0% found this document useful (0 votes)
196 views

Literary Criticism of Aristotle by Nasrullah Mambrol On May 1, 2017 - (0)

Aristotle disagreed with Plato's views on art and tragedy in several key ways: 1) He rejected Plato's view that art was useless, dangerous deception, arguing instead that art is natural, beneficial, and tied to morality/truth. 2) He argued mimesis in art is not mere mirroring of nature but involves idealizing, representing, and rendering concepts. 3) He defined tragedy's purpose as arousing emotions of pity and fear through depicting a change of fortune in a protagonist, which results in a catharsis or purification of emotions in the audience. The plot, not just character, is most important in tragedy.

Uploaded by

amnaarabi
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
196 views

Literary Criticism of Aristotle by Nasrullah Mambrol On May 1, 2017 - (0)

Aristotle disagreed with Plato's views on art and tragedy in several key ways: 1) He rejected Plato's view that art was useless, dangerous deception, arguing instead that art is natural, beneficial, and tied to morality/truth. 2) He argued mimesis in art is not mere mirroring of nature but involves idealizing, representing, and rendering concepts. 3) He defined tragedy's purpose as arousing emotions of pity and fear through depicting a change of fortune in a protagonist, which results in a catharsis or purification of emotions in the audience. The plot, not just character, is most important in tragedy.

Uploaded by

amnaarabi
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 7

Literary Criticism of Aristotle

By Nasrullah Mambrol on May 1, 2017 • ( 0 )


Aristotle (384-322 BC)

Disciple of Plato
Teacher of Alexander the Great.
Major Works: Poetics, Rhetoric
Poetics, incomplete, 26 chapters
Mainly concerned with tragedy, which was in his day, the most
development form of poetry.
Disagreeing with much else that Plato said, Aristotle agreed that art was
essentially Mimesis
But, he maintained, (good) art was neither useless nor dangerous, but
rather natural and beneficial.
Crucial to Aristotle’s defense of art is his

Rejection of Plato’s Dualism


Man is not an “embodied” intellect, longing for the spiritual release of
death, but rather an animal with, among all the other faculties, the
ability to use reason and to create

Rejection of Plato’s Rationalism


We must study humans as we would study other animals to discover
what their “nature” is. Look among the species; see who are the thriving
and successful and in what activities do they engage? For Aristotle, this
is how to determine what is and is not appropriate for a human and
human societies
Rejection that Mimesis= Mirroring Nature
Aristotle: Art is not useless

It is Natural:
It is natural for human beings to imitate
Any human society which is healthy will be a society where there is
imitative art
Nothing is more natural that for children to pretend
Art production and training is a necessary part of any education since it
uses and encourages the imaginative manipulation of ideas
Nothing is more natural than for human beings to create using their
imagination
Since art is imitation, it is an imaginative use of concepts; at its heart art
is “conceptual,” “intellectual”
maxresdefault

(1)Aristotle: good art is not dangerous

A) Art is not deceptive:


Artists must accurately portray psychological reality in order for
characters to be believable and their actions understandable
It teaches effectively and it teaches the truth
Convincing and powerful drama is convincing and powerful because it
reveals some truth of human nature
Introduces the concept of “Organic Unity” – the idea that in any good
work of art each of the parts must contribute to the overall success of
the whole
Just as in biological organisms each part contributes to the overall health
and wellbeing of the creature, so too in good works of art reflects or
imitates reality
Unified action, “with its several incidents so closely connected that the
transposal or withdrawal of any one of them will disjoin and dislocate
the whole”

B) Sensuous art is not a bad thing:


Aristotle did not believe that the mind was one thing and body was
something else and therefore Aristotle did not have the bias against
physical pleasure that Plato had
The only way of acquiring knowledge at all, according to Aristotle, was
through the senses and so developing, exercising and sharpening those
senses through art was a healthy thing to do
Art was not solely concerned with the sensual pleasures, but rather
was/should be an intellectual, conceptual affair.

C) (Good) Art is tied to Morality and Truth


(Successful Tragic) Drama always teaches morality. When trying to
understand how tragedies achieve their peculiar effect (Pathos), he
notes the psychology and morality on which they must be based
NB: Aristotle believe that drama imitated not only “evens” but actions.
As such they imitated intended behaviours, psychological forces and the
unseen “inner life” of persons
He unwittingly set up two functions for a work of art to fulfil; to imitate
nature’s perceptual detail and to imitate nature’s “organic unity.”
Aristotle agreed that art did stir up negative emotions but, he claims it
then purged these in harmless, healthy way. This led to the principle of
Catharsis

Doctrine of Catharsis

Art is neither psychologically destabilizing nor politically destructive


Art is a therapeutic part of the healthy life of not only the individual, but
of the nation

2)Aristotle: Mimesis is not equal to imitation

Mimesis is more like

Rendering
Depicting
Construing
Idealizing
Representing
Aristotle’s Critical Responses

Poetry is more Philosophical than History


“Poetry is sometimes more philosophic and of graver importance than
history (He means a mere chronicle of events here), since its statements
are of the nature rather of universals, whereas those of history are
singulars”
Poetry describes “not the thing that has happened” as Aristotle imagines
history does “but a kind of thing that might happen, (i.e, what is possible)
as being probable or necessary”
Thus history mere “mirrors,” but not art. Art is necessarily conceptual
/cognitive.
Aristotle-Park-1000x500-c-centerAristotle on Tragedy

In the Poetics, Aristotle compares tragedy to such other metrical forms


as comedy and epic. He determines that tragedy, like all poetry, is a kind
of imitation (mimesis), but adds that it has a serious purpose and uses
direct action rather than narrative to achieve its ends. He says that
poetic mimesis is imitation of things as they could be, not as they are —
for example, of universals and ideals — thus poetry is a more
philosophical and exalted medium than history, which merely records
what has actually happened.

The aim of tragedy, Aristotle writes, is to bring about a “catharsis” of the


spectators — to arouse in them sensations of pity and fear, and to purge
them of these emotions so that they leave the theater feeling cleansed
and uplifted, with a heightened understanding of the ways of gods and
men. This catharsis is brought about by witnessing some disastrous and
moving change in the fortunes of the drama’s protagonist (Aristotle
recognized that the change might not be disastrous, but felt this was the
kind shown in the best tragedies — Oedipus at Colonus, for example,
was considered a tragedy by the Greeks but does not have an unhappy
ending).

According to Aristotle, tragedy has six main elements: plot, character,


diction, thought, spectacle (scenic effect), and song (music), of which the
first two are primary. Most of the Poetics is devoted to analysis of the
scope and proper use of these elements, with illustrative examples
selected from many tragic dramas, especially those of Sophocles,
although Aeschylus, Euripides, and some playwrights whose works no
longer survive are also cited.

Several of Aristotle’s main points are of great value for an understanding


of Greek tragic drama. Particularly significant is his statement that the
plot is the most important element of tragedy:

Tragedy is an imitation, not of men, but of action and life, of happiness


and misery. And life consists of action, and its end is a mode of activity,
not a quality. Now character determines men’s qualities, but it is their
action that makes them happy or wretched. The purpose of action in the
tragedy, therefore, is not the representation of character: character
comes in as contributing to the action. Hence the incidents and the plot
are the end of the tragedy; and the end is the chief thing of all. Without
action there cannot be a tragedy; there may be one without
character. . . . The plot, then, is the first principle, and, as it were, the
soul of a tragedy: character holds the second place.

Aristotle goes on to discuss the structure of the ideal tragic plot and
spends several chapters on its requirements. He says that the plot must
be a complete whole — with a definite beginning, middle, and end —
and its length should be such that the spectators can comprehend
without difficulty both its separate parts and its overall unity. Moreover,
the plot requires a single central theme in which all the elements are
logically related to demonstrate the change in the protagonist’s fortunes,
with emphasis on the dramatic causation and probability of the events.

Aristotle has relatively less to say about the tragic hero because the
incidents of tragedy are often beyond the hero’s control or not closely
related to his personality. The plot is intended to illustrate matters of
cosmic rather than individual significance, and the protagonist is viewed
primarily as the character who experiences the changes that take place.
This stress placed by the Greek tragedians on the development of plot
and action at the expense of character, and their general lack of interest
in exploring psychological motivation, is one of the major differences
between ancient and modern drama.

Since the aim of a tragedy is to arouse pity and fear through an


alteration in the status of the central character, he must be a figure with
whom the audience can identify and whose fate can trigger these
emotions. Aristotle says that “pity is aroused by unmerited misfortune,
fear by the misfortune of a man like ourselves.”

In addition, the hero should not offend the moral sensibilities of the
spectators, and as a character he must be true to type, true to life, and
consistent.

The hero’s error or frailty (harmartia) is often misleadingly explained as


his “tragic flaw,” in the sense of that personal quality which inevitably
causes his downfall or subjects him to retribution. However,
overemphasis on a search for the decisive flaw in the protagonist as the
key factor for understanding the tragedy can lead to superficial or false
interpretations. It gives more attention to personality than the
dramatists intended and ignores the broader philosophical implications
of the typical plot’s denouement. It is true that the hero frequently takes
a step that initiates the events of the tragedy and, owing to his own
ignorance or poor judgment, acts in such a way as to bring about his
own downfall. In a more sophisticated philosophical sense though, the
hero’s fate, despite its immediate cause in his finite act, comes about
because of the nature of the cosmic moral order and the role played by
chance or destiny in human affairs. Unless the conclusions of most
tragedies are interpreted on this level, the reader is forced to credit the
Greeks with the most primitive of moral systems.

It is worth noting that some scholars believe the “flaw” was intended by
Aristotle as a necessary corollary of his requirement that the hero should
not be a completely admirable man. Harmartia would thus be the factor
that delimits the protagonist’s imperfection and keeps him on a human
plane, making it possible for the audience to sympathize with him. This
view tends to give the “flaw” an ethical definition but relates it only to
the spectators’ reactions to the hero and does not increase its
importance for interpreting the tragedies.

The remainder of the Poetics is given over to examination of the other


elements of tragedy and to discussion of various techniques, devices,
and stylistic principles. Aristotle mentions two features of the plot, both
of which are related to the concept of harmartia, as crucial components
of any well-made tragedy. These are “reversal” (peripeteia), where the
opposite of what was planned or hoped for by the protagonist takes
place, as when Oedipus’ investigation of the murder of Laius leads to a
catastrophic and unexpected conclusion; and “recognition” (anagnorisis),
the point when the protagonist recognizes the truth of a situation,
discovers another character’s identity, or comes to a realization about
himself. This sudden acquisition of knowledge or insight by the hero
arouses the desired intense emotional reaction in the spectators, as
when Oedipus finds out his true parentage and realizes what crimes he
has been responsible for.

Aristotle wrote the Poetics nearly a century after the greatest Greek
tragedians had already died, in a period when there had been radical
transformations in nearly all aspects of Athenian society and culture. The
tragic drama of his day was not the same as that of the fifth century, and
to a certain extent his work must be construed as a historical study of a
genre that no longer existed rather than as a description of a living art
form.

In the Poetics, Aristotle used the same analytical methods that he had
successfully applied in studies of politics, ethics, and the natural sciences
in order to determine tragedy’s fundamental principles of composition
and content. This approach is not completely suited to a literary study
and is sometimes too artificial or formula-prone in its conclusions.

Nonetheless, the Poetics is the only critical study of Greek drama to have
been made by a near-contemporary. It contains much valuable
information about the origins, methods, and purposes of tragedy, and to
a degree shows us how the Greeks themselves reacted to their theater.
In addition, Aristotle’s work had an overwhelming influence on the
development of drama long after it was compiled. The ideas and
principles of the Poetics are reflected in the drama of the Roman Empire
and dominated the composition of tragedy in western Europe during the
seventeenth, eighteenth, and nineteenth centuries.

You might also like