Normative Structures in IP
Normative Structures in IP
Chapter 1
O ver the past decade the structure of world politics has undergone a
number of substantial changes. For the past half-century we have lived in
an international system dominated by the bipolar rivalry between the
United States and the Soviet Union. Although the Cold War system has
dissolved as quickly as it emerged, it is still not clear what kind of interna-
tional structure will take its place. For example, scholars have debated
whether the world is moving toward multipolarity with the rise of Eu-
rope, Japan, and perhaps China, or whether American dominance is still
sufficient to define the international system as unipolar.1 But while these
analysts have been charting trends in relative power to predict the emer-
gence of new rivalries, others have begun to consider the construction of
an entirely different kind of systemic structure. Departing from prevailing
conceptions of the international system, these scholars have suggested
that state leaders’ understandings of their international environment may
constitute an international structure that is as influential as the measures
of relative power that are traditionally viewed as giving shape to world
politics.
1
John Mearsheimer (1990, 2001) typifies this kind of analysis in his discussion of the
history of Great Power politics as well as international security following the end of the
Cold War.
2 CHAPTER 1
ing.2 At its core, however, the “realist” approach to world politics asserts
that two central realities permeate every aspect of world politics.3 First,
the constant environment in which all of international politics takes place
is one of anarchy. That is, no power stands above that of the nation-state.
Second, the only variable that can shape this environment significantly is
the relative distribution of power among the states in the system. Specifi-
cally, the prevalence of conflict and the ease of achieving cooperation
may vary depending on whether one, two, or three or more states domi-
nate the system. This approach tends to see conflict as a pervasive aspect
of world politics, and argues that the only possible constraint on the
outbreak of violence is a countervailing threat of violence. Through the
maintenance of this so-called balance of power, violence can often be
avoided, but these intermissions between disputes are not what one
would normally consider a “peace.” Finally, realists assert that interna-
tional agreement, institutions, and the like are of no consequence in re-
ducing international conflict. What counts are the interests of states and
their ability to achieve and maintain them by force.
The realist vision of the international system as rooted exclusively in
power and national interests has had a profound influence on the devel-
opment of theories of foreign policy behavior over the past several de-
cades. Perhaps the single most prominent and popular theoretical ap-
proach to foreign policy to emerge during this period has been the
rational theory of deterrence.4 Although scholars have produced many
specific variants of deterrence theory, all of these arguments share several
presumptions. Once again, deterrence theorists view conflict as a perva-
sive aspect of international politics. In addition, they argue that the best
way for a state to prevent its enemies from starting a conflict or seizing its
valued assets is to threaten to inflict such damage on them that they
prefer complying with their opponent’s wishes to risking a conflict. Spe-
cifically, theories of deterrence present two necessary and sufficient condi-
tions for preventing enemies from initiating a conflict: (1) demonstrate a
capability to inflict severe damage on one’s opponent; and (2) demon-
strate a willingness to use this capability if its opponent does not comply.
2
For a critique of the realist paradigm as either theoretically incoherent or manifestly
false, see Legro and Moravcsik (1999).
3
The list of major realist works is a very long one, but some of the most prominent and
representative of this approach are Carr (1946) and Morgenthau (1985). Perhaps the cen-
tral realist work in this regard is Waltz (1979). A more recent statement of the realist
perspective on world politics can be found in Mearsheimer (2001).
4
Again, the list of prominent realist works on deterrence is extremely long, but some of
the more significant ones are Schelling (1960, 1966); Russett (1967); Mearsheimer (1983);
and Huth (1988).
N O R M AT I V E S T R U C T U R E S 3
4 CHAPTER 1
the reexamination of Wilsonian ideas concerning the rule of law and in-
ternational security. Citing a wide range of events occurring during the
early 1990s that he believed to be incompatible with traditional realism,
Kegley suggests that “the time has arrived to revise and reconstruct clas-
sical realism, and build a refashioned paradigm inspired by Wilsonian
idealism.” (Kegley 1993, 143) Over the past several years, a number of
scholars have begun to answer this challenge. In response to the ideolog-
ical collapse of the Cold War, scholars such as Alex Wendt, Martha Fin-
nemore, Kathryn Sikkink, and many other have begun to theorize about
an international system in which ideas are as influential as material capa-
bilities (Wendt 1992, 1999; Klotz 1995; Katzenstein 1996; Finnemore
1996; Keck and Sikkink 1998).
N O R M AT I V E S T R U C T U R E S 5
dent causal impact of their own.9 These revisionists note that a variety of
different normative structures may operate within any given power struc-
ture.10 Thus norms must develop in a manner that is in some ways inde-
pendent of power and interests. If norms are not entirely determined by
power and interests, then these ideas may have an independent influence
on state behavior.
We must also recognize that the construction of a normative frame-
work for world politics should not eliminate international conflict any
more than the passage of a law should eliminate crime. Nor would such a
framework imply that military power will become irrelevant to state be-
havior. Rather we should expect the development of commonly under-
stood norms to help international policy makers take incremental steps
toward reducing the incidence of violent conflict and stabilizing peaceful
relationships. Conflicts should become less frequent as states’ expecta-
tions about their relations converge, and the conflicts that do emerge
should be more easily resolved in compliance with the accepted norma-
tive standards. Specifically, as I will discuss in chapter 3, we should expect
the accession to behavioral norms to ease the enforcement of these stan-
dards for at least two reasons. First, norms define which acts are illegiti-
mate and demand punishment by other states. Second, punishments
should be more likely to result in compliance because the trespassers rec-
ognize the standards of behavior that they have violated as legitimate. In
this manner, norms can help states to reestablish cooperative relations
and minimize the long-term effects of disputes.
6 CHAPTER 1
11
The most prominent works in this area concern the construction of what are known as
international regimes. See, for example, Krasner (1983) and Keohane (1984). I will elabo-
rate further on my discussion of international regimes in chapter 2. Other more recent work
has focused more explicitly on the development of international norms. See, for example,
Keck and Sikkink (1998) and Klotz (1995). In general this work also has not focused on
security affairs. Some exceptions are Price and Tannenwald (1996); Price (1995); Legro
(1995); and Tannenwald (1999). A partial exception is Finnemore (1996).
N O R M AT I V E S T R U C T U R E S 7
Second, empirical support for the role of security norms would remind
international relations theorists that we must not restrict our attention
to conventional realist hypotheses concerning power, interests, and re-
sources. Moreover, it would specifically suggest that we must give more
careful consideration to the independent role that ideas may play in the
conduct of world politics. Finally, the finding that norms can affect the
resolution of security conflict would provide some encouragement for
those who hope to build more elaborate security structures based on
common normative standards of behavior.
I will test the proposition that norms affect the resolution of security-
related disputes against the central competing realist paradigm for under-
standing military conflict: rational coercion theory.12 This is perhaps the
most appropriate competing explanation to consider in my analysis be-
cause of its powerful influence as a vision of foreign policy making
throughout the Cold War. Moreover, it exemplifies the realist, power-
based notions of international relations that deny any independent role
for ideas in shaping foreign policy. Briefly, my findings indicate that these
settlements do shape state leaders’ responses to crisis-bargaining behavior
in ways that cannot be explained by a purely realist framework. These
results indicate that international security norms can and have helped to
stabilize peace and cooperation, even between states that represent sub-
stantial security risks to one another. At the same time, however, tradi-
tionally realist variables—such as coercion and reputation for toughness—
are central to my explanation of crisis outcomes. Thus my argument
represents an important step toward integrating normative approaches
with the prevailing—yet incomplete—realist approach to crisis bargain-
ing.
My analysis proceeds as follows. In chapter 2 I will review the norma-
tive and realist literatures that relate most directly to my investigation of
norms in security conflicts. In doing so, I hope to place my research in its
proper perspective and define more precisely its contribution to our un-
derstanding of security policy. I will also outline some of the various
theoretical and methodological pitfalls involved in the study of norms
that I hope to circumvent in this work. In chapter 3 I will carefully out-
line normative and realist theoretical frameworks. Following the discus-
sion of each theoretical model, I will develop specific testable hypotheses
from each approach concerning militarized conflict behavior. In chapter
4 I will turn my attention to constructing a research design for testing
12
As I will discuss and demonstrate in chapter 3, rational theories of deterrence and
coercion are, in fact, identical in every significant respect. Their only difference is in the
specific task to which deterrent and coercive threats are put. Deterrence concerns the pre-
vention of an action before it begins, while coercion concerns the reversal of an action that
has already been taken. I choose to phrase my discussion in terms of a theory of coercion
because it is more appropriate to the bargaining behavior that I will examine.
8 CHAPTER 1