0% found this document useful (0 votes)
362 views

Sartre and Ryle On The Imagination by Paul Ricoeur

Sartre and Ryle on the Imagination by Paul Ricoeur

Uploaded by

monti9271564
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
362 views

Sartre and Ryle On The Imagination by Paul Ricoeur

Sartre and Ryle on the Imagination by Paul Ricoeur

Uploaded by

monti9271564
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 8
THE LIBRARY OF LIVING PHILOSOPHERS VOLUME XVI THE PHILOSOPHY OF JEAN-PAUL SARTRE EDITED BY PAUL ARTHUR SCHILPP SOUTHERN ILLINOIS UNIVERSITY—CARBONDALE, LA SALLE, ILLINOIS ¢ OPEN COURT « ESTABLISHED 1885 Paul Ricoeur SARTRE AND RYLE ON THE IMAGINATION R. Bradley DeFord, Translator T is not casy to draw out all the consequences of the decisive distinc tion introduced by Kant between productive and reproductive imagina- tion. Philosophy of the imagination has a preference for images that can be regarded as mental or physical replicas (photographs, pictures, drawings, fiagrams) of an absent thing. Thus it tends to neglect heuristic fictions in a icologics and utopias). In a gencral way, micient as well as classical and modern—fails to account agination in terms that do not reduce it to “reproduc- imagination. The claim of the fiction-image, over against the picture~ litficult to maintain throughout. Sartre and Ryle are taken here as representatives of certain tentative modern philosophers who recognize the irreducibility of the image of the art of imagining, but who nevertheless fail to liberate the image from its bondage to the model or original of which it would be the picture or rep- lica. The choice of these two men is, however, motivated more particularly ilosophy of but in terms of theory as well. In fact ties than differences, and among their ir common unwillingness to deviate from ‘the paradigm of reproductive imagination. In that sense, I see them as two modern thinkers who reinforee the primacy of the original in spite of their efforts to acknowledge the specificity of the imagination. But because the specificity they acknowledge is defined by difference from straight seeing or the second of three , Penasyvania. The ‘ously been published.‘much time on the difference of method between these assume that a linguistic analysis, which ‘our statements about experience, cannot st facts without putting what we say under critique of language ressure of experience is well supported by counterexamples which play a role similar to that of Husser!’s tive variations.” On the other hand, | assume that a phenomenology, claims to start with lived experience, never seeks merely to re experience, but inquires into its structures on the basis of ight links essences to examples in @ way that differs from the inductive linkage between laws and facts. Furthermore, the “reduc tion” of the pseudo-evidence of the given as already there and already (ed compels us to articulate the complex meanings which appear to between the theory of essential intuition mm of meaning leads us to say that A speakability of lived mn is the factor common to this is way I do not want to em- 1 oUF puFpOse. phenomenolo; experience. U guistic analysis and phi phasize a difference « SARTRE Let me say at the outset that in focusing on the two volumes that Sartre devotes specifically to the subject of the imagination—Imagination: A Psy- ‘chological Critique and The Psychology of Imagination=-1 am not claiming that these two works express his complete thought on the subject. In order juld have to take into account ism, bis monographs framework of this context. A principal decision is made at the begi chological Critique. That decision concerns a paradig will never be dislodged from its prominent position. The duce an image of my friend Peter, who dwells in Berlin. This choice of ‘examples, as we shall see, is not without consequences. It imposes from the very outset the paradigm of absence. Later on, the case of non-existent entities will introduce no dramatic change in this description. i IE IMAGINATION 169 can be explail . The best way solve the fallacy of immanence is to address on whose referent exists elsewhere. same Peter may be the theory of the image. On the contrary, reinforced by all the arguments that underscore the difference between a mental image and 2 perceived object. Let us recall the arguments: The sal the sense of a simuilacrum endowed with lesser thing, possessed ots own existence, given to consciousness like any ther thing, a taining external relations to the thing of w is the image” (5).* Sartre that the principal metaphysical systems (Des- cartes, Leibaiz, and Hume) all share the projudice of “metaphysical iden- tification” between image and porception, Even more modern psychol- ‘ogies, such as those influenced by Bergson and the Wartzburg school of in psychology, only make the image more fluid but no less a thing. “The image remains in the guise of an inert element” (77). Philoso- phers and psychologists, equally deceived by the fallacy of immanence and its corollary, the substa Wf AEE con inguish between essen- is spontaneity-consciousness, pertainin, ie of having image, which supports and grounds the difference between image and 1. The self-transparency accompanying this spontaneity-consciousness “That there arc only two types of existence, as ig-in-the-world and as consciousness, is an ontological law” (116). * The parenheialy placed muters in this section refer to pages nation: A Psychological Crit Pt170 PAUL RICOEUR ‘The paradox is that this polemic does not shake the privilege of the original in the slightest. On the contrary, it reasserts that privilege. As Hus- sett tells us, to have an image isto be intentionally directed toward some- thing, In the example of the flute-playing centaur discussed by Husser] in Ideas I, the centaur as such (that is, as represented) is not a psychic state: it exists nowhere; nevertheless, it is not the invention itself. This example from fiction compels us to consider the. problem of fiction in terms of @ transcendent n But what about the object of the image of Sartre's friend Peter? Here is a real object that is the same for perception as for imagination. Image and perception aim in two different ways at the exis Peter. Shall we say that the image nevertheless has an object (Peter image”), in the same way that the invention of the centaur has the repre- sented centaur as its object? Then there are two objects, and we unwit- tingly re-establish the inert content which we have denounced and at the same time deny our initial tater tthe image was only a relation, 2 mode of givenness. It seems, therefore, that the referent of the fiction and the referent of the picture cannot be treated within the same framework. Husserl’s centaur is not an image of an existing object, as Sartre's image of Peter is." But in Imagination itis uncritically assumed that the theory of the picture may be extended to that of the fiction, and vice versa. That is why Sartre's concluding statement remains ambiguous: “An image can enter into consciousness only if itis @ syathesis, not an element. ‘There are not, and never could be, imagesin consciousness. Rather, image isa certain type of consciousness. An image is an act, not some thing, An image is a eon- sciousness of some thing” (146). But which some thing? ‘The real Peter, or ‘a mental appearance. as the object of the act? The Psychology of Imagination* provides partial answers to. this paradox of the object of the picture-image and, in the process, further rein- forces the strategic position of the original of the picture. The reinforce- ‘ment begins with the assertion that the first characteristic of the image is, that the image is a “consciousness.” It is for reflective consciousness that the image appears as an object. For direct intentional consciousness, the object is Peter-out-there. It is that Peter who appears in the form of an image. It only when T reflect and try to describe the image as an image (that is, by an act of the second degree) that Lform the judgment: [have an image. This having been acknowledged, we must reassert that the same chair, at one time perceived and at another time imagined, exists out there: “Whether I see or imagine that chair, the object of my perception and that + The pareabetcal placed numbers inthis section sles to pages i Sastre, The Foy Ina tr. by Bernard Frechtman (2 1966) 5. SARTRE AND RYLE ON THE IMAGINATION m of my image are iden is that chair of straw on which I am seated Only consciousness is related in two different ways to the same chair” (7). ‘The ouly correct way of speaking of the absent friend Peter would be to speak of “the imaginal consciousness of Peter” (7), Thus itis the object of perception which gives an object to the picture. The key position of the original is again reinforced by the second characteristic of the image, that of its being not observed, but quasi- observed. To observe is to learn endlessly from the inexhaustible richness of the perceived thing. By “nothing can be learned from an image that is not already known" (11). Quasi-observation “is an observation which teaches nothing” (12). We move in “a world in which nothing hap- pens” (13) Buti not this poverty of the image a feature of the image of the absent, which is not applicable to fiction? 1s not this poverty the counterpart of the richness of the original? We shall see that fiction does not share this pov- erty of the image of an absent object, but rather produces new meaning capable of generating a metamorphosis of reality. ‘The denial of the specificity of fiction is made complete with the third characteristic of the image: its character of nothingness. This character, which is proper to the positional act of imagining as it appears for a reflec. five, non-thetic consciousness, blurs all the important contrasts between ind picture. Sartre asserts that “this [imaginal] act can assume four and no more: it ean posit the object as non-existent, or as absent, o ing elsewhere; it can also neutralize itself, that is, not posit its object as existing” (15). This lst allows Sartre to generalize the negative character of the positional act of absence to the point of non-existence. But the four forms of the list are not homogeneous. Absence and presence are sub- classes of reality, as the example of Peter shows: the same Petex is the object of both the perception and the image. Howes uunreality is opposed both to absence and to preseuce as reality. Therefore, @ theory of absence cannot be extended to a theory of unreality. This logi- cal error excludes from the discussion the case of fiction on its own terms, Consequently, the fourth characteristic, that of spontaneity, is applied indiscriminately to both picture and fiction, since it becomes merely the counterpart to the fact that the object occurs as a nothingness. Can we say, however, that when consciousness invents it is ereative in the same way as when it produces the image of an absent thing or person? In the one case it creates its object, the ihe other, it seems to me, it creates only the mode of givenness, and this creation is only for the non-thetic reflective consciousness. Does the next chapter of this work open the description to the specific traits of fiction? Apparently not. Is inquiry into the image-family is di-in PAUL RICOBUR rected toward a problem that concerns only the relation between two kinds of pictures, the physical picture and the mental picture—not the relation, -¢ and fiction. Both Kinds of pictures make an object present h cases the problem that absorbs that of the role of the analogue. This problem, once ag ‘to an original, whose analogue is a likeness. In the case of a purely meatal image, the search for the analogical representative of the aimed-at object is and to my mind very fhrough caricatures, impersonifications, schematic drawings, to interpretation of spots, shapes, ctc., and hypnagogic images, the material analogue disappears step by st imate to form the “ hypothesis that now ocular movements and feelings exert the same function (as regards the morphic function of the intentional attitude) as the physical support of the portrait. as genial as this description may be, it reinforces the privilege of the original by its very aitempt—which is, to my mind, successf gencralize on the concept of the analogue from the physical picture to the ture. The picture-family has found its homogeneity, perhaps, at paradigm. This is this remarkable of consciousness absent person appe: if lly to possess the absent. This desire turns into produce the object of one’s thought, the thing ‘one can take possession of it” (159). Desire wants to “obtain” things, even to “reproduce their integral existence” (159): "The object is reproduced for no other purpose than to arouse feel ing” (182). (One will have noticed the insistence on reproduction in this context of self-deception.) 5. SARTRE AND RYLE ON THE IMAGINATION 173 on the role of absence. It evoke a more Jess compulsive reactions ary objects to the act of Sis not die if o asi To wo erent . Further, Sates dcsson of lsc sonmaotance se, that the spontaneiy of consciousness and the experience o oe ascribed fo the same phenomenon, masterfully Sescbed we spellbourd rant or fatality 238), That exp most general and fun- mental assertions concerning the hentity between onee “the possiblity of posting sn hypothesis of unweaiy” vse 104 theoty of ction And id requisite if conscious posit the worl situation for image” (239-40). But this nthe problematic of n between fiction on-existence of fiction’s object, Phenomenology of fetion would have to turn ts bal magical for the sake of a Rye Tam not interested in the obvious epistemolo; Je and Sartre. Declai jose of Sartre the capacity of consciousness to neg world of reality and the correlation between freedom and the nothingness of our images are ‘able on the part of Ryle. Even the idea that the philosopher structure of imagination is foreign to in Concept of Mind, prefers to start m of the sorts of behavior that we should il ive (256).* Divergence is ‘Sartre concerning the consis- tency of the field covered by the word “image. divergent sorts” of behavior, Ry section refer to pages in Gilbert Rye Concept of Mind (New York: Barnes & Noble, 1949).am PAUL RICOEUR of aromance, their imaginat ‘witness, the colleague giving his opinion on reader, the nurse who refrains from adm human noises, the drama critic and the 0 specificity of fictions among the “divergent sorts of behavior. important fraction of the quoted examples obviously belong t0 this st class? But paradoxically enough, the initial discrepancy between Ryle and Sartre is offset by a convergence in their polemical concerns, which leads ‘Ryle to pick as a paradigmatic case for his plea the same kind of example as Sartre. emphasized, that ‘age of something. Furthermore, the concept of “pretending” which provides Ryle's key for solving—or issolving—the apparent paradox displayed by the mental image rein- forces the primacy of the original as much as does Sartre's concept of ation” of the absent friend ig the polemical concern of Concept of Mind to impose on , namely imagining that we see” ie commonly describe as ‘having a mental picture of Helvellyn’ or “having Helvellyn before the mind's eye” —which suggests most strongly “the notion that a mind is a ‘place,’ “where mental pictures are seen and reproductions of voices and tunes are heard” (256). As the reader will readily observe, this special case of imag- ining does not represent the whole list of “widely divergent sorts," but it does shift the emphasis from productive imagination to reproductive imag- ination. At this point the kinship between Ryle and Sartre begins. “Having Helvellyn before the mind's eye” is like reproducing an image of our friend Peter from Berlin, In fac, this startling convergence in the choice of exam~ ples proceeds from a common polemical concern, Both writers fight against tnisconstructions, misdescriptions, and misconceptions, and both claim to provide a new, more accurate account of what is actually experienced, This prok ity legitimates my contention that, beyond their theoretical ivergences, linguistic analysts and phenomenologists have a great deal in common in their practice of description. Both would amend fallacious de- ‘scription by looking more closely at experience on the basis of well-chosen. examples. "The fallacious description that Ryle and Sartre want to dismantle is much the same, namely, the description of images 2s entities existing ‘mind, which is itself conceived as the asylum o theatre where these ‘occur. While Sartre invokes the transparency and the sponta 5. SARTRE AND RYLE ON THE IMAGINATION 175 sciousness, Ryle would list among meaningless statements about the mind all of Sartre's assertions about consciousness. But this radical divergence at the level of fundamental assumptions concerning the mind or conscious ness does not prevent ther from attacking the same descriptions as falla- cious and from drawing the same conclusion: “To see is one thing; to pic- ture or visualize is another” (246) Secondly, the analysis of “pretending,” which Ryle elaborates for itself before applying it to the apparent paradox of the image as something seen in the mind's eye, has the same consequence as Sartre's theory of quasi- observation with respect to the priviloge of the original in the theory of the image as picture. The analysis of “pretending” is introduced by arguments ien to Sartre's phenomenology. Sartre would not say that to see in ind's eye is to seem to see, because for him to deny that images exist in the mind does not imply that they appear before us. Quasi-observation is a kind of observation. Here phenomenology would help us in distinguish- ing between existing and appearing. Neither would Sartre say that the ‘wrong description is induced by the existence of physical pictures bearing, For him, visible pictures are not posited as real but as analogues, which are the neutralized bearers of an rough and beyond the physical thing, Therefore Sartre ure” (Ryle, p. 247), since for him (accordins sis) the analogue of the 'ing appears as the corre through a hyletic analogue of the hyletic analogue h: is. I would say that and of pretending) impose the reference of the picture to an original as the main structure of the mental image. Ryle’s frame of reference the analysis of pretending is, of “0 logical analysis. It is a transposition into the sphere of doing of a Similar structure from the sphere of talking. When we quote a statement, assume an assertion, and in all similar cases of ovatio obliqua, we are doing, something more complex than merely asserting. We must first understand176 PAUL RICOEUR what it is to assert, then we must qualify it in two ways, namely as not asserting and as quasi-asserting. In the same way, such acts as cheating, playing a part, forging @ signature, and playing bears, whether or not they constitute deliberate simulation or dissi performances ‘with a certain sort of complex description” (260). We must be able to de- seribe some action directly in order to make sense of the complex descrip- ng a main clause (such as “X fights”) plus a subordinate clause be analyzed as a non- performance and The main advantage of this account of pretending is sets up f pretending for a treat ncied perce; by which we listen and follow and do something that can be eared. As Ryle the real difference is not between mock action and mock perception, but between performance and as-if performance. ing Helvellyn is realizing how Helvellyn would look. An something which stands in the same relation to seeing Helvel ticated performances stand to those more naive performances, whose men- tion is obliquely contained in the de mn of the higher order perfor- ances” (266). Thave no objection to this analysis of the logic of “pretending” as such, 1 take it for granted. My only reservations would be these: On the one hand, I doubt that “seeing in the mind’s eye” can be construed, without “playing at..." ited reasons pertaining to the specific mode of appearance mncier whether the logic of the hypo- logy of nothingness and of likeness ‘as partially developed by Sartre. The grammar of oratio obliqua shows the trace in language of an oper: at iraplies our capacity to deny reality and to invent something of the real, cither in the form of a picture or in the form of fiction. is point, we could make many objections to Ryle from the phenomenology. These reservations, however, are not my main concern, which is the import of this analysis of “pretend- ing” for our discussion about pictures and fictions. ‘The parallel between Sartre’s analysis of quasi-observation and Ryle’s analysis of “pretending” resides in their common trait of indirect reference to an original situation, is in one case quasi-observed and in the 5. SARTRE AND RYLE ON THE IMAGINATION 47 other ease quasi-performed. In other words, Ryle's oblique mention of a naive performance in a mock-performance posits the same kind of depe: dence on an original as does Sartre’s present image.” In both cases an original precedes—

You might also like