Thought of
Max Weber', American Political Science Review, 81, 3, 1987, pp. 737-755.
Schivelbusch, Wolfgang 'Railroad Space and Railroad Time', New German
Critique, 14, 1978, pp. 31-40.
Schorer, Mark The Structure of the Novel: Method, Metaphor and Mind', in
Barbara Hardy, ed., Middlemarch: Critical Approaches to the Novel,
London, Athlone, I 967.
Scott, Jonathan F. 'Inculcation of Nationalism in French Schools after 1870',
in Louis Snyder, ed., The Dynamics of Nationalism, Princeton, NJ, Van
Nostrand, 1964.
Seigel, Jerrold Marx's Fate: The Shape of a Life, Princeton, NJ, Princeton
University Press, 1978.
Sennett, Richard The Fall of Public Man, Cambridge, Cambridge University
Press, 1977.
Seton-Watson, Hugh Nations and States: An Enquiry into the Origins of
Nations and the Politics of Nationalism, London, Methuen, 1977.
Shafer, Boyd C. Nationalism: Myth and Reality, London, Victor Gollancz,
1955.
Shafer, Boyd C. 'If Only We Knew More about Nationalism', Canadian
Review of Studies in Nationalism, 7, 2, I 980, pp. I 97-218.
Shafer, Boyd C. 'Review of Gellner's Nations and Nationalism', Canadian
Review of Studies in Nationalism, 11, 1, 1984, pp. 141-142.
Shaheen, Samad The Communist ( Bolshevik) Theory of National Self-
Determination, The Hague, W van Hoeve, 1956.
Sharp, GeofT'A Revolutionary Culture', Arena, 16, 1968, pp. 2-11.
Sharp, GeofT'Hollowed Out from Within', Arena, 63, 1983, pp. 1-2.
Sharp, GeofT'Intellectuals in Transition', Arena, 65, 1983, pp. 84-95.
Sharp, GeofT'Constitutive Abstraction and Social Practice', Arena, 70, 1985,
pp. 48-82.
Sharp, Geoff 'Extended Forms of the Social', Arena Journal, new series 1,
1993, pp. 221-237.
Sharp, Geoff and White, Doug 'Features of the Intellectually Trained', Arena,
15, 1968, pp. 30--33.
Sharp, Nonie 'Nationalism and Cultural Politics', Arena, 43, 1976, pp. 58-77.
Sheffer, Gabriel, ed. Modern Diasporas in International Politics, London,
Croom Helm, 1986.
Shennan, J.H. The Origins of the Modern European State, 1450-1725,
London, Hutchinson, 1974.
220 Nation Formation
Shits, Edward 'Primordial, Personal, Sacred and Civil Ties', British Journal of
Sociology, 8, 1957, pp. 130-145.
Shouldice, Larry, ed. Contemporary Quebec Criticism, Toronto, University of
Toronto Press, 1979.
Simkhovitch, Vladimir G. 'Approaches to History: 3', Political Science
Quarterly, 47, 3, 1932, pp. 410---439.
Simmel, Georg Conflict and the Web of Group-Affiliations, translated by Kurt
H. Wolff and Reinhard Bendix, London, Free Press, (1908) 1955.
Simmel, Georg The Sociol ogy of Georg Simmel, translated, edited and with an
introduction by Kurt H. Wolff, London, Free Press, 1950.
Skocpol, Theda States and Social Revolutions: A Comparative Analysis of
France, Russia and China, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, (1979)
1984.
Smith, Alan G.R. The Emergence of a Nation-State: The Commonwealth of
England 1529-1660, Essex, Longman, 1984.
Smith, Anthony D. 'Ethnocentrism, Nationalism and Social Change',
International Journal of Comparative Sociology , 13, 1972, pp. 1-20.
Smith, Anthony D. "'Ideas" and "Structure" in the Formation of
Independence Ideals', Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 3, 1973, pp. 19-39.
Smith, Anthony D. The Ethnic Revival, Cambridge, Cambridge University
Press, 1981.
Smith, Anthony D. Theories of Nationalism, London, Duckworth, (1971)
second edition 1983.
Smith, Anthony D. 'Nationalism and Classical Social Theory', The British
Journal of Sociology, 34, 1, 1983, pp. 19-38.
Smith, Anthony D. The Ethnic Origins of Nations, London, Basil Blackwell,
1986.
Smith, Anthony D. 'History and Liberty: Dilemmas of Loyalty in Western
Democracies', Ethnic and Racial Studies, 9, I, 1986, pp. 43-65.
Smith, Anthony D. National Identity, London, Penguin, 1991.
Snyder, Louis L. German Nationalism: The Tragedy of a People, New York,
Kennikat Press, (1952) 1969.
Sohn-Rethel, Alfred Intellectual and Manual Labour: A Critique of
Epistemology, London, Macmillan, 1978.
Solovyof, Vladimir 'The National Question from a Moral Point of View',
chapter 5 in his The Justification of the Good: An Essay on Moral
Philosophy, London, Constable, (1897) 1918.
Stalin, Joseph Marxism and the National and Colonial Question: A Collection
ofArticles and Speeches, London, Lawrence and Wishart, (1913-34) 1947.
Stokes, Gale 'The Underdeveloped Theory of Nationalism', World Politics,
31, 1978, pp. 150-160.
Stokes, Gale 'How is Nationalism Related to Capitalism?', Comparative
Studies in Society and History, 28, 1986, pp. 591-598.
Strayer, Joseph R. 'The Tokugawa Period and Japanese Feudalism' in John
W Hall and Marius B. Jansen, eds, Studies in the Institutional History of
Early Modern Japan, Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press, 1968.
Bibliography 221
Symmons-Symonolewicz, Konstantin Modern Nationalism: Towards a
Consensus in Theory, New York, Polish Institute of Arts and Sciences in
America, 1968.
Symmons-Symonolewicz, Konstantin 'National Consciousness in Medieval
Europe: Some Theoretical Problems', Canadian Review of Studies in
Nationalism, 8, I, 1981, pp. 151-166.
Tabori, Paul The Anatomy of Exile: A Semantic and Historical Study,
London, Harrap, 1972.
Talmon, J.L. The Myth ofthe Nation and the Vision of Revolution: The Origins
of Ideological Polarisation in the Twentieth Century, London, Secker and
Warburg, 198 I.
Thom, Martin 'Tribes within Nations: The Ancient Germans and the History
of Modern France', in Homi Bhabha, ed., Nation and Narration, London,
Routledge, 1990.
Thompson, David Europe Since Napoleon, Harmondsworth, Penguin, (1957)
1971.
Thompson, John B. 'Ideology and the Social Imaginary', Theory and Society,
11, 5, 1982, pp. 659-68 l .
Thompson, John B. 'The Theory of Structuration: An Assessment of the
Contribution of Anthony Giddens' in Studies in the Theory of Ideology,
Cambridge, Polity Press, 1984.
Thompson, Kenneth Emile Durkheim, London, Ellis Horwood and
Tavistock, 1982.
Thompson, William Irwin From Nation to Emanation: Planetary Culture and
World Governance, Findhorn Scotland, Findhorn Publications, 1982.
Tiedemann, Arthur Modern Japan, Princeton, NJ, Van Nostrand, 1955.
Tilly, Charles, ed. The Formation of National States in Western Europe,
Princeton, NJ, Princeton University Press, 1975.
Tipton, C. Leon, ed. Nationalism in the Middle Ages, New York, Holt,
Rinehart and Winston, New York, 1972.
Tiryakian, Edward 'Emile Durkheim', in Tom Bottomore and Robert Nisbet,
eds, A History of Sociological Analysis, London, Heinemann, 1970.
Tiryakian, Edward and Nevitte, Neil 'Nationalism and Modernity', in
Edward Tiryakian and Ronald Rogowski, eds, New Nationalisms of the
Developed West, Boston, MA, Allen and Unwin, 1985.
Tiryakian, Edward and Rogowski, Ronald, eds New Nationalisms of the
Developed West: Toward Explanation, Boston, MA, Allen and Unwin,
1985.
Toffier, Alvin The Third Wave, London, Pan, 1981.
Tonnies, Ferdinand Community and Society, New York, Harper and Row,
(1887) 1963.
Trevor-Roper, Hugh 'The Invention of Tradition: The Highland Tradition of
Scotland', in Eric Hobsbawm and Terence Ranger, eds, The Invention of
Tradition, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1983.
Tudjman, Franjo Nationalism in Contemporary Europe, Boulder, CO, East
European Monographs, 1981.
222 Na/ion Formation
Tully, R.E. 'Moore's Defense of Common Sense: a Reappraisal After Fifty
Years', Philosophy, 51, 1976, pp. 289-306.
Tunstall, Jeremy The Media are American: Anglo-American Media in the
World, London, Constable, 1977.
Turner, Bryan S. 'Personhood a°;id Citizenship', Theory, Culture and Society,
3, 1, 1986, pp. 1-16.
Turner, Bryan S. Orienta/ism, Postmodernism and Globalism, London,
Routledge, 1994.
Turner, Stephen and Factor, Regis Max 1#:ber and the Dispute over Reason
and Value: A Study in Philosophy, Ethics, and Politics, London, Routledge
and Kegan Paul, 1984.
Urry, John and Gregory, Derek, eds Social Relations and Spatial Structures,
London, Macmillan, 1985.
van Abbe, Derek Image of a People: Modern German Writing in its Social
Context, London, Harrap, 1964.
Verne, Jules A Tour of the World in Eighty Days, New York, Burt, (1873) n.d.
Vilar, Pierre 'On Nations and Nationalism', Marxist Perspectives, 5, 1979, pp.
8-29.
Vincent, Andrew Theories of the State, Oxford, Basil Blackwell, 1987.
Virilio, Paul Speed and Politics, New York, Semiotext(e), 1986.
Walker, Mack Germany and the Emigration, /816-1885, Cambridge, MA,
Harvard University Press, 1964.
Walker, Mack German Home Towns: Community, State and General Estate,
1648-1871, Ithaca, NY, Cornell University Press, 1971.
Wallerstein, Immanuel The Modern World System: Capitalist Agriculture and
the Origins of the European World-Economy in the Sixteenth Century, New
York, Academic Press, 1976.
Walsh, M. Christine, ed. P rologue: A Documentary History of Europe,
1848-/960, Australia, Cassell, 1968.
Watanuki, Joji 'Nation-Building at the Edge of an Old Empire: Japan and
Korea', in S.N. Eisenstadt and Stein Rokkan, eds, Building States and
Nations, vol. 2: Analyses by Region, Beverly Hills, CA, Sage, 1973.
Webb, Keith The Growth of Nationalism in Scotland, Harmondsworth,
Penguin, 1978.
Weber, Eugen The Nationalist Revival in France, /905-1914, Berkeley, CA,
University of California Press, 1968.
Weber, Eugen Peasants into Frenchmen: The Modernization of Rural France,
1870-1914, Stanford, CA, Stanford University Press, 1976.
Weber, Max Inaugural Lecture, Freiburg, May 1895, 'The National State
and Economic Policy', Economy and Society, 9, 4, 1980, pp. 428-449.
Weber, Max Weber: Selections in Translation (edited by W.G. Runciman,
translated by Eric Matthews), Cambridge, Cambridge University Press,
(1895-1920) 1978.
Weber, Max The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism (translated by
Talcott Parsons), New York, Charles Scribner's Sons, (l 904-5 translated
1930) 1958.
Bibliography 223
Weber, Max From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology (essays from 1904--20
translated, edited and with an introduction by H.H. Gerth and C. Wright
Mills), New York, Oxford University Press, 1968.
Weber, Max The Theory of Social and Economic Organization (edited with
an introduction by Talcott Parsons), New York, Free Press (Part I of
Wirtschaft und Gesel/schaft, 1910-20, posthumously published 1921)
1945.
Weissbort, Daniel, ed. Post-War Russian Poetry, Harmondsworth, Penguin,
1974.
Wessell, Leonard P. Karl Marx, Romantic Irony and the Proletariat: The
Mythopoetic Origins of Marxism, Baton Rouge, Louisiana State
University Press, 1979.
White, Philip L. 'What is a Nationality', Canadian Re1•iew of Studies in
Nationalism, 12, I, 1985, pp. 1-23.
White, Richard Inventing Australia: Images and Identity /688-1980, Sydney,
George Allen and Unwin, 1981.
Wickham, Chris 'Historical Materialism, Historical Sociology', New Left
Review, 171, 1988, pp. 63-78.
Williams, Colin 'Ethnic Resurgence in the Periphery', Area, 11, 4, 1979, pp.
279-283.
Williams, E.N. The Ancien Regime in Europe, Harmondsworth. Pelican,
(1972) 1983.
Williams, Raymond The Long Re1•ol111ion, London, Chatto and Windus,
1961.
Williams, Raymond Television: Technology and Cultural Form, Glasgow,
Fontana Collins, 1974.
Williams, Raymond Keywords: A Vocabulary of Culture and Society,
Glasgow, Fontana, 1976.
Williams, Raymond Marxism and Literature. Oxford, Oxford University
Press, 1977.
Williams, Raymond Problems in Materialism and Culture, London, Verso,
1980.
Williams, Raymond 'Problems of the Coming Period', Nell' Left Review, 140,
1983, pp. 7-18.
Williams, Raymond Towards 2000, Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1985.
Williams, Raymond Loyalties, London, Chatto and Windus, 1985.
Wills, Garry Inventing America: Jefferson's Declaration of Independence, New
York, Vintage Books, 1979.
Wingfield-Stratford, Esme The Foundations of British Patriotism, London,
Right Book Club, 1940.
Wirth, Louis 'Types of Nationalism', American Journal of Sociology, 41,
1936, p. 723-737.
Wolf, Eric R. Europe and the People Without History, Berkeley, CA,
University of California Press, 1982.
Worsley, Peter The Third World, London, Weidenfeld and Nicolson, ( 1964)
1978.
224 Nation Formation
Wright, Erik Olin 'Giddens's Critique of Marxism', New Left Review, 138,
1983, pp. 11-35.
Wright, Moorhead 'An Ethic of Responsibility', in James Mayall, ed., The
Community of States, Londo!l, George Allen and Unwin, 1982.
Wright, Patrick On Living in an Old Country: The National Past in
Contemporary Britain, London, Verso, 1985.
Wylie, Jonathan 'The Sense of Time, the Social Construction of Reality, and
the Foundations of Nationhood in Dominica and the Faroe Islands',
Comparative Studies in Society and History, 24, 1982, pp. 438-466.
Zeitland, Irving M. Ideology and the Development of Sociological Theory,
Englewood Cliffs, NJ, Prentice-Hall, 1968.
Zernatto, Guido 'Nation: The History of a Word', Review ofPolitics, 6, 1944,
pp. 351-366.
Zijderveld, Anton C. The Abstract Society: A Cultural Analysis of Our Time,
Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1974.
Zizek, Slavoj For They Know Not What They Do: Enjoyment as a Political
Factor, London, Verso, 1991.
Zubaida, Sarni 'Theories of Nationalism', in Gary Littlejohn, Barry Smart,
John Wakefield and Nira Yuval-Davis, eds, Power and the State, London,
Croom Helm, 1978.
Index
absolutism 40, 67,112,154--157,158,161, Albert,Prince,of Saxe-Coburg-Gotha 64
165; see also state allocative resources 151,159,164,165
abstract community xi,xv, 1-2,33, 35,43, Allgemeine Statslehre 126
44,46,48,53,85,102,104,117,151,164, Alsace and Lorraine,the regions of 88,89
175,176,178,182, 184, 186,192,passim; Alsatians and Lotharingians 37
as intentional oxymoron 16,185 Althusser, Louis 107,108, I 13,143,146
abstract society 25,123 analysis of modes of integration 31,I99-200;
The Abstract Society 25 defined 20-21; see also levels
abstract systems 176 analysis of modes of practice 31,198-199;
abstraction,and 'recalling of the concrete' defined 20
44-45,100-101; and reconstituting of Anderson,Benedict ix,xiii,I,5-8,15,39,44,
social relations 8,32,41,45--46,54,67,71, I l l ,130,134--135,139,157, 193;defining
134,185; and sense of liberation 44,72-73, nation 5; on imagination 7;on category of
134; as material process xii,39--42,80,93, time 6,68,78;on national formation as
I63ff.,184,188,195;as phantom 121; as 'modular' 8; on print culture 31,32,161
process in realm of ideas xii,I,5, 7 fn.13, anthropology xiii,44
39,77,93,94,119,188; as reification 73; Arena ix,xi fn. l, 176
avoiding dichotomy between concrete and Armstrong,John 13,15
abstract 3,33 fn.45, I l 9ff.; commodity Around the World in Eighty Days 56
abstraction 41,58,76,164,184;defined Asia (and the 'East') 98,155,156 fn.13-14,
184; in Hegelian sense 77; labour 164
abstraction 41,73,76,162,163-164,184; Australia and Australians 2,34, 36, 54, 106,
levels of 3,25, 37--46,80, 99,121,144; of 168,192
art 100;of boundaries 145; of Austria 34,61,118
communication 166; of intellectual authenticity 36,187
practice 42--45,79,80,194; of presence 37, authoritative resources 151,159-160,164,
100,166;of the person 11,73,175; of time 165
and space xi,9, 24,26, 31,36,38,57-58, authority 97,155,156; traditional versus
91,99,122,141,148,162,167,175,184, bureaucratic 27,29,127; see also
187,194 legitimacy
Academie Fran,aise 55 Azeglio, Massimo d' 62
Acton, Lord 66 fn.72,67,104,115
Adorno,Theodor l 46 Balibar, Etienne 5
agency and agents 25-27,28,32,54,153, Barres, Auguste Maurice 89,100,IOI
170-177; as self-reflexive 170-173, Barth, Fredrik I 68
175-176; comites 27; missi dominici 27 base-superstructure metaphor 21, 41, 48, 51,
agency-extended integration 14,25-31,32, 59, 61, 10Crl07,112, 114, IICrl 17,122,
38,43,45,66,75,94,134,154,155,163, 143, 148, 180,182
164,166,182,183,186,193, 199 Basques 15
age of nationalism 15,52ff. Baudelaire,Charles 67, 70
age of relativity 58 Bauer, Otto 48, 49, 51, 83, I14
age of self-definition 16 Bauman, Zygmunt 33
age of subjectivist culture 95, 98ff.,124,146, Bavaria 64
181 Beck, Ulrich 149
agrarian society 130-131, 139, 142, 144, 160 Belgium 34, 64
226 Nation Formation
Bell, D,m1el 106 Cannan, Edwin 12
Bendix, Reinhard 155- I 56 capital xv,34, 55,66,152,155,159
Benjamin,Walter 68, 78 Capital (Das Kapital) 53,78
Bergson, Henri 96 Capital and Class 129
Berman, Marshall 59 capitalism 41,55,58,68, I 10,114,117,
Bernstein, Richard 177-178,179 159-162,181,188;and uneven
1 he Bih/e 4-5, 23; The Vulgate 11 development 109,155,167,189;as
Bismarck, Otto von 52,60. 61,65, 71,89 homogenizing (levelling) force 56,58;
Blaut,James 50 industrial capitalism 20,151,160-161,
Bloch, Marc 174 163,199,200;information capitalism 20,
blood, 'and soil' xiii,22,24,89, 180, 182; 'is 148, 199;late capitalism 36,37,106,124,
thicker than water' 24; 'of free 141,147,170,176; monopoly capitalism
personalities' 43,92; of the people xiv;ties 106; print capitalism 6,54,79,161;
4,6,16,24,61,63,64, 99,168 postmodern capitalism xv, 200; see also
Bloom,Solomon 65-66 mode of production
Bluntschli,Johann 126 Castells, Manuel 36
body and embodiment xiv,21,22,28,31,34, Castoriadis,Cornelius 6-7,152
35,124,200;corpus Christi 28;embodied Castro, Fidel 126
difference 38;embodied interaction 23-25, Catalans 15
30,42;embodied power 60;King's Two categorical analysis 200;defined 21
Bodies 28-29,61-62,185,195; see also categorical formations 38;see also particular
di�embodied integration formations such as modernity
body politic 11,29,30,39-40,62,155,195 Caucasus I
borderless world 123 Cavour, Camillo Benso 62
borders, see boundaries cenotaphs and tombs 2-3, 28,44, 185;
Borochov, Ber 51 defined 3;in Warsaw 2,6; Polish Tomb
Bosnia xv of the Unknown Soldier 2;see also
Bottomore,Tom 49 death
Bougainville xv Central Problems in Social Theory 172
boundaries xiv,12-14,20,24,35,127,141, change, see historical change
144ff.,165,168,1-84; and cosmopolitanism Charlemagne 27,28
43;as distingiTished from frontiers 13,153; Charles V 41
national 12,34,54,61,152,191;state 13, Charron, Pierre 40
89,152,164,192 Chaucer, Geoffrey 63
Bourdieu, Pierre 23 Chile 157
Brant, Sebastien 75 China 26,155,158
Braudel, Fernand 22, 25, 139 Chirac,Jacques 118
The Break-up of Britain 118 Chu Hsi,philosophy of 156
Bretons 37 citizens and citizenship xii,2,46,55,60,61,
Breuilly, John 60, l 08 86,192;and abstract egalitarianism 70;
Britain (United Kingdom) 15,33,42,63, and the public sphere 191; as members of
113,115, 119-120, l 21;as phoney an illusory sovereignty 81;passport
geography 121;break-up of 108 citizenship 121
Brown,John,as royal retainer, 64 city, as a power container 162
Browning, Elizabeth Barrett 23 city state,see state
Buckle,H.T. 67 Cfri/ War in France 53
Bulgaria 64 class 11,13,38,44,48,56,58,59,64,68,74,
bureaucracy,see modes of organization 81, 99,110,119,131,141,153,162, 172,
Burke, Edmund 43 173,181, l 94;class consciousness 164;
Burke, Kenneth 98 ruling class 47,50,70,81,117,119,142,
Burschenshaft 52 162; class struggle 50,163; Junker class 90;
petit-bourgeoisie 11O; working class
Cambodia (Kampuchea) 3 (proletariat) 50,91,115
Canadian Revie11· of Studies in Nationalism cognitive maps (mental maps) 16,38
125 Colletti,Lucio I 08
Index 227
commodification 148,157,161,163,172, death and mortality xi,I. 3,12,24,44,58,
I 97; of time and space 36,162 99, 100, IOI; hara kiri 36; in the name of
common culture thesis 142 the nation I,86,89,126,185; skulls 2-4,
Communist Manifesto 47,52,53, 70,76 111; see also cenotaphs and tombs
community 123,141,164, 179,191-192, Debord,Guy 146
196---197; creole 157; defined 184; from Debray,Regis 22,49,I18,146
above 12I; of foreigners 10; natural 117; of deconstruction 179,181,182,200
strangers 40,45,46,59,189 (see also A Deleuze, Giles 152
Nation of Strangers); of tradition 128; Derrida,Jacques 152
religious 5,10; sacred 6; total 76; 'unto determination 143,148,159
death' 100-101,102,I95; see also abstract The Difficult Dialogue 51
community,ethnic community dilTusionism, I19,156,157,158
computers 58,I06,119 Dilke, Charles Wentworth 56
Comte, Auguste 77,91 diplomacy 61,71
Connolly, James 51 Diponegoro, Prince 117-118
Connor, Walker 15,59 discontinuity, see continuity
conservatism 99 disembodied integration (and extension) 5,
The Constitution of Society 170,172 31-34,36,38,45,74,134,166,175,180,
constitutive abstraction argument (levels 184,192,193,195, 199;see alsoextension
argument) xi fn.l,43,68,78,85,114,120, The Divided Nation 41
155,181-197 passim division of labour 37,96,97,131, 137,140,
A Contemporary Critique of Historical 141,143, 160
Materialism 108,172 Djibouti 14
contingency 15I Dostoevsky, Fyodor 67
continuity,historical,75 'double hermeneutic' 21
continuity-in-discontinuity 19,44,75-77,79, Dowd,Charles Ferdinand 56
114,167-168,174ff.,190-193 Dupre, Louis 70-71
contradiction xi-xiii,I,16,28-29,46,58,82, Durkheim, Emile xiii, 25,42,69,83-102
96,99, 184,187; defined 185; ontological passim, 127,128, 138, 151,152,179,180,
(cultural),28,34,48,64,99,195; see also 181, 182,194; ambiguous response to
nation nation 88,92-93,96,97
Cooley, Charles 25,83
Cornish,language 145 Eagleton,Terry 78-79,107
Corsicans 37 East Timor I
Coser, Lewis 98-99 Eberhard, Wolfram 139
cosmopolitanism xi,43,47,88,89,92,106, economic reductionism,115
110,144,183,186,196; 'a brotherhood of education 65--06,89, 90-91, 137,143 144,
mankind' 180 189; generic intellectual training 66,91,
Coulanges, Fustel de 25 145,173,192,193,194 (see also
cultural; definition of 124; realm of I06; rise intellectually trained); literacy 131
of 52,107,122,133,137,146 149,177, Egypt 28,118
182 Einstein,Albert 58,91 fn.31,96
cultural capital 116 The Elementary Forms of Reli!{ious Life 85,
cultural management 2, 21,36, 61,188 88 fn.22
culture,as commodified. 148; as Elias, Norbert 27,139
epiphenomena) 115, 122; as simulacrum Eliot,George 78-79
147-148; see also cultural embeddedness 18-19, 46; in relation to
Culture, Identity and Politics 123 choice 17
'wltus of the abstract man' 76 embodiment; see body
Czechoslovakia 34,107 Emerson, Rupert 125, 127
empires 26---27,60, 86. 90, 105,191, 192;
Dante Alighieri 63, 80,99, 182 Assyrian 26; British 54. 63; Carolingian
Darwin, Charles 58 26, 27; Chinese 26; French.118; Hol}
Darwinism 80, 90 Roman Empire of the German Nation 71;
Davis,Horace I09 Roman 26, 27,75,159
228 Nation Formation
empirical generalization 31. 53,154,191, Feuerbach, Ludwig 70
198; defined 19-20 Fiori,Guiseppe l08
empiricism 20, 68, 78,125 flags 2-3
The Enchanted Glass 119,121 Flaubert, Gustave 88, 89
Encounters ll'ith Nationalism 123,134 Fogg, William Perry 56
Engels,Friedrich 42,47-82 passim, 83 foreigners and foreignness 33,121
Er.gland and the English 29,33,56,64,65, form 51,88,129,148,154,170,176,182,192;
86,I10,113,122,154; as 'first nation',63 defined 19; as distinguished from content
Enlightenment 41,48 4,6,16 fn.48,155,195; form analysis,20
Enquiry Concerning Political Justice 43 fn.3, 189,191; as related to content 8,99,
Erasmus,Desiderius 75 IOI; textual form 78
Ernest I of Hanover 64 Foucault, Michel 152,162
essentialism xii,15,22,80,112,113-114,116, fragmentation and dissolution 58,71,I00,
117,122,182,190 IOl-l 02,106,110,148,161,172, 185;'all
Ethiopia 14 that is solid melts into air' 66ff.,IOI,124,
ethnic community (ethnie) 15-17,59; defined 180; social entropy 146
16; vertical ethnie 142 France and the French 11,15,36,37,56,60,
ethnic revival 64, l 05-I06 71,86,88-89, l 06, I10,118,154;as 'first
ethnicity 11,16,27,35,36,112,113-114, nation-state' 8;France l 0
121,161;as contradictory 15;ethnic Frankfurt school 138
cleansing I Frederick William I 13
ethnocentrism 17,I00,132 French Revolution,see revolutions
Eurocentrism 155-158 Freud,Sigmund 48,169
Europe 13, 25,26,27,40,53,56,60,63,70, Freudianism 80
71,72,86,97,100,104, l 05,I18,120,151, Frisians 37
154-157,169,174,182,183; Eastern frontiers 13, 153, 157
Europe 48,106,108,137,195;Western functionalism 91, l 19, 128, 132, 142, 145,
Europe l 06, II0,112,I58,164,I65;see 190
alsoparticular countries, regions and
peoples Garibaldi,Giuseppe 62
European Bureau of J:_,esser Languages 145 Geertz,Clifford 22,104,128,168
evolution from 'the simple to the complex' Gellner,Ernest xiii,50,51,87,96,98,108,
132,138-139 110,111,I13,129-150passim, 160,167,
exile 53,60,72,80,118,129,188,189 177,179, 182-195passim; on nations as
extension,social 34,35,36,38-39,48,54, invented 15,104,115,145,148;on
57-58,64, 66, 79,80, 81,120,140, 141, relationship between structure and culture
148,153,164,168,175,177,183, 185;see 132ff.;on 'rise of the cultural' 122,133,
also space 135-137,142-143,146ff.
Gemeinschaft und Gesellschaft 127,138
face-to-face,as a level of social integration, gender 17,29 fn.28,38,126,200;and
xii,14,23-25,26,27,30,38,43,45,75,80, patriarchy 200;and sexual difference 124,
122,134,171,174, 192,195,196,199; I82; see also fatherland
communities I0,133; interaction 6,30,31, genealogy 12,16,26,28;claims to integrity
85,120,175,184;metaphors of xii,23,42, of 35;and the sacred 6; tracing ancestors
120;relations 9,28,32, 43,59,61,64,66, xi
104,117,140,155,163,164,171,185 genocide 3
factuality 68-69 Genossenschaft/Herrschaft distinction 127
family xii,5,30,34,120, 174; metaphors of 5 Geoffrey of Monmouth 42
fascism 86, IOI geography,discipline of xiii,13,84,139
fatherland 5, 28,41,72,86,93; 'in abstracto' Germanie 10
93,181; see also patria German Law of Associations 54
feminism 53, l 07 German Mentality and the War 84
Ferry,Jules 89 Germany II,44-45,47,52,56,59,60--61,65,
feudalism 13,25,26,27,65, 98,112,114, 71-72, 75,77,88,89-90,112; German
142,159,162,164,173,174,199 unification 52,53,60,62, 71,90
Index 229
Giddens,Anthony xiii,xiv,12-14,98,108, history, discipline of xiii,54, 68,75, 84,94,
134-135,139,149,150,151-178,179, 101,139
182-195 passim; definition of nation 14, history, treated asjanus-faced 103, I16---117,
167; on presence 23,34 fn.49,36,167,168, I18, 132,190
170--171; on social integration 24 fn.12, History of Civilization in England 67
171-172; on time and space 36---37,153, History of the Kings of Britain 42
166, I68,171 Hobbes,Thomas 28,195
Gierke,Otto von 54,127 Hobsbawm, Eric 62,109,115,118,125, 167
gift exchange,see modes of exchange Hobson,John A. 92
Gill,Gerry 179 Hohenlohe-Schillingfiirst,Chlodwig zu 61
global village 58, 119 homeland 29
globalization xv,48,56---58, 68,81,106,148, Un Homme Libre 100
176,191,196; and local xi; and meta homogenization of culture 142, 143, 179,
national 34,181 183-184, 190
Godwin,William 43 Horne, Donald 136, 148
Goffman,Irving 23 Hroch, Miroslav 8,110,137
Goody, Jack 31,32 Huizinga,Johan 9,11
Goldmann, Lucien 107, 146 humanism 30,44---45
Gramsci,Antonio 49,51,107,108
Grand Theory 113 IBM (International Business Machines)
Great Chain of Being 75,142 140
Great Divide 3,54,96---97,98, 113,127-128, ideal-type theorizing 87,94,97,127;
132,160,190ff.; traditional/modern distinguished from 'form analysis' 22
distinction 138,150,153,190 identity 21,26,38,45,157,164,176,194;
Great Transformation 127 being remade 72, 148, 175; fragility of xi,
Greater Britain 56 147; framed by kinship 10, 164; framed by
Greenfeld, Liah 7,88 the nation 136, 149; identity politics 17; as
Grundrisse 107 ontologically contradictory 28,144,192;
Guattari, Felix 152 as part of an aggregate I0,11; totemic 2,
Guenee,Bernard 11,27 fn.21 175; see also national identity
Gutenberg,Johann 54 ideology 8 fn.15,21,78-79,91,107,112,121,
126, 165; of autonomy 177; as fabrication
Habermas,Jurgen 24 fn.12,138 115-116; ideological formation 160;
Haiti 157 ideological state apparatuses 143
Hall,John 130 !gnatieff,Michael 196
Hamlet4 imaginary 6---7,69,152; defined 7
Hanover 64 imagination and imagining,concepts of 5-8,
Hardy,Thomas 67 46
Hechter,Michael 130 Imagined Communities I,5-8
Hegel,Georg 41,74,75,76,85 imperialism, I10, I18,156; see also empires
Heller,Agnes 172-173 India 63,71
Henry VIII 29 individualism 43,94,139; anarchic 76; and
Hertz, Frederick 11 ideology of autonomy 176---177, 200; and
Hintze,Otto I65 possessive individual 177
historical change xi,xiv,60--61,101, 129; 'the individuation 74,96,136; Discovery of the
more things change . . .' 76; see also Individual 172
upheaval Indonesia I,6, I I7-118
historical materialism 8,48, I09,126,165, industrial society 130,140,143,190
177,194,198; as cultural materialism 21, industrialism 106,143,151, 159-161, 188;
I07; in relation to idealism 7; see also conjunction with capitalism 160
base-superstructure metaphor industrialization 115,131, 137,145,189
historicity xiv, 100,103,105,121,175, information revolution 54
187-188,190,195; past as pastiche 36, information society 32, 177
106; past as place to be visited 44; present integration, social; see levels of integration;
as constructed or artificial 116---117,121 see also societal integration
230 Ntitipn Formwion
intellectual practice 47,85, 186,192-195; as kingship 28-29,43,60,74,156; see also
abstract and abstracting 9,31,43--44,45, monarchy
68, 74, 77-80, 94,98,100-101,184; as kinship 3-5,6,10,16,24,27,30,36,45,61,
technique xii,45 117, 135,174,176,187; and nation 4-5,
intellectually trained 43,45,46,97, 110, �3. 59,I64,I68, I 83; and state 5,39
I 86, I92; defined 9 fn.20; see also Kitching,Gavin 129,149
education knowledge 200; relativization of,65,IO I; as
intellectuals (intelligentsia) 42-45,46,54,65, single epistemological space in modem
72,98, JOI,108,112,I15,124,145,188; societies 138,140-141,142,143,183-184
ambiguous place of 43,67-68,74,193; Kohn,Hans 154
clerical (scribal) 9,I0,43, 67,13I,136, Kornhauser,William 138
142, 192; contradictory ("double' ) Kristeva,Julia 152
ontology o f45,67,77,99,176,181,186; Kropotkin, Peter 84
defined 9 fn.20; inventing or promoting Kulrurkampf65, 89,91
national formation 8,98,11O; and related
groupings 31,56 language(s) 6,11,54-55, 62, 107,131,200; as
interaction,distinguished from contact and abstracting 9; mother tongue 5; Romance
integration 23-25,192 fn.12; see also face IO; as vernaculars or dialects 8,9,31,60,
to-face 63,145, 182
international relations 12 Lasch,Christopher 147
internationalism 43,52,54,195,196 Latin I0,11; as truth language 9
internationalization 53-59, 65,66,180; see Latin America 8,110,157
also globalization law 29,153,166,174; Law of Guarantees 62
intersection,as analytically distinguished Lawrence, D.H. 92
from conjuncture 38,59; see also levels Le Bon,Gustave 91, I69
invention,cultural xiv,8,36,62,103-104, Le Play,Pierre 54
ll 5-117,145,190; ofmeaning 95-96; of Lefort, Claude 6
nations 15,60, 152, 180, 186--188; of legitimacy 60,142; crisis of 128; see also state
tradition 18, 52,115-116,118, 122 Lenin,Vladimir 49,83
The Invention of Tradition 115 Leopold I 64
Ireland and the Irish I5; Gaeltachr 145 Lerner, Daniel 128
lrian Jaya (West Papua) I levels (modes),of (ontological) abstraction,
lskander, Fazil 4 see abstraction; the concept of xiv, 3, 36,
Israel 14 38, 56,59,65,81,136--137,140,174,176,
Italia irredenta 61 180,185,188; of integration 2,4, 5,6,14,
Italians,making of,62 21-37,42,43,59-66 passim, 71,79,80,
Italy 61-62,65; and Italia, 188-189 117, 121-122, 133-134,137,149,163,166,
167,174,180,185,189,192,196 (see also
Jameson, Fredric 36,51,107,122; on the particular modes of integration); the
cultural sphere 147-149 intersection-in-contradiction of 27, 28,32,
Japan 13,36,65,98,I55,I56; Way of Japan 34,38,66,76,99,120,121,140,164,197;
as the Way of the Gods, I56 the intersection-in-dominance of 21,
Jews 14; Hebrew, 145 31-32,34,38,39,45,127,174,181,185,
Johnson, Samuel 196 193; of theoretical or epistemological
Johnston, R.J. 139 abstraction 19,31,127,154,189,
198-200
Kandinsky,Wassily JOO lexicography 54; Cornish-English dictionary
Ka utsky, Karl 83 154
Kedourie,Elie 104,I15,142 liberalism 18,50,78
Kenya 14 'lifting out', as a process 68,78,79,99; see
Kiernan, V.G. 154 also abstraction
King's Two Bodies, see body and linguistics,the discipline of xiii, 55
embodiment literary studies xiii,78-79
kingdom 5,29,154,191; etymology of Locke,John 70
concept 11-12; see also state,monarchical Louis XIV 13,29
Index 231
Louis XVI 157 migration xv, 56,192;Auswanderung 72
Lyotard, Jean-Fran9ois 138, 139 Miliband, Ralph 49,124
military institutions 26 fn.17, 30,65,115,
MacDougall, Hugh 67 174; Gefolgschaft 27,28,159;loyalty to
Mach, Ernst 96 26--27
Machiavelli, Niccolo 21,39,80,177 military power 71,102,110,151,153-154,
Maclaughlin, Jim 30 I 56,158-160, 182,183;nuclear weapons
McNeill, William 158 testing 118
Maine, Henry 25,54,127 Minogue, Kenneth 104
The Man Without Qualities 100 Mishima Yukio 126
Mann, Michael 7,22,26 fn.17, 153,158 Mitterand,Fran�ois 118
Mann,Thomas 96 Mitzman, Arthur 89
Manx, the language of 145 mobile privatization l 06, 139
maps 38;as abstract lines 13 modernism 15,19,21,100,103,132,155,
Marcuse, Herbert 146 167,180,182,187
market xii,9,54,134, 155, 159,163;see also modernity xiii,91,106,128,149,176,180,
mode of exchange l 91,200;and the dissolution of solidity
Marx, Karl xiii, 41,42,48-82 passim, 83,85, 67-72,111;early modern period 11-13,
111,119,128,149,152,162,164,179,180, 45;modern as against archaic or
182,194;ambiguous response to the primordial 54,113,167 (see also Great
nation 59-60,66, 70,80-82,181;on Divide; primordialism);modern period 96,
'historic' nations 62,112;on historyless 114,117,137,139,151
peoples 55,81 Moderniry and Self-ldenlily l 76
marxism I8,20,21,48, 50-51, 82, I03-122 modernization 65,89,128,141,181,194;
passim, 144,146,148,151,159,180; modernization theory l 29; 'reflexive
Second International 49, 83 modernization' 149
mass communications; see mass media modes (and means) of communication 20,30,
mass media xii,32-33,35,117,120,134,137, I19,127,134,189, 198;electronic (digital)
192;electronic,including television 33,34, 9, 45,166,185;oral 24, 32;print 6,8,9,
35,45,192;news, the concept of 54; 30,31,99,175;telegraph and telephone
newspaper and the press 6,32,33,45,54, 54, 58,64,180;writing 9,27,30,31,32,
61,64,100,175,180,192;satellite 43,45,89,175, 181;see also mass media
broadcasting 34,58 modes of enquiry 20,189,199;
mass society model 129, I381T. scientific-rational, 68-69,77-78, 96,140
masses, as a category of people 33,110, l 23, modes of exchange 20,127,174,189,198;
193 barter 9,27;commodity and capital 9,20,
Mauss,Marcel 27,128 fn.19 25,27,36,37,42,59,64,134, 137,156,
Mayer,Arno 66 159,180;reciprocity ('gift exchange') 3,4,
Mazzini, Giuseppe 53,63,67,80,126 9,24,27,117,164 (see also reciprocity, as
mediation,the concept of,xii,25 social relation)
medieval period 10-1 I,26--27,39,41,42,45, modes (and means) of organization 20, 27,
47,60,97,98,182,188 189 127,165 167,169,189,199;
Meiji Restoration 65 bureaucratic-rational 27,29, 31, 32,97,
Meinecke, Friedrich 43,84,92,186 135;patrimonial 27,29
Meininger theatre troupe 68 modes of practice 19,20,22,198 199; see
Mendeleyev, Dimitri 77,96 also particular modes. for example, modes
merchants and traders 9,86,188 of production
Mesopotamia 31 modes (and means) of production 20, 41, 68,
methodological individualism 85,94-95,101, 74, 81,106, 110, 114,122, l55ff., 163, 165,
170 174,182,189, 196,198, 199; capitalist 6,
methodological nationalism 86, 123 37, 42,73,81, 86;information-based
Mexico 157 I06-107
Michelet, Jules 126 monarchy 4, 26, 28, 33. 39,60-6 l. 62, 63-64.
Middle East 26 66-67,89,112, 119-121, 155;theCro"n
Middlemarch 78 119; see also kingship
232 Nqtion Formation
Monet, Claude 67 nation,cont.
money 27, 153, 161, 163, 189 as phantom 124 fn.3; as politically
Montesquieu,Charles-Louis de Secondat 80, sovereign people 13; postmodern nations
99 34-36,39, 46,185,191,192; and poverty
mortality,see death and mortality of theory xii,48-52,59,75,83, 84-87,98,
Mosca, Gaetano 83, 85, 86-87 • 104,119,123,124-125,151,181,182-184;
Moser,Justus 44,45 fn.85, 75 pre or preter-national association 43; as
Muir, Ramsay 84 'primordial' relation xi,19-20, 46,66,114,
multiculturalism 93,192 180; reduced to virtual community 94-95,
Munck,Ronaldo 51 125 fn.3; as repository of highest ideals 90,
Musil, Robert Elder von 100,IOI 92;.as self-conscious 79,148; sub-state
myth-symbol complexes (mythomoteur) nations 15,37; as uneven in formation 66;
15-16,67 as 'willed' association 12,13,83 fn.l,90,
125-126
Nairn,Tom xiii,49,51, 81,103, 104,107-122 A Nation of Strangers 140
passim, 124,130,144,159,161,167,179, nation-building 8,33,36, 158
182-195 passim; on 'historic' nations 111, national identity 35,86,136,176; as a social
112; on the nation as 'natural' 112-113; on fact 84,108,112; as given or natural 105,
nationalism 112-113, 180 113, 114; as primordial 112-113, 121;
naming 7, 174 contradictions of xi-xiii, 16,120;
natio 9-11, 14, 16,29-30, 42, 45, 186, 'nationality as 'already dead' 49,55, 58,59
191-192; defined 10,30; as pre-modern 18; national integration as imperative 88-90,
as pre-political 67 96
nation,as abstract community xi-xiii,xv, national interest 85, 93,95
1-17,45, 46, 85, 98, 178, 179,182,passim national symbols,see symbols and signs
(see also abstract community); abstract nationalism xi, xv, I,8,30,34, 43,54,62,
nation 90, 92-93; as abstract relation to 112,145,166,191; changing form of
99; as anachronistic 123; as becoming 105-106,107; concept of 11-12,109,110;
artificial l 04; as bound by destiny or fate cultural 60; as culture worshipped directly
47,48,114; as bounded community 48,86, 123; defined 11-12; dispassionate 89,93,
141; as chosen 35,46; 'classical' nations 95; as European 8, 98,169; as
35,46,149; as com,rnunity of strangers identification with High Culture 123; as
xi-xii 6,16,25,'33,39,75, 80,86,104,163, invented 104, I 141T.; as inventing nations
I 66,178, 185; concept of 10-12,59,81,83, 104,148, 167, 187; asjanus-faced 111,167;
97-98, 109,191; contradictory nature of liberal nationalism 85, 89; as modem 37,
xii-xiii I,12,16,35, 46,59,66,80,102, 106, 121; and modernization 110-111, 129,
149,177,178,183,195; as deeply 161; nationalist movements 105-106; neo
embedded 18-19,46,105,180, 195; nationalism 37,42, 105-106, 119, 146, 191,
defined 91T.,14, 167; diaspora nations 14; 195; new nationalism 35-37, 42,106, 110,
as disengaging from traditional ties xiii; 191; as objective need for homogeneity
'drank of the blood of free personalities' I42; oppositional as against official
43,92; as 'fictitious' unity 67,81,I15 nationalism 193; as personal psychology
fn.44,187; and form of subjectivity 78; 1671T.,183; as political ideology 8,14, 43,
fragility of 80; as gut-felt xii; 'historic' 60, 105, 125, 128,166, 1671T., 183; post
nations 62, 111, 112, l 141T.,182-183,189; nationalism I96; as pre-modem 120;
as imagined community I,5-8,39; as reduced to fictitious representation 69; as
imposed association 30,92, 112; religion 5, 76,84, 99; as replacing religion
irredentist nations 14; as matter of attitude 86; as tribalism 5, 119; ultra-nationalism
or feeling,15,95; as melting into air 80, 90,95, 101
180; as modern xii-xiii,18,33, 80,113; Die Nationalitiitenfrage und die
modem nations 39,46,193; as modular, Sozialdemokratie 48
transportable 8; as 'natural' or taken for nationality, see national identity
granted 17, 34-35, 42,47,49,67, 80-81, Nations and Nationalism 129,131,132,
85,86,90,92, 111,114,180; 'old con 140
tinuous nations' 62; as organic society 97; nation-state, as abstract community 151, 164;
Index 233
nation-state, con/. ontological security 37, 171,172
as administrative structure I05, 158, 161, ontology 161; changing forms of 5,57,116,
164ff.,180,182, 187; as artificial 117,152, 160, 164, 177; and cultural depth, 35--36,
181; and capitalism 159-16 I; as central to 46, 92, IO I, 146; defined xii; and identity
international relations xi, 151; classical 148; ontological shakiness, 149; and social
nation-state 34,191; concept of IO, 12-13, frame 7, 91, 118; 'what is-ness' , 96, IOI,
I58; conjunction of nation and state 12, 14, 180, 181; see also abstraction,
40, 42, 45,47,57,67,89, 96,104, 131, 180, contradiction
182,185; and continuing tribal solidarities Ooms, Herman 156
5; 'death of' xi 37,111,165,180; defined The Organization of rhe Family 54
13ff.,157,160, 165, 166; dissolving from Orridge, Andrew 130
within 34; as European in origin 154-157; Ortega y Gasset, Jose 138
as framing people's lives xi, xv, 70, 152; Ouston, Philip 100
'historic' 62, 11 O; immutability of 83; as
imposed 117; as kokutai 5, 65; as modem Packard, Vance 140
xi, xii 14,18,34, 46, 67, 70,114,118; Pan-German League 52 fn.20, 85, 90
modem nation-state 34-35,41; monopoly Pareto, Vilfredo 83, 85
over means of violence 65 ( see also Paris Commune 53
violence); as nation-state (state-nation) parochialism IOI, I08, 196; penetrated from
158, I66, I82; as part of system of nation outside 148
states 151; permeability of boundaries xv, Parsons, Talcott 128
34; as power container 153, 160,165, 167; particularistic relations 5, 6
resistance to 117, I8 I; as rooted in past 68; patria (la patrie) 9, 28, 29-30, 40, 42, 88, 114,
as taken for granted 90, 151; unevenly 116, 154, 188; communis patria 11,29; see
consolidating 30 fn.35,59-60,70,105,180; also fatherland, state
and Volksgeist 76 patrimony 27, 29, 191
The Nation-State and Violence 158, 161,168 patriotism (amor patriae) 17, 29-30, 86, 87,
natural, and the artificial 132,181; see also 8&-89, 99, 188, 195; compatriotism 164;
nation pro patria mori 29-30
naturalization of citizenry xi, 16 people 11, 16, 20, 29, 41,42, 44, 60, I10; as
Nietzsche, Friedrich 58,67,70, 73,96, 165 audience 45--46; as basic unit of analysis
Netherlands and the Dutch 37, 72, 110,154 55; as natural subject of history 43; 'of the
New Left Review 107, 108 United States of America' 157
New Zealand 34,36 perennialism 19
Newton, Isaac 77 performing arts 68, 69, 76
Nicholas II 64 Periodic Table of Elements 77, 78
Nimni, Ephraim 50 persons; as abstract heroes 3, 35; abstracted
Nisbet, Robert 128 xii, 29, 93, 119; as actors 171, 172-173; as
Normandie 10 autonomous authors of our own identity
North America 105 176--177; fictitious or 'Artificial/ person'
nostalgia 44, 117,176 28, 74; mobility of 131,140,144; as self
active subjects 134, 148, 170,176, 190;
Oakesmith, John 84 theorized 48, l70ff.
object-mediated integration 25 Peterson, Scott 4
objectification (rcification) 73 Petrarch. Francesco 63, 80, 99, 182,188,
objective relations; see under subjective being 189
Olympics 35,36 peuple; see people
ontological categories, concept of xii, 21, 37, Philosophes 54
182,200; see also specific categories such as Philosophiae Natura/is Principia
body and embodiment, time Mathematica 77
ontological formations 21,123,149, 200;see phtlosophy, the discipline of 68, 69,76, 177;
also particular formations such as as keeper of the state 79
modernity Phoenicians 59,112
ontological levels, as collapsed into one plane Picardie 10
141; see also plane Piedmontesc 61,62
234 Natipn Formation
place. abstraction of 13, 26,36, 45,67,188, Quebecois 15
191. 192; category of xi,10, 71, 81,117, Queen Mother (Elizabeth Bowes-Lyon) 33
182, 189, 195,196; defined 26 fn.16;
disdain for 186; out of place 43; unvisited race 12,16,17,35,67,90, 117
places xii racial difference 17, 38
Planck, Max 96 racism 55, IOI
plane,metaphor of xiv, 56, 58, 59,66, 81-82, railways 54,57,64
92, IOI,116,154,167,170; defined 38, Ranger,Terence 115
185,190,191 Ranke,Leopold von 68
Plato 79 ration,11lization 41,96,97,101-102,181, 193,
Poggi, Gianfranco 27,154,155 197
Poland 3 real (reality),as against artificial 73-74,103,
Polanyi, Karl 127 104,I16--117,121,147; category of xiii,
political economy,the disciple of 18, 48 69-70,71,94,100,121, 124; reality as
political science 83,86 simulacrum 147; reality as veiled 69,73,
popular culture 60, 148 80,IOI,181
Portugal 64, I10 reciprocity,as social relation 3,4,27,45,132,
positivism 68,69,76,96 164, 170,196; see also modes of exchange
post-industrialism 106 Redus, Elisee 84
postmodemism xiv,21,106,123,149, 152, religion xii,9, 61,78,84,97,123,174;
188 Calvinism 89; Christianity 72;
postmodemity (postmodern settings) I8,35, Confucianism 156; Judaism and rabbinic
38,146,149,191,196,200 tradition 72,89; Protestantism 108;
post-structuralism 21,113-114,115,122, 145 Reformation 63; Shinto 156
Poulantzas,Nicos 51,107,I10,I13,125,162 religious institutions,bishoprics, abbeys and
power 152,153; abstracted 29,40,I19-120, monasteries 27,30,61,112,114, 134;
155,165,179; administrative power 151, Church (Christian) 4,65,89; Church of
153, 154, 165, 168,169; conferred by the England 63,67; medieval reform councils
people 62; depersonalized 13,27,40,155; I0,28; Vatican 62
disciplinary 156,162; embodied 155; as religious sodalities, Christendom 26,97,144;
everywhere I65; ex!ended by agents 25,60; Islamic society 144; Middle Kingdom
monarchical 62-,67,71,120; patrimonial 144
29; political 6I,98; and prestige 98; state Remembrance of Things Past 58
161,162,177 Renaissance 41,97
practical consciousness 171-172 Renan,Joseph Ernest 12,88,89,95, 126
presence (co-presence) 23-25,37,167, representation(s) 69; embodied 65; forms of
170--171,172,174--175; and contiguity 2-5
168; see also abstraction Republic of Gran Colombia 157
primordial-modern divide 113, 132,152,I86, republicanism 63,120
I90ff.; see also Great Divide; modernism, revanchisme 89
primordialism revolutions 55; English 63,I03; French 8,
primordialism xi, xii,15,16,18-19,22,IOI, 157; of 1848 52, 53 fn.21; Tudor 67
103-104,106,111,112,114,128, 146, 149, Reynolds,Susan 116
167,172, 180,182,188,190 Rhineland 52, 71
Principia Mathematica 96 Ricoeur, Paul 175
private property I3,153 Ripalda,Jose 41--42,74
progress,the ideology of I10,187; from tribe Risorgimento 62
to nation 84 Romanticism 72-73, 78
The Protestant Ethic 85, 95 fn.63 Romantics 43
Proust, Marcel 58 roots,social xi,xiii,36,I87
Prussia 59,71,72,76 Rose,J. Holland 84
psychoanalysis 108,109-110,185 Round the World 56
public relations 61,63 fn.63 Rousseau,Jean-Jacques 79, 80, 93,128
routinization I38,168,171-172,174
Quaderni de/ Carcere I07 Russell, Bertrand 96
Index 235
Russia xv, I, 71 Sohn·Rethel, Alfred 40-41,139
Rwanda xv, I,3 solidarity, mechanical and organic 25,96,
127,132,137,138; modem 97
Sack, Robert 139 Somali 14
sacred 4,156,187; rationalization of 61-62, South America 164
65; see also time, Messianic sovereignty 35,40,43, 60, 89,181,191; see
Santa Domingo 157 also state
Sartre,Jean.Paul 108 Soviet Union 48,I06; see also Russia
Sathyamurthy,T.V. 130 space,category of xiv,3,21,22,23,35,36,
Sayer, Derek 73 56--58, 74,80,91, 99, 142-143, 153,167,
science; see modes of enquiry 170,185,I87,I 93, I94,200; hyperspace
Schlegel,August Wilhelm von 72 36; as locale 24,36,99, 138, I96; as
Schopenhauer, Arthur 70 relative 57-58; and spatial extension 24,
Scotland and the Scottish 15,33,64,71, I08, 29,30,36,140,171,174,175-176,192; see
111,115-116, 118; Scots Gaelic 145; also abstraction of time and space; place;
Scottish National Party I08; and tartan 64 territory and territoriality
115 Spain 15,86,110
Scott,Sir Walter 23 Spencer, Herbert 84,9 I
Second Law of Thermodynamics 77-78 Sri Lanka 15
sectarianism IOI Stalin, Joseph 83,114
self,and other xii,10; as infinite 73; standardization 138, I39
subordinated 86; see also persons state 55-56, 59, 86,94, I05,112,119,131,
selfhood xii 15 I, 177,184, I93; absolutist state 40,45,
Seton.Watson, Hugh 61,62,125-126,127 60,153-157,160,161,162,164,174, 181;
Shafer, Boyd 125 'abstract state' 40 fn.70, 45,91, 103, I19,
Sharp, GeofT ix,xi fn.1, 41,58 fn.43, 120,157,191; abstraction of 14,32,40,63,
134-135,168,179,188 73,153; as administrative structure 156,
Shennan, J.H. 40,119 161; and agency extension 26--27,34,134;
Shils,Edward 104,128 anciens regimes 66,157; authoritarian state
Simkhovitch, Vladimir 76 13; bureaucratization of 97; city state 5,
Simmel, Georg 83,85,86 97; and concept of slalus 11, 39; defined
Smith,Adam 12,74 13; etymology of 11,39-40; family state 5;
Smith,Anthony xiii, 15,34,39,88,112 fn.31, as having personality 126; legitimacy 12,
128-129, 142,168,193 35; lo stato 39; modem state 81,110,153,
social change; see historical change 169; monarchical state 4,29,40,97,157;
social democracy 18 penetrating life.world 46; power state
social facts,concept of 69,91-92, IOI ( Machslaal) 89; sovereignty 13, 14,40,74,
social formation, concept of, 21,38,43,130, 174,188; Stondeslaat (policy of states) 29,
184,185,189,191,199; defined,19,20, 71,154; State·nations 112,157; traditional
127 state 153,161; as way of God 76,156
social movements 106,107 status 98
social regulation 21; see also cultural status/contract distinction 127
management Stokes,Gale 129
socialism 18,48,85, I99; ontological Stonehenge 44
socialism 196 strangers xi,xii,25,33,35, 166, 183,184,
societal (or system) integration 171, 172-173, 188,I92, 196; city of 86
174 Strauss, David 70
society,as equivalent to the nation,67,81, structural-functionalism 22, 129,138, 158
86,92,123,166,184; as it 'is' 96; structure 73,94, 135, 139, 141, 144, 161, 170,
etymology of 39 fn.65; Gese//scha/1 25, 182; defined xii, 137; duality of 171: in
138; hometown society (Natur/iche relation to culture 51,52, 132fT.,142,
Gemeinschaflen) 57,72, 180; as organism 146-149; in relation to form 4; see also
96--99; of spectacle 146; as unitary 153 base-superstructure metaphor
sociology 5, 83,84, 86,94,114, 177,180; structuralism 107, 122, 145, 176
conservative 115, 122; liberal 122, 123fT. structuration 151-178 passim
236 Ndtipn Formation
subjective being,in relation to objective totality,concept ofxiv, 72,77
relations 7,46,68,7 l ff.,95,122, 126, 130, totems 2 fn.2,I I9 see also identity
133, 146,152,164,166,170,179,182,186, tourism 44,56; aristocratic grand tour 56
188, 189-190 Towards a Marxist Theory of Nationalism I08
subjectivity xiv,24,37,58, 75,78,80,81..,85, trade 20
112,122,126,139,141,143,161,165,166, tradition xiii, xiv, 22,36, 111,149,156,172,
167,168,170,176,180,188,189-195 175; as categorical formation 38,128;
passim; Cartesian xiii; decentring the 'great' and 'little' I 31, 142
subject 176; and experience ofliberation traditional society 96,97,139,141-142,144
from structures 134; and imagination 7; traditionalism 21,43,200
levelling of59,185; 'pure subjectivity' I 00; Train," George Francis 56
and subjectification ofreal 71, 124; and transnational corporations 36
'subjectivist culture' 95-96, 135-136 trave156--57,80,99-IOO
surveillance 34,156,160,162,169 treason 71
Sweden 110 treaties and declarations; Act ofUnion 115;
symbols and signs 2-4,18,36,62,91 American Declaration ofIndependence
Symmons-Symonolewicz,Konstantin 114 152; Declaration ofArbroath 116;
A System of National Time for Railways 56 Flanders Treaty 13; Lateran Treaty 62
Treitschke, Heinrich von 95
Tacitus,Cornelius 75 tribal society 2-4,5,6,21,24,26,42-43,75,
Tamils 15 114,130-132,135,139,167,172, 173,174,
tariffs 89 199; Aranda 2; Cree nation 15; Javanese 6;
taxation 153,159; fiscal reorganization 154 Kabyle 23; Miri 4 fn.6; Pintupi 2 fn.2,168;
technology 144, 158-159,165,187,194 Trobriand Islanders 2-3,6
teleology 91,111 fn.30,132,154,185 Turgenev, Ivan 67
territory and territoriality xiv, 12,13-14,26, Turkey 37
29,36,38,63,153,161,188; and Turnverein 52
boundaries,13,166,195
theology and the theological 68; as a uneven development 109,110,112, 143,
Comtean stage in history 77; 'God is dead' 144ff., 157,161,167,189
70 United Provinces ofCentral America 157
Theories of Nationa/i;m 129 United States ofAmerica 36,56,106;
theorizing; see intellectual practice Thirteen States in North America 157
Third World 35,105 unity; as description ofsocieties 170, 181;
Thompson,E.P. 107 sense of78,97,122
Thought and Change 132,135 universalism 10,55,68,74,76,100, 143,174;
Tilly,Charles 154 and particularism 128
time,category ofxiv,3,6,21,22,23, 35,36, universities; separation into nationes 9-10,
37,80,81,91,99,134,138,140,141,167, 11,30,45,114,192
170,171,174--176,185,187,192,194,200; upheaval (dislocation) 48,67, 70-72,75,81,
defined,13 fn.33; as disembodied 57; 95,111; 'storm and stress' 71,76; 'Things
homogenous empty (calendrical) 6,33,78, fall apart' 73; see also fragmentation and
187,195,200; Messianic (traditional) 6, dissolution
68,70,78,195; as relative,57-58; world
standard time 56; world time 13,37,157, Venezuela 157
I8 I,192; see also abstraction oftime and Verne, Jules 56,67
space Victoria von Saxe-Coburg-Gotha 63-64,74
Time 3-4 Vilar, Pierre 50
time-space distantiation 38,153,168,171, Village Communities 54
174--176,183 Vindication of Natural Society 43
Tocqueville,Alexis de 70,80,99 Vinyals, d'Abadal i de 15
Toffier,Alvin 146 violence, means of I58ff.,166; see also
Tokugawa Shogunate 65,156 military, war
Tolstoy,Lev 96,101 The Violence of Abstraction 73
T6nnies,Ferdinand 25,83,85,86,127 Virilio, Paul 33
Index 237
Vittorio Emmanuele II 61 Whitehead, Alfred 96
Volk; see people Wild Child of Aveyron 80
Vosges. region of 88 Wilhelm 160
Wilhelm II 60-61,64
Walker, Mack 57 fn.39, 72 Williams. Raymond 33. 104, 107, I 16-117,
Wallerstein,Immanuel 55 138
war xv, I, 71, 102,115,151, 153-154, 157, Wilson's Fourteen Points 12
158; Gulf War 35, 195; and Wimpfehng, Jacob 75
noncombatants 86; passions and Wolf, Eric 55
glorifications of 99-t00, 101, 195; world system 20. 56
professional soldiers 9, 26-27. 159; world systems theonsts 20, 55. 141
Vietnam War 107; War of American Wright, Patrick 117
Independence 157; World War 1 86,87,
JOO, 181; World War 11 2 Young Germany 52
Weber, Max xiii,42, 65,83-102 passim, 110, Yugoslavia I
127, 138, 149, 151. 152. 159. 165,169.172.
179, 180, 181. 182,194-195: ambiguous lizek, Slavoj xii
response to nation 88, 89,94-98 Zjidcrvcld, Anton 25, 135 fn.42
Webster, Noah 54 Zuba1da, Sam.i 113
Welsh IS: language 145
Wh;ic is .1 n.1tion and \\'hy ts 1ntio11.1lism \Yidespre.1d
in the \\'orld tHl\\·? This book .1rgm·s th.it despite till'
ab1111tL11Ke of \\'ricing 011 the ·n.1tion' a11d ·11.1tio11.11isn1 ••
they are t\\'o of the most misumkrstood .111d 1111dcr
..
thcorized concepts in the co11tc111por.ir� ,,orld.
.-
Moreou·r. the strong p.1ssio11s these conceph .m •list·
_ I, haw obstructed .1 better undnst,111d111g of them.
J.1111es argues th.it the nation is .111 .1bstr.Kt .ind C<>tltr.1-
TCS
SAGE
Publications
London
Thousand Oaks
New Delhi
m association
with
Theory,
Culture &
Society