This document defines and distinguishes between human acts and acts of man. A human act proceeds from deliberate free will and has three essential constituents: knowledge, freedom, and voluntariness. For an act to be morally good, it must be good in its object, end, and circumstances. The object, end, and circumstances can each determine an act's morality. While an intrinsically evil object can never be made good, circumstances and ends can affect acts that are intrinsically indifferent or good.
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PPTX, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0 ratings0% found this document useful (0 votes)
264 views
Human Act
This document defines and distinguishes between human acts and acts of man. A human act proceeds from deliberate free will and has three essential constituents: knowledge, freedom, and voluntariness. For an act to be morally good, it must be good in its object, end, and circumstances. The object, end, and circumstances can each determine an act's morality. While an intrinsically evil object can never be made good, circumstances and ends can affect acts that are intrinsically indifferent or good.
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PPTX, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 55
Human Act
A human act is an act
which proceeds from the deliberate free will of man. In a wide sense, the term human act means any sort of activity , internal or external, bodily or spiritual, performed by a human being. Ethics, however, employs the term in a stricter sense, and call human only those acts that are proper to man as man. Now man is an animal and he has many activities in common with brutes. But man is more than animal; he is rational, that is to say, he has understanding and free will. Hence it is only the act that proceeds from the knowing and freely willing human being that has the full character of a human act. Such an act alone is proper to man as man. And therefore ethics understand by human acts only those acts that proceed from a deliberate and freely willing human being. Acts of Man Man’s animal acts of sensation (i.e., use of the senses and appetition) (i.e., bodily tendencies), as well as acts that man performs indeliberately or without advertence and the exercise of free choice are called acts of man. Thus, such acts as are effected in sleep, in delirium, in the state of unconsciousness; acts done abstractedly or with complete inadvertence; acts performed in infancy; acts due to infirmity of mind or the weakness of senility—all these are acts of man, but they are not human acts. Acts of Man Human Act It is to be noticed that acts which are in themselves acts of man may sometimes become human act by the advertence and consent of the human agent Example: If I hear words of blasphemy as I walk along the street, my act of hearing is an acts of man; but the act becomes a human act if I deliberately pay attention and listen Example: My eyes may fall upon an indecent sight or upon a page of obscene reading matter. The act of seeing and even of reading and understanding the words, is an act of man; but it becomes a human act the moment I deliberately consent to look or to read. Constituents of Human Act In order that an act be human, it must possess three essential qualities: it must be knowing , free and voluntary. Hence we list the essential elements, or constituents of the human act: A. Knowledge For the purposes of Ethics, deliberation means knowledge. Now, a human act is by definition a deliberate act; that is, it is a knowing act. No human act is possible without knowledge. A human act proceeds from the deliberate will: it requires deliberation. Now deliberation does not mean quiet, slow, painstaking action. It means merely advertence or knowledge in intellect of what one is about and what this means. An act may be done in the twinkling of an eye, and still be deliberate. For example: A hunter flushes game; the birds rise; the hunter whips up his gun and fires. The act of firing is the work of a whips up his gun and fires. The act of firing is the work of a split second and it is a deliberate act. The hunter adverts to what he is doing, and so adverting, wills and does it. In a word , the hunter know what he is doing. His knowledge makes the act deliberate. The will cannot act in the dark, for the will is a blind faculty in itself. It cannot choose unless it see to choose and the light , the power to see, is afforded by intellectual knowledge Example: • I cannot choose to eat oranges or not to eat oranges , if I have never seen nor heard of oranges. • I cannot will to love and serve God if I do not know God. B. Freedom A human act is an act determined by the will and by nothing else. It is an act, therefore, that is under control of the will, an act that the will can do or leave undone. Such an act is called a free act. Thus every human act must be free. In other words, freedom is an essential element of the human act. C. Voluntariness The Latin word for will is voluntas and from this word we derive the English terms, voluntary and voluntariness. To say, therefore, that a human act must be voluntary or must have voluntariness, is simply to say that it must be a will-act. Voluntariness is the formal essential quality of the human act, and for it to be present, there must ordinarily be both knowledge and freedom in the agent. Hence, the term voluntary act is synonymous with human act. Example: A Catholic is aware that today is Sunday and that he has the obligation of hearing Mass (knowledge). He is free to attend Mass or to stay away—not , indeed, free from duty in the matter, but physically free to perform the duty or leave it unperformed (freedom). He wills to do his duty and to hear Mass (voluntariness). Determinants of Morality A human act, to be morally good act, must be found in agreement with the Norm of morality on all three points, i.e. it must be good in itself or objectly, in its end and in its circumstances “Bonum ex integra causa, malum ex quocumque defectu.” A thing to be good must be entirely good; it is vitiated by any defect.
Example: Analogy of the Body
A. Object - the act itself - by the object is meant the human act performed , the deed done -If an act as object is good or evil, it has objective morality If an act, considered abstractly, is indifferent (i.e. neither good nor bad), its morality is determined by the end for which it is performed and by the circumstances which affect it. Certain actions are in themselves, or objectively good and certain others are objectively evil : and this morality is intrinsic, i.e. resides in the act independently of positive law prescribing or forbidding the act. The object is the primary determinant of morality. If the object be evil, our quest end there, the act is definitely evil and forbidden; nothing can make it good. But if the act is good as an object, it may still be vitiated by its circumstances, particularly by that circumstance called “the end of the agent.” Hence, if we find an act good in itself as an object, we have still to look to the end of the agent and to the other circumstances before pronouncing permissible as an individual act. B. The End - it is the end in which the agent intends or wishes to achieve by his act. - It is the end he has in view , his purpose, his motive in performing the act. How far does the influence of the end of the agent extend? 1. An objectively good act performed for a good purpose takes on a new goodness from the good end; and if it have several good ends, it takes on a new goodness from each. 2. An objectively evil act performed for an evil purpose takes on a new malice or evil from the evil end; and if it have several evil ends, it takes on a new malice from each. 3. An act which is objectively good, but done for an evil end, is entirely evil if the evil end is the whole motive of the act; likewise the act is entirely evil if the evil end is gravely evil even though it is not the whole motive of the act; but the act is only partially evil if the evil end is neither gravely evil nor the whole motive of the act. 4. An objectively evil act can never become good by the reason of a good end. 5. An act which is indifferent objectively becomes good if done for a good end and evil if done for an evil end. C. Circumstances -are conditions that affect an act and may affect it morally although thy do not belong to the essence of the act as such. In other words circumstances are conditions without which the act could exist, but which happen to affect or qualify it in its concrete performance. Kinds of Circumstances 1. Who? Circumstances of person Who is the agent? To whom is the action is done? 2. What? Circumstances of quantity or quality of the object
What is the extent of the act?
Was the injury inflicted serious or slight? Was the amount stolen large or small 3. Where? Circumstance of place
Where did the act commit?
4. In what condition? How? Circumstance of manner
• Was the agent in good faith or bad?
• Was the agent’s evil disposition intensely malicious or only slightly so? 5. When? Circumstances of time - How long did the agent retain an evil thought or intention for a long period or momentarily? The ethical principles involved in the matter of circumstances as determinants of morality are the following: 1. An indifferent act becomes good or evil by reason of its circumstances. 2. A good act may become evil by reason of circumstances. 3. A good or evil act may become better or worse by reason of circumstances, and may even take on specifically new goodness or malice from its circumstances. 4. An evil act can never be made good by circumstances. 5. A circumstances which is gravely evil destroys the entire goodness of an objectively good act. 6. A circumstances which is evil, but not gravely so, does not entirely destroy the goodness of an objectively good act.